Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Explanation and Understanding. Von Wright - 1977 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 82 (1):108-120.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  • The poverty of historicism.Karl Raimund Popper - 1957 - London,: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
    Hailed on publication in 1957 as "probably the only book published this year that will outlive the century," this is a brilliant of the idea that there are ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   262 citations  
  • The Poverty of Historicism.Karl R. Popper - 1957 - London,: Routledge.
    On its publication in 1957, _The Poverty of Historicism_ was hailed by Arthur Koestler as 'probably the only book published this year which will outlive the century.' A devastating criticism of fixed and predictable laws in history, Popper dedicated the book to all those 'who fell victim to the fascist and communist belief in Inexorable Laws of Historical Destiny.' Short and beautifully written, it has inspired generations of readers, intellectuals and policy makers. One of the most important books on the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  • Laws and explanation in history.William H. Dray - 1957 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
  • Meaning in history.Wilhelm Dilthey - 1961 - London,: Allen & Unwin.
  • The Structure of Social Action [1937].Talcott Parsons - 1937 - Free Press.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations  
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Ian Hacking.
  • The later philosophy of R.G. Collingwood.Alan Donagan - 1962 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • The philosophy of the social sciences.Alan Ryan - 1970 - London,: Macmillan.
    Applies a philosophical analysis of the natural sciences to the social sciences.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Philosophy Of Mind.Alan R. White - 1967 - Westport, Conn.: Random House.
  • Action.Donald George Brown - 1968 - London,: Allen & Unwin.
    An essay in descriptive metaphysics, this book offers a sketch of the concept of action embodied in pretheoretical, folk ways of speaking. It focuses on the points of view of the agent and spectator in the kind of action in which the question of what to do can arise for the agent. It explores the relations among such action, inanimate action, and the inanimate action of parts of the body on external objects, finding in them analogous roles for the notion (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Mind.C. J. Bryant - 1967 - Philosophical Quarterly 17 (69):365-366.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Explanation Of Behaviour.C. Taylor - 1964 - Humanities Press.
  • The Philosophy of the Social Sciences.Robert C. Stalnaker - 1973 - Philosophical Review 82 (1):126.
  • Rationality in Action: A Symposium.Barry Smith - 2001 - Philosophical Explorations 4 (2):66-94.
    Searle’s tool for understanding culture, law and society is the opposition between brute reality and institutional reality, or in other words between: observer-independent features of the world, such as force, mass and gravitational attraction, and observer-relative features of the world, such as money, property, marriage and government. The question posed here is: under which of these two headings do moral concepts fall? This is an important question because there are moral facts – for example pertaining to guilt and responsibility – (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   242 citations  
  • Rationality in Action.John R. Searle - 2001 - MIT Press.
    The study of rationality and practical reason, or rationality in action, has been central to Western intellectual culture. In this invigorating book, John Searle lays out six claims of what he calls the Classical Model of rationality and shows why they are false. He then presents an alternative theory of the role of rationality in thought and action. A central point of Searle's theory is that only irrational actions are directly caused by beliefs and desires—for example, the actions of a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   238 citations  
  • Reasons and purposes: human rationality and the teleological explanation of action.G. F. Schueler - 2003 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    People act for reasons. That is how we understand ourselves. But what is it to act for a reason? This is what Fred Schueler investigates. He rejects the dominant view that the beliefs and desires that constitute our reasons for acting simply cause us to act as we do, and argues instead for a view centred on practical deliberation--our ability to evaluate the reasons we accept. Schueler's account of 'reasons explanations' emphasizes the relation between reasons and purposes, and the fact (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • A deductive-nomological model of probabilistic explanation.Peter Railton - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (2):206-226.
    It has been the dominant view that probabilistic explanations of particular facts must be inductive in character. I argue here that this view is mistaken, and that the aim of probabilistic explanation is not to demonstrate that the explanandum fact was nomically expectable, but to give an account of the chance mechanism(s) responsible for it. To this end, a deductive-nomological model of probabilistic explanation is developed and defended. Such a model has application only when the probabilities occurring in covering laws (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • V.—Are Historical Events Unique?P. H. Nowell-Smith - 1957 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57 (1):107-160.
  • The possibility of altruism.Thomas Nagel - 1970 - Oxford,: Clarendon P..
    Just as there are rational requirements on thought, there are rational requirements on action. This book defends a conception of ethics, and a related conception of human nature, according to which altruism is included among the basic rational requirements on desire and action. Altruism itself depends on the recognition of the reality of other persons, and on the equivalent capacity to regard oneself as merely one individual among many.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   521 citations  
  • Determinism in history.Ernest Nagel - 1959 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 20 (3):291-317.
  • The Idea of History.Arthur E. Murphy - 1947 - Philosophical Review 56 (5):587.
  • Theory of Action.Charles Marks & Lawrence H. Davis - 1980 - Philosophical Review 89 (4):634.
  • The conceivability of mechanism.Norman Malcolm - 1968 - Philosophical Review 77 (January):45-72.
  • Explanation and Human Action.A. R. Louch - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (3):81-84.
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.David Bohm - 1964 - Philosophical Quarterly 14 (57):377-379.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1157 citations  
  • The function of general laws in history.Carl Gustav Hempel - 1942 - Journal of Philosophy 39 (2):35-48.
