Search results for 'Arvid' (try it on Scholar)

38 found
Sort by:
  1. Erlandsson Arvid (2012). Disgust Predicts Non-Consequentialistic Moral Attitudes. Educational Studies 54:133-144.score: 30.0
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  2. Lundervold Arvid (2011). White Matter Integrity Changes in Healthy Aging - a Longitudinal Multimodal Magnetic Resonans Imaging Study. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 5.score: 30.0
  3. J. W. Pirie (1938). Arvid G. Elg: In Faustum Reiensetn Studia. Pp. xiv + 156. Uppsala: Almqvist och Wiksell, 1937. Paper. The Classical Review 52 (02):86-87.score: 9.0
    No categories
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  4. George P. Klubertanz (1965). "Collected Papers, Volume 2: Studies in Social Theory," by Alfred Schutz, Ed. Arvid Brodersen. The Modern Schoolman 42 (4):422-423.score: 9.0
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  5. Gunnar Björnsson & Arvid Båve (2007). Meaning as a Normative Concept. Theoria 73 (3):190-206.score: 6.0
    IN LATE SPRING 2007, professor Allan Gibbard gave the Hägerström Lectures at Uppsala University, Sweden, under the title of “Meaning as a Normative Concept”. He met up with Gunnar Björnsson and Arvid Båve to talk about the views he develops and defends in the lectures.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  6. Arvid Båve (2009). A Deflationary Theory of Reference. Synthese 169 (1):51 - 73.score: 3.0
    The article first rehearses three deflationary theories of reference, (1) disquotationalism, (2) propositionalism (Horwich), and (3) the anaphoric theory (Brandom), and raises a number of objections against them. It turns out that each corresponds to a closely related theory of truth, and that these are subject to analogous criticisms to a surprisingly high extent. I then present a theory of my own, according to which the schema “That S(t) is about t” and the biconditional “S refers to x iff S (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  7. Arvid Båve (2008). A Pragmatic Defense of Millianism. Philosophical Studies 138 (2):271 - 289.score: 3.0
    A new kind of defense of the Millian theory of names is given, which explains intuitive counter-examples as depending on pragmatic effects of the relevant sentences, by direct application of Grice’s and Sperber and Wilson’s Relevance Theory and uncontroversial assumptions. I begin by arguing that synonyms are always intersubstitutable, despite Mates’ considerations, and then apply the method to names. Then, a fairly large sample of cases concerning names are dealt with in related ways. It is argued that the method, as (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  8. Arvid Båve (2010). Deflationism and the Primary Truth Bearer. Synthese 173 (3):281 - 297.score: 3.0
    The paper discusses what kind of truth bearer, or truth-ascription, a deflationist should take as primary. I first present number of arguments against a sententialist view. I then present a deflationary theory which takes propositions as primary, and try to show that it deals neatly with a wide range of linguistic data. Next, I consider both the view that there is no primary truth bearer, and the most common account of sentence truth given by deflationists who take propositions as primary, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  9. Arvid Båve (2011). How To Precisify Quantifiers. Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (1):103-111.score: 3.0
    I here argue that Ted Sider's indeterminacy argument against vagueness in quantifiers fails. Sider claims that vagueness entails precisifications, but holds that precisifications of quantifiers cannot be coherently described: they will either deliver the wrong logical form to quantified sentences, or involve a presupposition that contradicts the claim that the quantifier is vague. Assuming (as does Sider) that the “connectedness” of objects can be precisely defined, I present a counter-example to Sider's contention, consisting of a partial, implicit definition of the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  10. Arvid Båve (2013). Formulating Deflationism. Synthese 190 (15):3287-3305.score: 3.0
    I here argue for a particular formulation of truth-deflationism, namely, the propositionally quantified formula, (Q) “For all p, ${\langle \text{p}\rangle}$ is true iff p”. The main argument consists of an enumeration of the other (five) possible formulations and criticisms thereof. Notably, Horwich’s Minimal Theory is found objectionable in that it cannot be accepted by finite beings. Other formulations err in not providing non-questionbegging, sufficiently direct derivations of the T-schema instances. I end by defending (Q) against various objections. In particular, I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  11. Arvid Båve (2009). Why is a Truth-Predicate Like a Pronoun? Philosophical Studies 145 (2):297 - 310.score: 3.0
    I begin with an exposition of the two main variants of the Prosentential Theory of Truth (PT), those of Dorothy Grover et al. and Robert Brandom. Three main types of criticisms are then put forward: (1) material criticisms to the effect that (PT) does not adequately explain the linguistic data, (2) an objection to the effect that no variant of (PT) gives a properly unified account of the various occurrences of "true" in English, and, most importantly, (3) a charge that (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  12. Arvid Båve (2006). Deflationism: A Use-Theoretic Analysis of the Truth-Predicate. Dissertation, Stockholm Universityscore: 3.0
    I here develop a specific version of the deflationary theory of truth. I adopt a terminology on which deflationism holds that an exhaustive account of truth is given by the equivalence between truth-ascriptions and de-nominalised (or disquoted) sentences. An adequate truth-theory, it is argued, must be finite, non-circular, and give a unified account of all occurrences of “true”. I also argue that it must descriptively capture the ordinary meaning of “true”, which is plausibly taken to be unambiguous. Ch. 2 is (...)
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  13. Arvid Båve (2012). On Using Inconsistent Expressions. Erkenntnis 77 (1):133-148.score: 3.0
    The paper discusses the Inconsistency Theory of Truth (IT), the view that “true” is inconsistent in the sense that its meaning-constitutive principles include all instances of the truth-schema (T). It argues that (IT) entails that anyone using “true” in its ordinary sense is committed to all the (T)-instances and that any theory in which “true” is used in that sense entails the (T)-instances (which, given classical logic, entail contradictions). More specifically, I argue that theorists are committed to the meaning-constitutive principles (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  14. Arvid Båve (2013). Compositional Semantics for Expressivists. Philosophical Quarterly 63 (253):633-659.score: 3.0
    I here propose a hitherto unnoticed possibility of solving embedding problems for noncognitivist expressivists in metaethics by appeal to Conceptual Role Semantics. I show that claims from the latter as to what constitutes various concepts can be used to define functions from states expressed by atomic sentences to states expressed by complex sentences, thereby allowing an expressivist semantics that satisfies a rather strict compositionality constraint (as well as a further, substantial explanatory constraint). The proposal can be coupled with several different (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  15. Arvid W. Adell (1987). The Art of "On the Other Hand". Teaching Philosophy 10 (2):103-109.score: 3.0
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  16. Arvid Guterstam & H. Henrik Ehrsson (2012). Disowning One's Seen Real Body During an Out-of-Body Illusion. Consciousness and Cognition 21 (2):1037-1042.score: 3.0
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  17. Eva G. Krumhuber, Arvid Kappas & Antony S. R. Manstead (2013). Effects of Dynamic Aspects of Facial Expressions: A Review. Emotion Review 5 (1):41-46.score: 3.0
    A key feature of facial behavior is its dynamic quality. However, most previous research has been limited to the use of static images of prototypical expressive patterns. This article explores the role of facial dynamics in the perception of emotions, reviewing relevant empirical evidence demonstrating that dynamic information improves coherence in the identification of affect (particularly for degraded and subtle stimuli), leads to higher emotion judgments (i.e., intensity and arousal), and helps to differentiate between genuine and fake expressions. The findings (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  18. Arvid W. Adell (1987). The Art Of. Teaching Philosophy 10 (2):103-109.score: 3.0
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  19. Florian Waszak Arvid Herwig (2012). Action-Effect Bindings and Ideomotor Learning in Intention- and Stimulus-Based Actions. Frontiers in Psychology 3.score: 3.0
    According to ideomotor theory, action-effect associations are crucial for voluntary action control. Recently, a number of studies started to investigate the conditions that mediate the acquisition and application of action-effect associations by comparing actions carried out in response to exogenous stimuli (stimulus-based) with actions selected endogenously (intention-based). There is evidence that the acquisition and/or application of action-effect associations is boosted when acting in an intention-based action mode. For instance, bidirectional action-effect associations were diagnosed in a forced choice test phase if (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  20. Chau-Kiu Cheung & Steven Arvid Scherling (1997). Ethical Reasoning and Machiavellianism Among Business Students in Hong Kong. Teaching Business Ethics 1 (3):283-302.score: 3.0
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  21. Arvid Strand & Petter Naess (2012). What Kinds of Traffic Forecasts Are Possible? Journal of Critical Realism 11 (3):277-295.score: 3.0
    Based on metatheoretical considerations, this article discusses what kinds of traffic forecasts are possible and what kinds are impossible to make with any reasonable degree of accuracy. It will be argued on ontological and epistemological grounds that it is inherently impossible to make exact predictions about the magnitude of the ‘general’ traffic growth 20–30 years ahead, since many of the influencing factors depend on inherently unpredictable geopolitical trajectories as well as contested political decision-making. Due to the context-dependency of each particular (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  22. Arvid Carlsson & Maria Carlsson (1991). A Faulty Negative Feedback Control Underlies the Schizophrenic Syndrome? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):20-21.score: 3.0
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  23. Arvid O. I. Hoffmann, Sam F. Henry & Nikos Kalogeras (2013). Aspirations as Reference Points: An Experimental Investigation of Risk Behavior Over Time. [REVIEW] Theory and Decision 75 (2):193-210.score: 3.0
    This paper examines the importance of aspirations as reference points in a multi-period decision-making context. After stating their personal aspiration level, 172 individuals made six sequential decisions among risky prospects as part of a choice experiment. The results show that individuals make different risky-choices in a multi-period compared to a single-period setting. In particular, individuals’ aspiration level is their main reference point during the early stages of decision-making, while their starting status (wealth level at the start of the experiment) becomes (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  24. Arvid Kappas (2011). Emotion and Regulation Are One! Emotion Review 3 (1):17-25.score: 3.0
    Emotions are foremost self-regulating processes that permit rapid responses and adaptations to situations of personal concern. They have biological bases and are shaped ontogenetically via learning and experience. Many situations and events of personal concern are social in nature. Thus, social exchanges play an important role in learning about rules and norms that shape regulation processes. I argue that (a) emotions often are actively auto-regulating—the behavior implied by the emotional reaction bias to the eliciting event or situation modifies or terminates (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  25. Arvid Kappas (2011). Emotion is Not Just an Alarm Bell—It's the Whole Tootin' Fire Truck. Cognition and Emotion 25 (5):785-788.score: 3.0
  26. Stephanie A. Shields & Arvid Kappas (2006). Magda B. Arnold's Contributions to Emotions Research. Cognition and Emotion 20 (7):898-901.score: 3.0
  27. Arvid Aulin (1982). The Cybernetic Laws of Social Progress: Towards a Critical Social Philosophy and a Criticism of Marxism. Pergamon Press.score: 3.0
  28. Arvid Brodersen (1970). Some Notes on Reality-Orientation in Contemporary Societies. In. In Alfred Schutz & Maurice Alexander Natanson (eds.), Phenomenology and Social Reality. The Hague,Nijhoff. 174--184.score: 3.0
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  29. Arvid Brodersen (forthcoming). Soviet Social Science and Our Own. Social Research.score: 3.0
    No categories
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  30. Ithiel de Sola Pool, Norton E. Long, Arvid Brodersen, Arnold Brecht, Hans Neisser & Howard B. White (forthcoming). The" New Political Science" Reexamined: A Symposium. Social Research.score: 3.0
    No categories
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  31. Karl Arvid Edin (1929). The Differential Birth Rate Changes: Stockholm'upper'classes More Fertile Than The'lower'. The Eugenics Review 20 (4):258.score: 3.0
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  32. Arvid Kappas (2006). Appraisals Are Direct, Immediate, Intuitive, and Unwitting… and Some Are Reflective…. Cognition and Emotion 20 (7):952-975.score: 3.0
  33. Arvid Kappas (1999). Brief Report Don't Wait for the Monsters to Get You: A Video Game Task to Manipulate Appraisals in Real Time. Cognition and Emotion 13 (1):119-124.score: 3.0
  34. Arvid Kappas (2013). Social Regulation of Emotion: Messy Layers. Frontiers in Psychology 4.score: 3.0
    Emotions are evolved systems of intra- and interpersonal processes that are regulatory in nature, dealing mostly with issues of personal or social concern. They regulate social interaction and in extension, the social sphere. In turn, processes in the social sphere regulate emotions of individuals and groups. In other words, intrapersonal processes project in the interpersonal space, and inversely, interpersonal experiences deeply influence intrapersonal processes. Thus, I argue that the concepts of emotion generation and regulation should not be artificially separated. Similarly, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  35. Arvid J. Lukauskas & Yumiko Shimabukuro (2006). The Non-Linear Process of Institutional Change: The Bank of Japan Reform and Its Aftermath. Japanese Journal of Political Science 7 (2):127-152.score: 3.0
    In 1997, the Japanese Diet revised the Bank of Japan law thereby granting the central bank greater independence in monetary policy making. The revision was an attempt by Japan's political class to weaken the authority of the powerful Ministry of Finance over the central bank and augment its own influence. The Bank of Japan, however, gained more autonomy than politicians ever intended, leading to frequent confrontations between the government and the central bank over monetary policy. This paper explores the new (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  36. Petter Næss & Arvid Strand (2012). What Kinds of Traffic Forecasts Are Possible? Journal of Critical Realism 11 (3):277-295.score: 3.0
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  37. Wolfgang Prinz, Miriam Beisert & Arvid Herwig (eds.) (2013). Action Science: Foundations of an Emerging Discipline. The Mit Press.score: 3.0
    An emerging discipline depends on a rich and multifaceted supply of theoretical and methodological approaches. The diversity of perspectives offered in this book will serve as a guide for future explorations in action science.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  38. Carmen Weiss, Arvid Herwig & Simone Schütz-Bosbach (2011). The Self in Action Effects: Selective Attenuation of Self-Generated Sounds. Cognition 121 (2):207-218.score: 3.0
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation