113 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Bernard J. Baars [82]B. J. Baars [18]Bernard Baars [12]B. Baars [11]
  1. A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1988 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Conscious experience is one of the most difficult and thorny problems in psychological science. Its study has been neglected for many years, either because it was thought to be too difficult, or because the relevant evidence was thought to be poor. Bernard Baars suggests a way to specify empirical constraints on a theory of consciousness by contrasting well-established conscious phenomena - such as stimulus representations known to be attended, perceptual, and informative - with closely comparable unconscious ones - such as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   541 citations  
  2. The functions of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1988 - In A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  3. The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent evidence.Bernard J. Baars - 2002 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6 (1):47-52.
  4. In the theatre of consciousness: Global workspace theory, a rigorous scientific theory of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1997 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 (4):292-309.
    Can we make progress exploring consciousness? Or is it forever beyond human reach? In science we never know the ultimate outcome of the journey. We can only take whatever steps our current knowledge affords. This paper explores today's evidence from the viewpoint of Global Workspace theory. First, we ask what kind of evidence has the most direct bearing on the question. The answer given here is ‘contrastive analysis’ -- a set of paired comparisons between similar conscious and unconscious processes. This (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  5. Criteria for consciousness in humans and other mammals.Anil K. Seth, Bernard J. Baars & David B. Edelman - 2005 - Consciousness and Cognition 14 (1):119-39.
    The standard behavioral index for human consciousness is the ability to report events with accuracy. While this method is routinely used for scientific and medical applications in humans, it is not easy to generalize to other species. Brain evidence may lend itself more easily to comparative testing. Human consciousness involves widespread, relatively fast low-amplitude interactions in the thalamocortical core of the brain, driven by current tasks and conditions. These features have also been found in other mammals, which suggests that consciousness (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  6. How conscious experience and working memory interact.Bernard J. Baars & Stan Franklin - 2003 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7 (4):166-172.
  7.  42
    Global Workspace Dynamics: Cortical “Binding and Propagation” Enables Conscious Contents.Bernard J. Baars, Stan Franklin & Thomas Zoega Ramsoy - 2013 - Frontiers in Psychology 4.
  8. Global workspace theory of consciousness: Toward a cognitive neuroscience of human experience?Bernard J. Baars - 2006 - In Steven Laureys (ed.), Boundaries of Consciousness. Elsevier.
  9. Consciousness provides the nervous system with coherent, globally distributed information.B. J. Baars - 1983 - In Richard J. Davidson, Gary E. Schwartz & D. H. Shapiro (eds.), Consciousness and Self-Regulation. Plenum. pp. 101.
  10.  30
    Conscious contents provide the nervous system with coherent, global information.Bernard J. Baars - 1983 - In Richard J. Davidson, Gary E. Schwartz & D. H. Shapiro (eds.), Consciousness and Self-Regulation. Plenum. pp. 41--79.
  11. Brain, conscious experience, and the observing self.Bernard J. Baars, Thomas Zoega Ramsoy & Steven Laureys - 2003 - Trends in Neurosciences 26 (12):671-5.
    Conscious perception, like the sight of a coffee cup, seems to involve the brain identifying a stimulus. But conscious input activates more brain regions than are needed to identify coffee cups and faces. It spreads beyond sensory cortex to frontoparietal association areas, which do not serve stimulus identification as such. What is the role of those regions? Parietal cortex support the ‘first person perspective’ on the visual world, unconsciously framing the visual object stream. Some prefrontal areas select and interpret conscious (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  12. Identifying hallmarks of consciousness in non-mammalian species.David B. Edelman, Bernard J. Baars & Anil K. Seth - 2005 - Consciousness and Cognition 14 (1):169-87.
    Most early studies of consciousness have focused on human subjects. This is understandable, given that humans are capable of reporting accurately the events they experience through language or by way of other kinds of voluntary response. As researchers turn their attention to other animals, “accurate report” methodologies become increasingly difficult to apply. Alternative strategies for amassing evidence for consciousness in non-human species include searching for evolutionary homologies in anatomical substrates and measurement of physiological correlates of conscious states. In addition, creative (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  13.  27
    Biological implications of a Global Workspace theory of consciousness: Evidence, theory, and some phylogenetic speculations.Bernard J. Baars - 1987 - In G. Greenberg & E. Tobach (eds.), Cognition, Language, and Consciousness: Integrative Levels. Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 209--236.
  14.  36
    A neurobiological interpretation of global workspace theory.Bernard J. Baars & James Newman - 1994 - In Antti Revonsuo & Matti Kamppinen (eds.), Consciousness in Philosophy and Cognitive Neuroscience. Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 211--226.
  15.  64
    Does Philosophy Help or Hinder Scientific Work on Consciousness?Bernard J. Baars & Katharine McGovern - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (1):18-27.
  16. Consciousness is computational: The Lida model of global workspace theory.Bernard J. Baars & Stan Franklin - 2009 - International Journal of Machine Consciousness 1 (1):23-32.
    The currently leading cognitive theory of consciousness, Global Workspace Theory,1,2 postulates that the primary functions of consciousness include a global broadcast serving to recruit internal resources with which to deal with the current situation and to modulate several types of learning. In addition, conscious experiences present current conditions and problems to a "self" system, an executive interpreter that is identifiable with brain structures like the frontal lobes and precuneus.1Be it human, animal or artificial, an autonomous agent3 is said to be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  17. How brain reveals mind: Neural studies support the fundamental role of conscious experience.Bernard J. Baars - 2003 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 10 (9-10):100-114.
    In the last decade, careful studies of the living brain have opened the way for human consciousness to return to the heights it held before the behavioristic coup of 1913. This is illustrated by seven cases: the discovery of widespread brain activation during conscious perception; high levels of regional brain metabolism in the resting state of consciousness, dropping drastically in unconscious states; the brain correlates of inner speech; visual imagery; fringe consciousness; executive functions of the self; and volition. Other papers (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  18. Some essential differences between consciousness and attention, perception, and working memory.Bernard J. Baars - 1997 - Consciousness and Cognition 6 (2-3):363-371.
    When “divided attention” methods were discovered in the 1950s their implications for conscious experience were not widely appreciated. Yet when people process competing streams of sensory input they show both selective processesandclear contrasts between conscious and unconscious events. This paper suggests that the term “attention” may be best applied to theselection and maintenanceof conscious contents and distinguished from consciousness itself. This is consistent with common usage. The operational criteria for selective attention, defined in this way, are entirely different from those (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  19.  93
    A thoroughly empirical approach to consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1994 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 1.
    When are psychologists entitled to call a certain theoretical construct "consciousness?" Over the past few decades cognitive psychologists have reintroduced almost the entire conceptual vocabulary of common sense psychology, but now in a way that is tied explicitly to reliable empirical observations, and to compelling and increasingly adequate theoretical models. Nevertheless, until the past few years most cognitive psychologists and neuroscientists avoided dealing with consciousness. Today there is an increasing willingness to do so. But is "consciousness" different from other theoretical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  20. Neural darwinism and consciousness.Anil K. Seth & Bernard J. Baars - 2005 - Consciousness and Cognition 14 (1):140-168.
    Neural Darwinism (ND) is a large scale selectionist theory of brain development and function that has been hypothesized to relate to consciousness. According to ND, consciousness is entailed by reentrant interactions among neuronal populations in the thalamocortical system (the ‘dynamic core’). These interactions, which permit high-order discriminations among possible core states, confer selective advantages on organisms possessing them by linking current perceptual events to a past history of value-dependent learning. Here, we assess the consistency of ND with 16 widely recognized (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  21. Applying global workspace theory to the frame problem.Murray Shanahan & Bernard Baars - 2005 - Cognition 98 (2):157-176.
  22.  22
    Essential Sources in the Scientific Study of Consciousness.Bernard J. Baars & J. B. Newman (eds.) - 2001 - MIT Press.
    Current thinking and research on consciousness and the brain.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  23. Subjective experience is probably not limited to humans: The evidence from neurobiology and behavior.Bernard J. Baars - 2005 - Consciousness and Cognition 14 (1):7-21.
    In humans, conscious perception and cognition depends upon the thalamocortical complex, which supports perception, explicit cognition, memory, language, planning, and strategic control. When parts of the T-C system are damaged or stimulated, corresponding effects are found on conscious contents and state, as assessed by reliable reports. In contrast, large regions like cerebellum and basal ganglia can be damaged without affecting conscious cognition directly. Functional brain recordings also show robust activity differences in cortex between experimentally matched conscious and unconscious events. This (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  24. The global workspace theory of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 2007 - In Max Velmans & Susan Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Blackwell. pp. 236--246.
  25.  94
    Metaphors of consciousness and attention in the brain.Bernard J. Baars - 1998 - Trends in Neurosciences 21:58-62.
  26.  67
    Surprisingly small subcortical structures are needed for the state of waking consciousness, while cortical projection areas seem to provide perceptual contents of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1995 - Consciousness and Cognition 4 (2):159-62.
  27. The role of consciousness in memory.S. Franklin, B. J. Baars, U. Ramamurthy & M. Ventura - 2005 - Brains, Minds and Media 1.
    Conscious events interact with memory systems in learning, rehearsal and retrieval (Ebbinghaus 1885/1964; Tulving 1985). Here we present hypotheses that arise from the IDA computional model (Franklin,Kelemen and McCauley 1998; Franklin 2001b) of global workspace theory (Baars 1988, 2002). Our primary tool for this exploration is a flexible cognitive cycle employed by the IDA computational model and hypothesized to be a basic element of human cognitive processing. Since cognitive cycles are hypothesized to occur five to tentimes a second and include (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  28.  44
    How does a serial, integrated and very limited stream of consciousness emerge from a nervous system that is mostly unconscious, distributed, parallel and of enormous capacity?Bernard J. Baars - 1993 - In G. R. Bock & James L. Marsh (eds.), Experimental and Theoretical Studies of Consciousness. Ciba Foundation Symposium 174. pp. 174--282.
  29.  31
    The Global Workspace Theory of Consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 2017 - In Susan Schneider & Max Velmans (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Chichester, UK: Wiley. pp. 227–242.
    Global Workspace Theory (GWT) can be compared to a theater of mind, in which conscious contents resemble a bright spot on the stage of immediate memory, selected by a spotlight of attention under executive guidance. Only the bright spot is conscious; the rest of the theater is dark and unconscious. GWT has been implemented in a number of explicit and testable global workspace models (GWM's). These specific GW models suggest that conscious experiences recruit widely distributed brain functions that are mostly (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  31
    A curious coincidence? Consciousness as an object of scientific scrutiny fits our personal experience remarkably well.Bernard J. Baars - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):669-670.
  31. A neural global workspace model for conscious attention.J. B. Newman, Bernard J. Baars & S. Cho - 1997 - Neural Networks 10:1195-1206.
  32.  50
    Global workspace theory emerges unscathed.Murray Shanahan & Bernard Baars - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6):524-525.
    Our aim in this reply is to defend Global Workspace theory (GWT) from the challenge of Block's article. We argue that Block's article relies on an outdated and imprecise concept of access, and perpetuates a common misunderstanding of GWT that conflates the global workspace with working memory. In the light of the relevant clarifications, Block's conclusion turns out to be unwarranted, and the basic tenets of GWT emerge unscathed.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  33. Understanding subjectivity: Global workspace theory and the resurrection of the observing self.Bernard J. Baars - 1996 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 (3):211-17.
    The world of our experience consists at all times of two parts, an objective and a subjective part . . . The objective part is the sum total of whatsoever at any given time we may be thinking of, the subjective part is the inner 'state' in which the thinking comes to pass.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  34. The global brainweb: An update on global workspace theory.Bernard J. Baars - 2003 - Science and Consciousness Review 2.
  35. A neurobiological interpretation of the global workspace theory of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars & J. B. Newman - 1994 - In Antti Revonsuo & Matti Kamppinen (eds.), Consciousness in Philosophy and Cognitive Neuroscience. Lawrence Erlbaum.
  36.  24
    Putting the focus on the fringe: Three empirical cases.Bernard J. Baars - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (2):126-36.
    After suggesting an operational definition for fringe experiences—as opposed to clearly conscious and clearly unconscious phenomena—we examine three empirical cases: The tip-of-the-tongue experience, the fringe experience of "wrongness," and the case of conscious focus on abstract, hard-to-image conscious contents. In each case, Mangan′s four major claims are explored in some detail. Most tasks seem to involve a combination of conscious experiences, complex unconscious representations, and multiple fringe experiences. The chief disagreement from this analysis involves vague experiences that are generally believed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37. One, not two, neural correlates of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars & Steven Laureys - 2005 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9 (6):269.
  38. Attention, self, and conscious self-monitoring.Bernard J. Baars - 1998 - In A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge University Press.
    ?In everday language, the word ?attention? implies control of access to consciousness, and we adopt this usage here. Attention itself can be either voluntary or automatic. This can be readily modeled in the theory. Further, a contrastive analysis of spontaneously self?attributed vs. self?alien experiences suggests that ?self? can be interpreted as the more enduring, higher levels of the dominant context hierarchy, which create continuity over the changing flow of events. Since context is by definition unconscious in GW theory, self in (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  39.  34
    Contrastive phenomenology: A thoroughly empirical approach to consciousness.B. Baars - 1997 - In Ned Block, Owen Flanagan & Güven Güzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates. MIT Press. pp. 187--202.
  40.  30
    The double life of BF Skinner: inner conflict, dissociation and the scientific taboo against consciousness.Bernard Baars - 2003 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 10 (1):5-25.
    B.F. Skinner was the voice of radical behaviourism for some five decades, fighting relentlessly against consciousness as a scientific question. While in public he always argued the case for behaviourism, in fact Skinner was deeply at odds with himself, as he reveals in several books. Surprisingly, as a college student he was deeply interested in becoming a stream-of-consciousness novelist. When that ambition failed, he reacted with a radical rejection of the conscious life. Decades later Skinner's inner struggle still continued, as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  41.  37
    Why volition is a foundation issue for psychology.Bernard J. Baars - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (4):281-309.
    Since the advent of behaviorism the question of volition or "will" has been largely neglected. We consider evidence indicating that two identical behaviors may be quite distinct with respect to volition: For instance, with practice the details of predictable actions become less and less voluntary, even if the behavior itself does not visibly change. Likewise, people can voluntarily imitate involuntary slips they have just made. Such examples suggest that the concept of volition applies not to visible behavior per se, but (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  42.  46
    Experimental Slips and Human Error: Exploring the Architecture of Volition.Bernard J. Baars - 1992 - Plenum Press.
    This work makes three valuable contributions to the study of human slips and errors.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43. Recovering consciousness: A timeline.Bernard J. Baars - forthcoming - Science and Consciousness Review.
  44. Cognitive theories of consciousness.Katherine McGovern & Bernard J. Baars - 2007 - In Philip David Zelazo, Morris Moscovitch & Evan Thompson (eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 177--205.
  45.  80
    Evolutionary pressures for perceptual stability and self as guides to machine consciousness.Stan Franklin, Sidney D’Mello, Bernard J. Baars & Uma Ramamurthy - 2009 - International Journal of Machine Consciousness 1 (1):99-110.
    The currently leading cognitive theory of consciousness, Global Workspace Theory,1,2 postulates that the primary functions of consciousness include a global broadcast serving to recruit internal resources with which to deal with the current situation and to modulate several types of learning. In addition, conscious experiences present current conditions and problems to a "self" system, an executive interpreter that is identifiable with brain structures like the frontal lobes and precuneus.1Be it human, animal or artificial, an autonomous agent3 is said to be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46. The Neural Basis of Conscious Experience.Bernard J. Baars - 1988 - In A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  47. Attention vs consciousness in the visual brain: Differences in conception, phenomenology, behavior, neuroanatomy, and physiology.Bernard J. Baars - 1999 - Journal of General Psychology 126:224-33.
  48.  10
    Putting the Focus on the Fringe: Three Empirical Cases.Bernard J. Baars - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (2):126-136.
    After suggesting an operational definition for fringe experiences—as opposed to clearly conscious and clearly unconscious phenomena—we examine three empirical cases: The tip-of-the-tongue experience, the fringe experience of "wrongness," and the case of conscious focus on abstract, hard-to-image conscious contents. In each case, Mangan′s four major claims are explored in some detail. Most tasks seem to involve a combination of conscious experiences, complex unconscious representations, and multiple fringe experiences. The chief disagreement from this analysis involves vague experiences that are generally believed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49. How deliberate, spontaneous, and unwanted memories emerge in a computational model of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars, Uma Ramamurthy & Stan Franklin - 2007 - In John H. Mace (ed.), Involuntary Memory. New Perspectives in Cognitive Psychology. Blackwell. pp. 177-207.
  50.  24
    Editorial: What can Neuroscience Learn from Contemplative Practices?Zoran Josipovic & Bernard J. Baars - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
1 — 50 / 113