    The classic logical positivist account of historical explanation, putting forward what is variously called the "regularity interpretation" (#Gardiner, The Nature of Historical Explanation), the "covering law model" (#Dray, Laws and Explanation in History), or the "deductive model" (Michael #Scriven, "Truisms as Grounds for Historical Explanations"). See also #Danto, Narration and Knowledge, for further criticisms of the model. Hempel formalizes historical explanation as involving (a) statements of determining (initial and boundary) conditions for the event to be explained, and (b) statements of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   223 citations  
  • The compatibility of mechanism and purpose.Alvin I. Goldman - 1969 - Philosophical Review 78 (October):468-82.
    Norman Malcolm's recent argument against the conceivability of mechanism rests on the claim that purposive explanations of behavior – that is, explanations of behavior in terms of desires or intentions – are incompatible with neurophysiological explanations of behavior. I admit that intentions or desires can be causes of behavior only if they are necessary for behavior, and, generally, that events can be causes only if they are necessary for their effects (except in cases of over-determination). What I wish to deny (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The Freedom of the Will.Antony Flew - 1971 - Philosophical Quarterly 21 (85):378.
    The author, who pioneered this argument in 1961, here places it in the context of traditional discussions of the problem, and answers various criticisms that have been made.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Explanation, mechanism, and teleology.C. J. Ducasse - 1925 - Journal of Philosophy 22 (6):150-155.
  • Explaining Behaviour: Reasons in a World of Causes.Andy Clark - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (158):95-102.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   535 citations  
  • Review of William H. Dray: Laws and explanation in history[REVIEW]Arthur C. Danto - 1958 - Ethics 68 (4):297-299.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • theory of action.Lawrence Howard Davis - 1979 - Prentice-Hall.
  • Actions, Reasons, and Causes.Donald Davidson - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (23):685.
    What is the relation between a reason and an action when the reason explains the action by giving the agent's reason for doing what he did? We may call such explanations rationalizations, and say that the reason rationalizes the action. In this paper I want to defend the ancient - and common-sense - position that rationalization is a species of ordinary causal explanation. The defense no doubt requires some redeployment, but not more or less complete abandonment of the position, as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1245 citations  
  • Précis of Practical Reality.Jonathan Dancy - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (2):423-428.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   319 citations  
  • Practical Reality.Jonathan Dancy - 2000 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Practical Reality is a lucid original study of the relation between the reasons why we do things and the reasons why we should. Jonathan Dancy maintains that current philosophical orthodoxy bowdlerizes this relation, making it impossible to understand how anyone can act for a good reason. By giving a fresh account of values and reasons, he finds a place for normativity in philosophy of mind and action, and strengthens the connection between these areas and ethics.
  • Action.Arthur C. Danto - 1970 - Philosophical Review 79 (4):582.
  • History. Its Theory and Practice.Benedetto Croce - 1922 - Philosophical Review 31 (6):610-617.
  • The psychological reality of reasons.Arthur W. Collins - 1997 - Ratio 10 (2):108–123.
    Action explanations like ‘I am heading to the ferry because the bridge is closed,’ are supposed to require restatement: ‘I am... because I believe the bridge is closed,’ because (i) the objective claim may be false though the intended explanation is correct, and (ii) because objective circumstances have to be cognitively mediated if they are to bear on action. This supposition is rejected here. Restatements cannot withdraw the objective claim without withdrawing the explanation. In the context of reason‐giving, belief statements (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The idea of history.Robin George Collingwood - 1961 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by der Dussen & J. W..
    The Idea of History is the best-known book of the great Oxford philosopher, historian, and archaeologist R.G. Collingwood. It was originally published posthumously in 1946, having been mainly reconstructed from Collingwood's manuscripts, many of which are now lost. For this revised edition, Collingwood's most important lectures on the philosophy of history are published here for the first time. These texts have been prepared by Jan van der Dussen from manuscripts that have only recently become available. The lectures contain Collingwood's first (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Explanation. [REVIEW]David Braybrooke & Stephan Korner - 1977 - Philosophical Quarterly 27 (106):74.
  • The Freedom of the Will.J. R. Lucas - 1970 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    The author, who pioneered this argument in 1961, here places it in the context of traditional discussions of the problem, and answers various criticisms that have been made.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The philosophy of history.Patrick L. Gardiner (ed.) - 1974 - New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Things that happen because they should: a teleological approach to action.Rowland Stout - 1996 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Rowland Stout presents a new philosophical account of human action which is radically and controversially different from all rival theories. He argues that intentional actions are unique among natural phenomena in that they happen because they should happen, and that they are to be explained in terms of objective facts rather than beliefs and intentions.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Doing things for reasons.Rüdiger Bittner - 2001 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    What exactly are the reasons we do things, and how are they related to the resulting actions? Bittner explores this question and proposes an answer: a reason is a response to that state of affairs. Elegantly written, this work is a substantial contribution to the fields of rationality, ethics, and action theory.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The View from Nowhere.Thomas Nagel - 1986 - Behaviorism 15 (1):73-82.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   690 citations  
  • The Idea of History.R. G. Collingwood - 1946 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):252-253.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  • Doing Things for Reasons.Rudolph Bittner - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (210):144-147.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Practical Reality.Jonathan Dancy - 2000 - Philosophy 78 (305):414-425.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   442 citations  
  • Agency and causal explanation.Jennifer Hornsby - 1993 - In John Heil & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation. Oxford University Press.
    I. There are two points of view: ___ From the personal point of view, an action is a person's doing something for a reason, and her doing it is found intelligible when we know the reason that led her to it. ___ From the impersonal point of view, an action would be a link in a causal chain that could be viewed without paying any attention to people, the links being understood by reference to the world's causal workings.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations