Results for 'Conclusive reasons'

988 found
Order:
  1. Conclusive reasons.Fred I. Dretske - 1971 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49 (1):1-22.
  2. Conclusive Reasons.Fred I. Dretske - 2000 - In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   162 citations  
  3. Conclusive Reasons and Epistemic Luck.Tamar Lando - 2016 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 94 (2):378-395.
    What is it to have conclusive reasons to believe a proposition P? According to a view famously defended by Dretske, a reason R is conclusive for P just in case [R would not be the case unless P were the case]. I argue that, while knowing that P is plausibly related to having conclusive reasons to believe that P, having such reasons cannot be understood in terms of the truth of this counterfactual condition. Simple (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  61
    Conclusive reasons that we perceive sets.David MacCallum - 2000 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14 (1):25 – 42.
    Penelope Maddy has defended a modified version of mathematical platonism that involves the perception of some sets. Frederick Suppe has developed a conclusive reasons account of empirical knowledge that, when applied to the sets of interest to Maddy, yields that we have knowledge of these sets. Thus, Benacerraf's challenge to the platonist to account for mathematical knowledge has been met, at least in part. Moreover, it is argued that the modalities involved in Suppe's conclusive reasons account (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5.  56
    Some conclusive reasons against 'conclusive reasons'.George S. Pappas & Marshall Swain - 1973 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 51 (1):72 – 76.
  6.  47
    Empirically conclusive reasons and scepticism.Raymond Martin - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 28 (3):215 - 217.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  7.  93
    Conclusive reasons, knowledge, and action.John A. Barker & Fred Adams - 2012 - Philosophical Issues 22 (1):35-52.
    The article presents information on the capabilities of Dretske-style analysis of knowing (DAK) and of several competing analyses with respect to accounting for the apparent facts. It informs that the DAK can ground plausible verdicts about knowledge and ignorance in cases involving lotteries. It further informs that the knowledge-efficacy donor imply the implausible thesis.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  21
    Warrant, Conclusive Reason, and Failure-Of-Transfer-Of-Warrant.Murali Ramachandran - 2018 - Problemos 94:35.
    [full article, abstract in English; abstract in Lithuanian] Fred Dretske motivates his denial of epistemic closure by way of the thought that the warrant for the premises of a valid argument need not transfer to the argument’s conclusion. The failure-of-transfer-of-warrant strategy has also been used by advocates of epistemic closure as a foil to Michael McKinsey’s argument against the compatibility of first person authority and semantic externalism, and also to illuminate, more generally, why certain valid arguments appear ill-suited for the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  50
    Conclusive reasons and scepticism.William S. Boardman - 1978 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 56 (1):32 – 40.
  10.  61
    Conclusive reasons and knowledge.Douglas Odegard - 1976 - Mind 85 (338):239-241.
  11.  77
    Closure, Defeasibility and Conclusive Reasons.Claudio Almeida - 2007 - Acta Analytica 22 (4):301-319.
    It is argued, on the basis of new counterexamples, that neither knowledge nor epistemic justification (or epistemic rationality ) can reasonably be thought to be closed under logical implication. The argument includes an attempt to reconcile the fundamental intuitions of the opposing parties in the debate.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12.  11
    Moral Obligation as a Conclusive Reason: On Bernard Williams’ Critique of the Morality System.Allyn Fives - forthcoming - Topoi:1-10.
    Bernard Williams’ critique of _the morality system_, as illustrated in his reading of Aeschylus’ _Agamemnon_, is intended to show both that real moral conflicts can arise, and that a moral obligation is merely one reason among others and can be defeated by the thick concepts of a shared ethical life. In response, I want to advance two lines of argument. First, when Williams argues that a moral obligation can be the locus of moral conflict, a further step is required to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  39
    Some Inconclusive Reasons Against ‘Conclusive Reasons’.Martin Curd - 1983 - Philosophy Research Archives 9:293-302.
    In, “Some Conclusive Reasons Against ‘Conclusive Reasons’”, Pappas and Swain have criticized Dretske’s theory that conclusive reasons are necessary for knowledge. In their view this condition is too strong. They attempt to show this by means of two purported counterexamples: the cup-hologram case and the generator case. This paper defends Dretske’s analysis against these challenges.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  6
    Some Inconclusive Reasons Against ‘Conclusive Reasons’.Martin Curd - 1983 - Philosophy Research Archives 9:293-302.
    In, “Some Conclusive Reasons Against ‘Conclusive Reasons’”, Pappas and Swain have criticized Dretske’s theory that conclusive reasons are necessary for knowledge. In their view this condition is too strong. They attempt to show this by means of two purported counterexamples: the cup-hologram case and the generator case. This paper defends Dretske’s analysis against these challenges.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Dretske & McDowell on perceptual knowledge, conclusive reasons, and epistemological disjunctivism.Peter J. Graham & Nikolaj J. L. L. Pedersen - 2020 - Philosophical Issues 30 (1):148-166.
    If you want to understand McDowell's spatial metaphors when he talks about perceptual knowledge, place him side-by-side with Dretske on perceptual knowledge. Though McDowell shows no evidence of reading Dretske's writings on knowledge from the late 1960s onwards (McDowell mentions "Epistemic Operators" once in passing), McDowell gives the same four arguments as Dretske for the conclusion that knowledge requires "conclusive" reasons that rule of the possibility of mistake. Despite various differences, we think it is best to read McDowell (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16. Closure, defeasibility and conclusive reasons.Claudio de Almeida - 2007 - Acta Analytica 22 (4):301 - 319.
    It is argued, on the basis of new counterexamples, that neither knowledge nor epistemic justification (or “epistemic rationality”) can reasonably be thought to be closed under logical implication. The argument includes an attempt to reconcile the fundamental intuitions of the opposing parties in the debate.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  64
    Legal Gaps and Conclusive Reasons.Jose Juan Moreso, Pablo E. Navarro & Cristina Redondo - 2002 - Theoria 68 (1):52-66.
    In his influential paper Legal Reasons, Sources and Gaps' reprinted in The Authority of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), Raz says that legal gaps only exist when law speaks with uncertain voice or when it speaks with many voices, but there are no gaps when law is silent. In this later case, rules of closure, which are analytically true, prevent from the occurrence of gaps. According to Raz, if there is a gap in a legal system, then both (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  67
    Belief, Control, and Conclusive Reasons.Gordon Barnes - 2002 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (2):315-325.
  19.  7
    Belief, Control, and Conclusive Reasons.Gordon Barnes - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (3):315-325.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  15
    Near Triviality of Conclusive Reasons.Tetsuji Iseda - 2005 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 14 (1):1-20.
  21.  8
    CHAPTER 5: Causal Analyses, Conclusive Reasons Analyses, and Reliability Analyses.Robert K. Shope - 2017 - In The Analysis of Knowing: A Decade of Research. Princeton University Press. pp. 119-170.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. A Logical Transmission Principle for Conclusive Reasons.Charles B. Cross - 2015 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (2):353-370.
    Dretske's conclusive reasons account of knowledge is designed to explain how epistemic closure can fail when the evidence for a belief does not transmit to some of that belief's logical consequences. Critics of Dretske dispute the argument against closure while joining Dretske in writing off transmission. This paper shows that, in the most widely accepted system for counterfactual logic , conclusive reasons are governed by an informative, non-trivial, logical transmission principle. If r is a conclusive (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  62
    The Harms of Enhancement and the Conclusive Reasons View.Thomas Douglas - 2015 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 24 (1):23-36.
    :Many critics of bioenhancement go to considerable lengths to establish the existence of reasons against pursuing bioenhancements but do little to establish the absence of reasons in favor. This suggests that they accept what Allen Buchanan has called the conclusive reasons view. According to this view, our reasons against bioenhancement are obviously decisive, so there is no need to balance them against countervailing reasons. Buchanan criticizes the CRV by showing that the reasons most (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24.  28
    Notes . Discussion . Book reviews rights and conclusive reasons.Danny Priel - 2005 - Ratio Juris 18 (3):410-414.
  25. The conclusion of practical reasoning: the shadow between idea and act.Sarah K. Paul - 2013 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43 (3):287-302.
    There is a puzzle about how to understand the conclusion of a successful instance of practical reasoning. Do the considerations adduced in reasoning rationalize the particular doing of an action, as Aristotle is sometimes interpreted as claiming? Or does reasoning conclude in the formation of an attitude – an intention, say – that has an action-type as its content? This paper attempts to clarify what is at stake in that debate and defends the latter view against some of its critics.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  26. The Conclusion of Practical Reasoning.John Brunero - 2021 - The Journal of Ethics 25 (1):13-37.
    According to the Aristotelian Thesis, the conclusion of practical reasoning is an action. Critics argue against it by pointing to cases in which some interference or inability prevents the production of action, yet in which that interference or inability doesn’t impugn the success of an agent’s reasoning. Some of those critics suggest instead that practical reasoning concludes in an intention, while others suggest it concludes in a belief with normative content, such as a belief about what one has conclusive, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  8
    Public reason, civic trust and conclusions of science.Nebojsa Zelic - 2018 - Rivista di Estetica 69:99-117.
    Rawlsian idea of public reason refers to the boundaries on political justification of coercive laws and public policies that have wide impact on lives of citizens. The boundaries of public reason means that political justification should be based on reasons we can expect every citizen can reasonably accept independently of any comprehensive religious, philosophical or moral doctrine to which she adhere. In modern liberal democracies characterized by reasonable pluralism of comprehensive doctrines it is unjustified for political argumentation to be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Default Reasoning: Jumping to Conclusions and Knowing When to Think Twice.Kent Bach - 1984 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 65 (1):37.
    Look before you leap. - Proverb. He who hesitates is lost. - Another proverb.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  29. The conclusion of practical reason.Sergio Tenenbaum - 2007 - In New Trends in Philosophy: Moral Psychology. Rodopi. pp. 323-343.
  30. The Conclusion of Practical Reason.Sergio Tenenbaum - 2007 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 94:323-343.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  31.  20
    Modeling Human Syllogistic Reasoning: The Role of “No Valid Conclusion”.Nicolas Riesterer, Daniel Brand, Hannah Dames & Marco Ragni - 2020 - Topics in Cognitive Science 12 (1):446-459.
    After 100+ years of studying syllogistic reasoning, what have we learned? Well, Riesterer and colleagues suggest that we have learned to throw away most of the data! If that seems like a bad idea to you then, be assured, that the authors agree with you. The sad fact is that the conclusion of “No Valid Conclusion” (NVC) is one of the most frequently selected responses in syllogistic reasoning but these “majority data” have been ignored by most researchers. Riesterer and colleagues (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  35
    The Conclusion of the Critique of Pure Reason.Jean Grondin - 1993 - Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 16 (1):165-178.
    Based on some interpretations about the Critique of Pure Reason, the author holds a real answer to the question about the possibility of Metaphysics remains in the uncertainty there. Without any proper Conclusion of the work, this question is displaced to the background and it is, in certain way, superseded by the question about God's existence and a future life. In II, The Transcendental Doctrine of Method, Kant points towards the Highest Good as a determining ground of the ultimate end (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. The conclusion of practical reasoning.Gerald W. Barnes - 1983 - Analysis 43 (4):193-199.
  34.  97
    Action as the Conclusion of Practical Reasoning; The Critique of a Rödlian Account.Evgenia Mylonaki - 2018 - European Journal of Philosophy (1):30-45.
    In this paper I take up the question of whether and in what sense action might be the conclusion of practical reasoning and argue against the answer provided by Sebastian Rödl's account of practical reasoning. Rödl's account aspires to steer a middle ground between the attitudinal and the neo-Aristotelian accounts of practical reasoning, by proposing that its conclusion is at once a thought and a movement. This account is worth considering for it promises to explain both practical reasoning's practicality and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  13
    Treatise, Conclusive Section of Volume I: Reason and Emotion in Hume’s Philosophy.Hee-Bong Choi - 2013 - 동서철학연구(Dong Seo Cheol Hak Yeon Gu; Studies in Philosophy East-West) 67:57-74.
  36.  39
    CONCLUSION. Faith in Reason.Frederick C. Beiser - 1996 - In The Sovereignty of Reason: The Defense of Rationality in the Early English Enlightenment. Princeton University Press. pp. 323-328.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  4
    The Conclusion of the Critique of Pure Reason.Jean Grondin - 1993 - Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 16 (1):165-178.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  6
    Conclusion: In Praise of Reason after All.Dan Sperber & Hugo Mercier - 2017 - In Dan Sperber & Hugo Mercier (eds.), The Enigma of Reason. Cambridge, MA, USA: Harvard University Press. pp. 328-336.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  9
    The reasons for the conclusion of the union and the relation in the process of conservative and radical influence in the Brest region.Vyacheslav Lypynsʹkyy - 2016 - Ukrainian Religious Studies 81:150-165.
    In his work "Religion and Church in the History of Ukraine," V.Lipinsky primarily answers the question: Did Volodymyr the Great accept Christianity in the time when Byzantium was still in connection with Rome and the prince was "Uniate", but "Orthodox"? Volodymyr the Great accepted Christianity in time when there was no official gap between Byzantium and Rome, but the relationship between these two Christian hierarchies was already very tense from the days of Photius, which is about a century before Vladimir (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  39
    Why Derek Parfit had reasons to accept the Repugnant Conclusion.Torbjörn Tännsjö - 2020 - Utilitas 32 (4):387-397.
    Total views imply what Derek Parfit has called ‘the repugnant conclusion’. There are several strategies aimed at debunking the intuition that this implication is repugnant. In particular, it goes away when we consider the principle of unrestricted instantiation, according to which any instantiation of the repugnant conclusion must appear repugnant if we should be warranted in relying on it as evidence against total theories. However, there are instantiations of the conclusion where it doesn't seem to be at all repugnant. Hence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41. Reasons and Persons.Derek Parfit - 1984 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Challenging, with several powerful arguments, some of our deepest beliefs about rationality, morality, and personal identity, Parfit claims that we have a false view about our own nature. It is often rational to act against our own best interersts, he argues, and most of us have moral views that are self-defeating. We often act wrongly, although we know there will be no one with serious grounds for complaint, and when we consider future generations it is very hard to avoid conclusions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2794 citations  
  42.  40
    Biased steps toward reasonable conclusions: How self-deception remains hidden.Roy F. Baumeister & Karen Pezza Leith - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1):106-107.
    How can self-deception avoid intention and conscious recognition? Nine processes of self-deception seem to involve biased links between plausible ideas. These processes allow self-deceivers to regard individual conclusions as fair and reasonable. Bias is only detected by comparing broad patterns, which individual self-deceivers will not do.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  12
    Reinstatement, floating conclusions, and the credulity of Mental Model reasoning.Jean-Franĉois Bonnefon - 2004 - Cognitive Science 28 (4):621-631.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  20
    The wording of conclusions in relational reasoning.Jean-Baptiste Van der Henst & Walter Schaeken - 2005 - Cognition 97 (1):1-22.
  45. weighing reasons.Garrett Cullity - 2018 - In Daniel Star (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity. New York, NY, United States of America: Oxford University Press.
    What is involved in weighing normative reasons against each other? One attractive answer offers us the following Simple Picture: a fact is a reason for action when it bears to an action the normative relation of counting in its favour; this relation comes in different strengths or weights; the weights of the reasons for and against an action can be summed; the reasons for performing the action are sufficient when no other action is more strongly supported, overall; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  46.  11
    Who jumps to conclusions? A comprehensive assessment of probabilistic reasoning in psychosis following traumatic brain injury (PFTBI).Batty Rachel, Francis Andrew, Thomas Neil, Hopwood Malcolm, Ponsford Jennie & Rossell Susan - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9.
  47.  12
    Accidents: Some reasoning about behavior, punishment, and a surprising conclusion.Tom Gillis - 2007 - Essays in the Philosophy of Humanism 15 (1):1-8.
    The author explores the idea that no behavior, even that of criminals, has any ultimate intentional basis, and that all decisions and beliefs occur by accident only.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  20
    The wording of conclusions in relational reasoning.Walter van der HenstSchaeken - 2005 - Cognition 97 (1):1-22.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  42
    Dubious Premises—Evil Conclusions: Moral Reasoning at the Nuremberg Trials.Edmund D. Pellegrino & David C. Thomasma - 2000 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 9 (2):261-274.
    Fifty years ago, 23 Nazi physicians were defendants before a military tribunal in Nuremberg, charged with crimes against humanity. During that trial, the world learned of their personal roles in human experimentation with political and military prisoners, mass eugenic sterilizations, state-ordered euthanasia of the and the program of genocide we now know as the Holocaust. These physicians, and their colleagues who did not stand trial, were universally condemned in the free world as ethical pariahs. The term became the paradigm for (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  18
    Law, an Affair of Reason, conclusion.Gerard Smith - 1939 - Modern Schoolman 17 (1):8-9.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 988