Switch to: Citations

References in:

'Identity' without Identity

Mind 121 (481):67-95 (2012)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Identity and necessity.Saul A. Kripke - 1971 - In Milton Karl Munitz (ed.), Identity and individuation. New York,: New York University Press. pp. 135-164.
    are synthetic a priori judgements possible?" In both cases, i~thas usually been t'aken for granted in fife one case by Kant that synthetic a priori judgements were possible, and in the other case in contemporary,'d-". philosophical literature that contingent statements of identity are ppss. ible. I do not intend to deal with the Kantian question except to mention:ssj~".
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   437 citations  
  • Conjunctions, Disjunctions and Lewisian Semantics for Counterfactuals.Alexander R. Pruss - 2007 - Synthese 156 (1):33-52.
    Consider the reasonable axioms of subjunctive conditionals if p → q1 and p → q2 at some world, then p → at that world, and if p1 → q and p2 → q at some world, then → q at that world, where p → q is the subjunctive conditional. I show that a Lewis-style semantics for subjunctive conditionals satisfies these axioms if and only if one makes a certain technical assumption about the closeness relation, an assumption that is probably (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • How things might have been: individuals, kinds, and essential properties.Penelope Mackie - 2006 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    A novel treatment of an issue central to much current work in metaphysics: the distinction between the essential and accidental properties of individuals. Mackie challenges widely held views, and arrives at what she calls "minimalist essentialism," an unorthodox theory according to which ordinary individuals have relatively few interesting essential properties. Mackie's clear and accessible discussions of issues surrounding necessity and essentialism mean that the book will appeal as much to graduate students as it will to seasoned metaphysicians.
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
    In the course of the discussion, Professor Quine pinpoints the difficulties involved in translation, brings to light the anomalies and conflicts implicit in our ...
  • The Possible and the actual: readings in the metaphysics of modality.Michael J. Loux (ed.) - 1979 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    Preface In these days, an anthology on the topic of possible worlds hardly needs justification. No issue has given rise to as much literature in the past ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Strict Identity with No Overlap.Achille C. Varzi - 2006 - Studia Logica 82 (3):371-378.
    It is common lore that standard, Kripke-style semantics for quantified modal logic is incompatible with the view that no individual may belong to more than one possible world, a view that seems to require a counterpart-theoretic semantics instead. Strictly speaking, however, this thought is wrong-headed. This note explains why.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Models for Counterparts.Alessandro Torza - 2011 - Axiomathes 21 (4):553-579.
    Lewis proposed to test the validity of a modal thesis by checking whether its possible-world translation is a theorem of counterpart theory. However, that criterion fails to validate many standard modal laws, thus raising doubts about the logical adequacy of the Lewisian framework. The present paper considers systems of counterpart theory of increasing strength and shows how each can be motivated by exhibiting a suitable intended model. In particular, perfect counterpart theory validates all the desired modal laws and therefore provides (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Counterparts and identity.Robert Stalnaker - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 11 (1):121--40.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Counterparts and Identity.Robert Stalnaker - 1986 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 11 (1):121-140.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Trans-World Identification and Stipulation.Nathan Salmon - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 84 (2-3):203 - 223.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • In defense of linguistic ersatzism.Tony Roy - 1995 - Philosophical Studies 80 (3):217 - 242.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Word and Object.Henry W. Johnstone - 1961 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 22 (1):115-116.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   300 citations  
  • Identify and Individuation. [REVIEW]W. V. Quine - 1972 - Journal of Philosophy 69 (16):488-497.
  • It simply does not add up: Trouble with overall similarity.Michael Morreau - 2010 - Journal of Philosophy 107 (9):469-490.
    Comparative overall similarity lies at the basis of a lot of recent metaphysics and epistemology. It is a poor foundation. Overall similarity is supposed to be an aggregate of similarities and differences in various respects. But there is no good way of combining them all.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • How Things Might Have Been: Individuals, Kinds, and Essential Properties. [REVIEW]André Gallois - 2007 - Philosophical Quarterly 57 (227):297-300.
  • Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic.David Lewis - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (5):113-126.
  • Counterfactual Dependence and Time’s Arrow.David Lewis - 1979 - Noûs 13 (4):455-476.
  • A New Problem of Descriptive Power.Stephan Leuenberger - 2006 - Journal of Philosophy 103 (3):145-159.
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • How to Russell a Frege-Church.David Kaplan - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (19):716-729.
  • Quick completeness proofs for some logics of conditionals.John P. Burgess - 1981 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 22 (1):76-84.
  • Hintikka's Revolution: The Priciples of Mathematics Revisited1. [REVIEW]R. Cook - 1998 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (2):309-316.
  • The principles of mathematics revisited.Jaakko Hintikka - 1996 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book, written by one of philosophy's pre-eminent logicians, argues that many of the basic assumptions common to logic, philosophy of mathematics and metaphysics are in need of change. It is therefore a book of critical importance to logical theory. Jaakko Hintikka proposes a new basic first-order logic and uses it to explore the foundations of mathematics. This new logic enables logicians to express on the first-order level such concepts as equicardinality, infinity, and truth in the same language. The famous (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • The fallacies of the new theory of reference.Jaakko Hintikka & Gabriel Sandu - 1995 - Synthese 104 (2):245 - 283.
    The so-called New Theory of Reference (Marcus, Kripke etc.) is inspired by the insight that in modal and intensional contexts quantifiers presuppose nondescriptive unanalyzable identity criteria which do not reduce to any descriptive conditions. From this valid insight the New Theorists fallaciously move to the idea that free singular terms can exhibit a built-in direct reference and that there is even a special class of singular terms (proper names) necessarily exhibiting direct reference. This fallacious move has been encouraged by a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Counterpart-theoretic semantics for modal logic.Allen Hazen - 1979 - Journal of Philosophy 76 (6):319-338.
  • Expressive completeness in modal language.Allen Hazen - 1976 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 5 (1):25--46.
    The logics of the modal operators and of the quantifiers show striking analogies. The analogies are so extensive that, when a special class of entities (possible worlds) is postulated, natural and non-arbitrary translation procedures can be defined from the language with the modal operators into a purely quantificational one, under which the necessity and possibility operators translate into universal and existential quantifiers. In view of this I would be willing to classify the modal operators as ‘disguised’ quantifiers, and I think (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Adequacy Conditions for Counterpart Theory.M. J. Cresswell - 2004 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (1):28-41.
    David Lewis's modal realism claims that nothing can exist in more than one world or time, and that statements about how something would have been are to be analysed in terms of its counterpart. I first explain why the counterpart relation depends on de re modal statements in an intensional language, so that intuitive properties of similarity relations cannot be used to show that the counterpart relation is not an equivalence relation. I then look at test sentences in (the intensional) (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Contingent identity.Allan Gibbard - 1975 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 4 (2):187-222.
    Identities formed with proper names may be contingent. this claim is made first through an example. the paper then develops a theory of the semantics of concrete things, with contingent identity as a consequence. this general theory lets concrete things be made up canonically from fundamental physical entities. it includes theories of proper names, variables, cross-world identity with respect to a sortal, and modal and dispositional properties. the theory, it is argued, is coherent and superior to its rivals, in that (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   285 citations  
  • The Metaphysics of Modality.Mark A. Brown - 1990 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (3):615-619.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The metaphysics of modality.Graeme Forbes - 1985 - Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    Analytic philosophy has recently demonstrated a revived interest in metaphysical problems about possibility and necessity. Graeme Forbes here provides a careful description of the logical background of recent work in this area for those who may be unfamiliar with it, moving on to d discuss the distinction between modality de re and modality de dicto and the ontological commitments of possible worlds semantics. In addition, Forbes offers a unified theory of the essential properties of sets, organisms, artefacts, substances, and events, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   144 citations  
  • Book Reviews. [REVIEW]Melvin Fitting & Richard Mendelsohn - 1998 - Studia Logica 68 (2):287-300.
  • Dear haecceitism.Delia Graff Fara - 2009 - Erkenntnis 70 (3):285–297.
    If a counterpart theorist’s understanding of the counterpart relation precludes haecceitist differences between possible worlds, as David Lewis’s does, how can he admit haecceitist possibilities, as Lewis wants to? Lewis (Philosophical Review 3–32, 1983; On the Plurality of Worlds, 1986) devised what he called a ‘cheap substitute for haecceitism,’ which would allow for haecceitist possibilities while preserving the counterpart relation as a purely qualitative one. The solution involved lifting an earlier (Journal of Philosophy 65(5):113–126, 1968; 68(7):203–211, 1971) ban on there (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Counterparts and Actuality.Michael Fara & Timothy Williamson - 2005 - Mind 114 (453):1-30.
    Many philosophers, following David Lewis, believe that we should look to counterpart theory, not quantified modal logic, as a means of understanding modal discourse. We argue that this is a mistake. Significant parts of modal discourse involve either implicit or explicit reference to what is actually the case, raising the question of how talk about actuality is to be represented counterpart-theoretically. By considering possible modifications of Lewis's counterpart theory, including actual modifications due to Graeme Forbes and Murali Ramachandran, we argue (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Semantics of natural language.Donald Davidson & Gilbert Harman - 1970 - Synthese 22 (1-2):1-2.
  • Identity through possible worlds: Some questions.Roderick M. Chisholm - 1967 - Noûs 1 (1):1-8.
  • Reducing reductionism: on a putative proof for Extreme Haecceitism.Troy Thomas Catterson - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 140 (2):149-159.
    Nathan Salmon, in his paper Trans-World Identification and Stipulation (1996) purports to give a proof for the claim that facts concerning trans-world identity cannot be conceptually reduced to general facts. He calls this claim ‘Extreme Haecceitism.’ I argue that his proof is fallacious. However, I also contend that the analysis and ultimate rejection of his proof clarifies the fundamental issues that are at stake in the debate between the reductionist and haecceitist solutions to the problem of trans-world identity. These issues (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Plurality of Worlds. [REVIEW]D. B. - 1928 - Modern Schoolman 4 (8):138-139.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Two modal–isms: Fictionalism and ersatzism.Berit Brogaard - 2006 - Philosophical Perspectives 20 (1):77–94.
    It is sometimes said that no living philosopher is a genuine modal realist. This is no doubt an exaggeration. But at least this much is true: while we all partake of possible world talk when philosophizing, most of us regard this talk as incurring no commitment to a plurality of concrete worlds.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Reducing possible worlds to language.Phillip Bricker - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 52 (3):331 - 355.
    The most commonly heard proposals for reducing possible worlds to language succumb to a simple cardinality argument: it can be shown that there are more possible worlds than there are linguistic entities provided by the proposal. In this paper, I show how the standard proposals can be generalized in a natural way so as to make better use of the resources available to them, and thereby circumvent the cardinality argument. Once it is seen just what the limitations are on these (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Arthur Prior and Hybrid Logic.Patrick Blackburn - 2006 - Synthese 150 (3):329-372.
    Contemporary hybrid logic is based on the idea of using formulas as terms, an idea invented and explored by Arthur Prior in the mid-1960s. But Prior’s own work on hybrid logic remains largely undiscussed. This is unfortunate, since hybridisation played a role that was both central to and problematic for his philosophical views on tense. In this paper I introduce hybrid logic from a contemporary perspective, and then examine the role it played in Prior’s work.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Impossible worlds and propositions: Against the parity thesis.Francesco Berto - 2010 - Philosophical Quarterly 60 (240):471-486.
    Accounts of propositions as sets of possible worlds have been criticized for conflating distinct impossible propositions. In response to this problem, some have proposed to introduce impossible worlds to represent distinct impossibilities, endorsing the thesis that impossible worlds must be of the same kind; this has been called the parity thesis. I show that this thesis faces problems, and propose a hybrid account which rejects it: possible worlds are taken as concrete Lewisian worlds, and impossibilities are represented as set-theoretic constructions (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Naming and necessity.J. E. J. Altham - 1981 - Philosophical Books 22 (1):36-37.
  • The Principles of Mathematics Revisited.Jaakko Hintikka - 1996 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book, written by one of philosophy's pre-eminent logicians, argues that many of the basic assumptions common to logic, philosophy of mathematics and metaphysics are in need of change. It is therefore a book of critical importance to logical theory. Jaakko Hintikka proposes a new basic first-order logic and uses it to explore the foundations of mathematics. This new logic enables logicians to express on the first-order level such concepts as equicardinality, infinity, and truth in the same language. The famous (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Philosophical Perspectives, Metaphysics.John Hawthorne (ed.) - 2006 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    _Philosophical Perspectives Volume 20, Metaphysics_, contains over 15 articles from leading philosophers of Metaphysics. Brings together original essays by some of the foremost thinkers in the field, among them Theodore Sider, Peter Van Inwagen and J.R.G. Williams Explores such topics as infinity and causation, the nature and epistemology of modality, and the persistence of objects through relativistic time.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol. Iii.D. Gabbay & F. Guenther (eds.) - 1986 - D. Reidel Publishing Co..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Most Counterfactuals Are False.Alan Hajek - 2014
  • The ersatz pluriverse.Theodore Sider - 2002 - Journal of Philosophy 99 (6):279-315.
    While many are impressed with the utility of possible worlds in linguistics and philosophy, few can accept the modal realism of David Lewis, who regards possible worlds as sui generis entities of a kind with the concrete world we inhabit.1 Not all uses of possible worlds require exotic ontology. Consider, for instance, the use of Kripke models to establish formal results in modal logic. These models contain sets often regarded for heuristic reasons as sets of “possible worlds”. But the “worlds” (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):278-279.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2801 citations  
  • Identity and Individuation.Milton K. Munitz - 1974 - Synthese 28 (3):553-559.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Entities and Indices.M. J. Cresswell - 1992 - Studia Logica 51 (2):338-339.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations