Switch to: Citations

References in:

Agency and the open question argument

Ethics 113 (3):490-527 (2003)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person.Harry G. Frankfurt - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (1):5-20.
    It is my view that one essential difference between persons and other creatures is to be found in the structure of a person's will. Besides wanting and choosing and being moved to do this or that, men may also want to have certain desires and motives. They are capable of wanting to be different, in their preferences and purposes, from what they are. Many animals appear to have the capacity for what I shall call "first-order desires" or "desires of the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1459 citations  
  • What Happens When Someone Acts?J. David Velleman - 1992 - Mind 101 (403):461-481.
    What happens when someone acts? A familiar answer goes like this. There is something that the agent wants, and there is an action that he believes conducive to its attainment. His desire for the end, and his belief in the action as a means, justify taking the action, and they jointly cause an intention to take it, which in turn causes the corresponding movements of the agent's body. I think that the standard story is flawed in several respects. The flaw (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   197 citations  
  • Certain Features in Moore's Ethical Doctrines.C. D. Broad - 1942 - In Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The philosophy of G. E. Moore. New York,: Tudor Pub. Co..
  • Kantian constructivism in moral theory.John Rawls - 1980 - Journal of Philosophy 77 (9):515-572.
  • The Possibility of Practical Reason.David Velleman - 2000 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by J. David Velleman.
    Suppose that we want to frame a conception of reasons that isn't relativized to the inclinations of particular agents. That is, we want to identify particular things that count as reasons for acting simpliciter and not merely as reasons for some agents rather than others, depending on their inclinations. One way to frame such a conception is to name some features that an action can have and to say that they count as reasons for someone whether or not he is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   285 citations  
  • The Possibility of Practical Reason.J. David Velleman - 1996 - Ethics 106 (4):694-726.
  • Brandt's definition of "good".J. David Velleman - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (3):353-371.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Xii Responsibility for Self.Charles Taylor - 1976 - In Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (ed.), Identities of Persons. University of California Press. pp. 281-300.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Facts and Values: Studies in Ethical Analysis.F. E. Sparshott & Charles L. Stevenson - 1965 - Philosophical Review 74 (4):530.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Persons, perspectives, and full information accounts of the good.Connie S. Rosati - 1995 - Ethics 105 (2):296-325.
  • Naturalism, normativity, and the open question argument.Connie S. Rosati - 1995 - Noûs 29 (1):46-70.
  • Internalism and the good for a person.Connie S. Rosati - 1996 - Ethics 106 (2):297-326.
    Proponents of numerous recent theories of a person's good hold that a plausible account of the good for a person must satisfy existence internalism. Yet little direct defense has been given for this position. I argue that the principal intuition behind internalism supports a stronger version of the thesis than it might appear--one that effects a "double link" to motivation. I then identify and develop the main arguments that have been or might be given in support of internalism about a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Moral realism.Peter Railton - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (2):163-207.
  • Naturalism and Prescriptivity.Peter Railton - 1989 - Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (1):151.
    Statements about a person's good slip into and out of our ordinary discourse about the world with nary a ripple. Such statements are objects of belief and assertion, they obey the rules of logic, and they are often defended by evidence and argument. They even participate in common-sense explanations, as when we say of some person that he has been less subject to wild swings of enthusiasm and disappointment now that, with experience, he has gained a clearer idea of what (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Facts and Values.Peter Railton - 1986 - Philosophical Topics 14 (2):5-31.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   208 citations  
  • Geach on `good'.Charles R. Pigden - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (159):129-154.
    In his celebrated 'Good and Evil' (l956) Professor Geach argues as against the non-naturalists that ‘good’ is attributive and that the predicative 'good', as used by Moore, is senseless.. 'Good' when properly used is attributive. 'There is no such thing as being just good or bad, [that is, no predicative 'good'] there is only being a good or bad so and so'. On the other hand, Geach insists, as against non-cognitivists, that good-judgments are entirely 'descriptive'. By a consideration of what (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Self-interest and the Concept of Self-sacrifice.Mark Carl Overvold - 1980 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (1):105-118.
    Owing to a genral dissatisfaction with hedonistic theories of value, a number of recent discussions have sought to identify an agent's selfinterest, individual utility, or personal welfare with what the agent most wants to do, all things considered. Two features of these accounts merit special attention for the argument in this paper. First, on such accounts any desire or aversion which persists in the face of complete information is logically relevant to the determination of an agent's self interest. This includes (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Freedom and desire.Wright Neely - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (September):32-54.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The Possibility of Practical Reason.David Velleman J. - 1996 - Ethics 106 (4):694-726.
  • Epistemic freedom.J. David Velleman - 1989 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (1):73-97.
    Epistemic freedom is the freedom to affirm anyone of several incompatible propositions without risk of being wrong. We sometimes have this freedom, strange as it seems, and our having it sheds some light on the topic of free will and determinism. This paper sketches a potential explanation for our feeling of freedom. The freedom that I postulate is not causal but epistemic (in a sense that I shall define), and the result is that it is quite compatible with determinism. I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Good and Evil.Peter Geach - 1956 - Analysis 17 (2):33 - 42.
  • The good life: A defense of attitudinal hedonism.Fred Feldman - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (3):604-628.
    The students and colleagues of Roderick Chisholm admired and respected Chisholm. Many were filled not only with admiration, but with affection and gratitude for Chisholm throughout the time we knew him. Even now that he is dead, we continue to wish him well. Under the circumstances, many of us probably think that that wish amounts to no more than this: we hope that things went well for him when he lived; we hope that he had a good life.
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • The Good Life: A Defense of Attitudinal Hedonism.Fred Feldman - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (3):604-628.
    What makes a life go well for the one who lives it? Hedonists hold that pleasure enhances the value of a life; pain diminishes it. Hedonism has been subjected to a number of objections. Some are (a) based on the claim that hedonism is a form of “mental statism”. Others are (b) based on the claim that some pleasures are base or degrading. Yet others are (c) based on the claim that when a bad person enjoys a pleasure, his receipt (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Dispositional ethical realism.Bruce W. Brower - 1993 - Ethics 103 (2):221-249.
  • Autonomy, Reason, and Desire.Robert Audi - 1991 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 72 (4):247-271.