Search results for 'Continuity' (try it on Scholar)

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  45
    Laura Klaming & Pim Haselager (2013). Did My Brain Implant Make Me Do It? Questions Raised by DBS Regarding Psychological Continuity, Responsibility for Action and Mental Competence. Neuroethics 6 (3):527-539.
    Deep brain stimulation is a well-accepted treatment for movement disorders and is currently explored as a treatment option for various neurological and psychiatric disorders. Several case studies suggest that DBS may, in some patients, influence mental states critical to personality to such an extent that it affects an individual’s personal identity, i.e. the experience of psychological continuity, of persisting through time as the same person. Without questioning the usefulness of DBS as a treatment option for various serious and treatment (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   9 citations  
  2.  29
    Anthony F. Peressini (forthcoming). Causation, Probability, and the Continuity Bind. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
    Analyses of singular (token-level) causation often make use of the idea that a cause in- creases the probability of its effect. Of particular salience in such accounts are the values of the probability function of the effect, conditional on the presence and absence of the putative cause, analyzed around the times of the events in question: causes are characterized by the effect’s probability function being greater when conditionalized upon them. Put this way it becomes clearer that the ‘behavior’ (continuity) (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  3.  40
    Simon Beck (2015). The Extreme Claim, Psychological Continuity and the Person Life View. South African Journal of Philosophy 34 (3).
    Marya Schechtman has raised a series of worries for the Psychological Continuity Theory of personal identity (PCT) stemming out of what Derek Parfit called the ‘Extreme Claim’. This is roughly the claim that theories like it are unable to explain the importance we attach to personal identity. In her recent Staying Alive (2014), she presents further arguments related to this and sets out a new narrative theory, the Person Life View (PLV), which she sees as solving the problems as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  4.  9
    K. Brad Wray (forthcoming). Systematicity and the Continuity Thesis. Synthese:1-14.
    Hoyningen-Huene develops an account of what science is, distinguishing it from common sense. According to Hoyningen-Huene, the key distinguishing feature is that science is more systematic. He identifies nine ways in which science is more systematic than common sense. I compare Hoyningen-Huene’s view to a view I refer to as the “Continuity Thesis.” The Continuity Thesis states that scientific knowledge is just an extension of common sense. This thesis is associated with Quine, Planck, and others. I argue that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  5.  20
    Kelly A. Parker (1998). The Continuity of Peirce's Thought. Vanderbilt University Press.
    A comprehensive and systematic reconstruction of the philosophy of Charles S. Peirce, perhaps America's most far-ranging and original philosopher, which reveals the unity of his complex and influential body of thought. We are still in the early stages of understanding the thought of C. S. Peirce (1839-1914). Although much good work has been done in isolated areas, relatively little considers the Peircean system as a whole. Peirce made it his life's work to construct a scientifically sophisticated and logically rigorous philosophical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   12 citations  
  6.  59
    Tom Froese & Ezequiel A. Di Paolo (2009). Sociality and the Life–Mind Continuity Thesis. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8 (4):439-463.
    The life–mind continuity thesis holds that mind is prefigured in life and that mind belongs to life. The biggest challenge faced by proponents of this thesis is to show how an explanatory framework that accounts for basic biological processes can be systematically extended to incorporate the highest reaches of human cognition. We suggest that this apparent ‘cognitive gap’ between minimal and human forms of life appears insurmountable largely because of the methodological individualism that is prevalent in cognitive science. Accordingly, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   5 citations  
  7.  15
    Paulo De Jesus (2016). Autopoietic Enactivism, Phenomenology and the Deep Continuity Between Life and Mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 15 (2):265-289.
    In their recent book Radicalizing Enactivism. Basic minds without content, Dan Hutto and Erik Myin make two important criticisms of what they call autopoietic enactivism. These two criticisms are that AE harbours tacit representationalists commitments and that it has too liberal a conception of cognition. Taking the latter claim as its main focus, this paper explores the theoretical underpinnings of AE in order to tease out how it might respond to H&M. In so doing it uncovers some reasons which not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  8.  4
    Michael D. Kirchhoff (forthcoming). Autopoiesis, Free Energy, and the Life–Mind Continuity Thesis. Synthese:1-22.
    The life–mind continuity thesis is difficult to study, especially because the relation between life and mind is not yet fully understood, and given that there is still no consensus view neither on what qualifies as life nor on what defines mind. Rather than taking up the much more difficult task of addressing the many different ways of explaining how life relates to mind, and vice versa, this paper considers two influential accounts addressing how best to understand the life–mind (...) thesis: first, the theory of autopoiesis developed in biology and in enactivist theories of mind; and second, the recently formulated free energy principle in theoretical neurobiology, with roots in thermodynamics and statistical physics. This paper advances two claims. The first is that the free energy principle should be preferred to the theory of AT, as classically formulated. The second is that the FEP and the recently formulated framework of autopoietic enactivism can be shown to be genuinely continuous on a number of central issues, thus raising the possibility of a joint venture when it comes to answering the life–mind continuity thesis. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  9. Michael C. Rea & David Silver (2000). Personal Identity and Psychological Continuity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (1):185-194.
    In a recent article, Trenton Mericks argues that psychological continuity analyses of personal identity over time are incompatible with endurantism. We contend that if Merricks’s argument is valid, a parallel argument establishes that PC-analyses of personal identity are incompatible with perdurantism; hence, the correct conclusion to draw is simply that such analyses are all necessarily false. However, we also show that there is good reason to doubt that Merricks’s argument is valid.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  10.  72
    Johan E. Gustafsson (2011). Phenomenal Continuity and the Bridge Problem. Philosophia 39 (2):289–296.
    Any theory that analyses personal identity in terms of phenomenal continuity needs to deal with the ordinary interruptions of our consciousness that it is commonly thought that a person can survive. This is the bridge problem. The present paper offers a novel solution to the bridge problem based on the proposal that dreamless sleep need not interrupt phenomenal continuity. On this solution one can both hold that phenomenal continuity is necessary for personal identity and that persons can (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  11.  80
    Robert Francescotti (2008). Psychological Continuity, Fission, and the Non-Branching Constraint. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 89 (1):21-31.
    Abstract: Those who endorse the Psychological Continuity Approach (PCA) to analyzing personal identity need to impose a non-branching constraint to get the intuitively correct result that in the case of fission, one person becomes two. With the help of Brueckner's (2005) discussion, it is shown here that the sort of non-branching clause that allows proponents of PCA to provide sufficient conditions for being the same person actually runs contrary to the very spirit of their theory. The problem is first (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  12. Desheng Zong (2011). Retention of Indexical Belief and the Notion of Psychological Continuity. Philosophical Quarterly 61 (244):608-623.
    A widely accepted view in the discussion of personal identity is that the notion of psychological continuity expresses a one--many or many--one relation. This belief is unfounded. A notion of psychological continuity expresses a one--many or many--one relation only if it includes, as a constituent, psychological properties whose relation with their bearers is one--many or many--one; but the relation between an indexical psychological state and its bearer when first tokened is not a one--many or many--one relation. It follows (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  13. Simon Beck (2011). Causal Copersonality: In Defence of the Psychological Continuity Theory. South African Journal of Philosophy 30 (2):244-255.
    The view that an account of personal identity can be provided in terms of psychological continuity has come under fire from an interesting new angle in recent years. Critics from a variety of rival positions have argued that it cannot adequately explain what makes psychological states co-personal (i.e. the states of a single person). The suggestion is that there will inevitably be examples of states that it wrongly ascribes using only the causal connections available to it. In this paper, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  14.  92
    Robert Francescotti (2010). Psychological Continuity and the Necessity of Identity. American Philosophical Quarterly 47 (4):337-350.
    In attempting to understand personal identity, it is common practice to imagine a person existing at some time t and a person existing at a time t* , and then to ask, What does it take for person x at t to be the same person as person y at t*?The Psychological Continuity Approach answers: there is a relation, R, of psychological continuity such that person x at t is the same person as person y at t* if (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  15.  17
    Hajime Ishihara (1992). Continuity Properties in Constructive Mathematics. Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (2):557-565.
    The purpose of this paper is an axiomatic study of the interrelations between certain continuity properties. We deal with principles which are equivalent to the statements "every mapping is sequentially nondiscontinuous", "every sequentially nondiscontinuous mapping is sequentially continuous", and "every sequentially continuous mapping is continuous". As corollaries, we show that every mapping of a complete separable space is continuous in constructive recursive mathematics (the Kreisel-Lacombe-Schoenfield-Tsejtin theorem) and in intuitionism.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   6 citations  
  16. Trenton Merricks (2000). Perdurance and Psychological Continuity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (1):195-199.
    If persons endure, personal identity cannot be analyzed in terms of psychological continuity. That is one conclusion defended in my “Endurance, Psychological Continuity, and the Importance of Personal Identity’ . Rea and Silver claim that my argument for that conclusion is sound only if a parallel argument is sound. The parallel argument concludes that if persons perdure, personal identity cannot be analyzed in terms of psychological continuity. In this paper, I show that Rea and Silver are mistaken. (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  17.  15
    Marij van Strien (2015). Continuity in Nature and in Mathematics: Boltzmann and Poincaré. Synthese 192 (10):3275-3295.
    The development of rigorous foundations of differential calculus in the course of the nineteenth century led to concerns among physicists about its applicability in physics. Through this development, differential calculus was made independent of empirical and intuitive notions of continuity, and based instead on strictly mathematical conditions of continuity. However, for Boltzmann and Poincaré, the applicability of mathematics in physics depended on whether there is a basis in physics, intuition or experience for the fundamental axioms of mathematics—and this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  18. Louis N. Sandowsky (2006). Hume and Husserl: The Problem of the Continuity or Temporalization of Consciousness. International Philosophical Quarterly. Vol. 46, No. 1, Issue 181 (March 2006) 46 (181):59-74.
    This paper examines Husserl’s fascination with the issues raised by Hume’s critique of the philosophy of the ego and the continuity of consciousness. The path taken here follows a continental and phenomenological approach. Husserl’s 1905 lecture course on the temporalization of immanent time-consciousness is a phenomenological-eidetic examination of how the continuity of consciousness and the consciousness of continuity are possible. It was by way of Husserl’s reading of Hume’s discussion of “flux” or “flow” that his discourse on (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  19.  7
    S. Jenei & F. Montagna (2003). On the Continuity Points of Left-Continuous T-Norms. Archive for Mathematical Logic 42 (8):797-810.
    Left-continuous t-norms are much more complicated than the continuous ones, and obtaining a complete classification of them seems to be a very hard task. In this paper we investigate some aspects of left-continuous t-norms, with emphasis on their continuity points. In particular, we are interested in left-continuous t-norms which are isomorphic to t-norms which are continuous in the rationals. We characterize such a class, and we prove that it contains the class of all weakly cancellative left-continuous t-norms.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  20.  33
    U. Klein (2009). Schrödinger's Equation with Gauge Coupling Derived From a Continuity Equation. Foundations of Physics 39 (8):964-995.
    A quantization procedure without Hamiltonian is reported which starts from a statistical ensemble of particles of mass m and an associated continuity equation. The basic variables of this theory are a probability density ρ, and a scalar field S which defines a probability current j=ρ ∇ S/m. A first equation for ρ and S is given by the continuity equation. We further assume that this system may be described by a linear differential equation for a complex-valued state variable (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  21.  19
    Ingunn Elstad & Kirsti Torjuul (2009). Continuity of Nursing and the Time of Sickness. Nursing Philosophy 10 (2):91-102.
    This paper explores the relationship between temporal continuity in nursing and temporal features of sickness. It is based on phenomenological and hermeneutical philosophy, empirical studies of sickness time, and the nursing theories of Nightingale, of Benner and of Benner and Wrubel. In the first part, temporal continuity is defined as distinct from interpersonal continuity. Tensions between temporal continuity and discontinuity are discussed in the contexts of care management, of conceptualisations of disease and of time itself. Temporal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  22.  31
    Mario Villalobos (2013). Autopoiesis, Life, Mind and Cognition: Bases for a Proper Naturalistic Continuity. [REVIEW] Biosemiotics 6 (3):379-391.
    The strong version of the life-mind continuity thesis claims that mind can be understood as an enriched version of the same functional and organizational properties of life. Contrary to this view, in this paper I argue that mental phenomena offer distinctive properties, such as intentionality or representational content, that have no counterpart in the phenomenon of life, and that must be explained by appealing to a different level of functional and organizational principles. As a strategy, and following Maturana’s autopoietic (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  23.  11
    Claudio Mazzola (2015). On Continuity and Endurance. Acta Analytica 30 (2):133-147.
    According to three-dimensionalism, objects persist in time by being wholly present at each time they exist; on the contrary, four-dimensionalism asserts that objects persist by having different temporal parts at different times or that they are instantaneous temporal parts of four-dimensional aggregates. Le Poidevin has argued that four-dimensionalism better accommodates two common assumptions concerning persistence and continuity; namely, that time itself is continuous and that objects persist in time in a continuous way. To this purpose, he has offered two (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  24.  63
    Martti Kuokkanen & Timo Tuomivaara (1994). The Threshold Model of Scientific Change and the Continuity of Scientific Knowledge. Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 25 (2):327 - 335.
    The continuity thesis of the Poznań school threshold model of the growth of scientific knowledge is considered in the light of the example of Van der Waals' and Boyle-Mariotte's laws. It is argued - using both traditional logical means and the structuralist reconstruction of the example - that the continuity thesis does not hold. A distinction between 'a historical and a systematic point of view' is introduced and it is argued that the continuity thesis of the threshold (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  25.  3
    D. Bridges & Luminita Simona Vîta (2001). Characterising Near Continuity Constructively. Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (4):535-538.
    The relation between near continuity and sequential continuity for mappings between metric spaces is explored constructively. It is also shown that the classical implications “near continuity implies sequential continuity” and “near continuity implies apart continuity” are essentially nonconstructive.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  26.  6
    Adrian M. S. Piper (1987). Personal Continuity and Instrumental Rationality in Rawls' Theory of Justice. Social Theory and Practice 13 (1):49-76.
    I want to examine the implications of a metaphysical thesis which is presupposed in various objections to Rawls' theory of justice.Although their criticisms differ in many respects, they concur in employing what I shall refer to as the continuity thesis. This consists of the following claims conjointly: (1) The parties in the original position (henceforth the OP) are, and know themselves to be, fully mature persons who will be among the members of the well-ordered society (henceforth the WOS) which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  27.  16
    Matthew E. Moore (2013). Peirce's Topical Theory of Continuity. Synthese 192 (4):1-17.
    In the last decade of his life C.S. Peirce began to formulate a purely geometrical theory of continuity to supersede the collection-theoretic theory he began to elaborate around the middle of the 1890s. I argue that Peirce never succeeded in fully formulating the later theory, and that while that there are powerful motivations to adopt that theory within Peirce’s system, it has little to recommend it from an external perspective.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  28.  1
    Douglas Bridges & Luminita Dediu (1999). Weak-Operator Continuity and the Existence of Adjoints. Mathematical Logic Quarterly 45 (2):203-206.
    It is shown, within constructive mathematics, that the unit ball B1 of the set of bounded operators on a Hilbert space H is weak-operator totally bounded. This result is then used to prove that the weak-operator continuity of the mapping T → AT on B1 is equivalent to the existence of the adjoint of A.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  29.  19
    Oritsegbubemi Anthony Oyowe (2013). Physical Continuity, Self and the Future. Philosophia 41 (1):257-269.
    Jeff McMahan's impressive recent defence of the embodied mind theory of personal identity in his highly acclaimed work The Ethics of Killing has undoubtedly reawakened belief that physical continuity is a necessary component of the relation that matters in our self-interested concern for the future. My aim in this paper is to resist this belief in a somewhat roundabout way. I want to address this belief in a somewhat roundabout way by revisiting a classic defence of the belief that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  30.  8
    Douglas Bridges & Hajime Ishihara (1994). Absolute Continuity and the Uniqueness of the Constructive Functional Calculus. Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (4):519-527.
    The constructive functional calculus for a sequence of commuting selfadjoint operators on a separable Hilbert space is shown to be independent of the orthonormal basis used in its construction. The proof requires a constructive criterion for the absolute continuity of two positive measures in terms of test functions.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  31.  22
    Christian Rosendal (2009). Automatic Continuity of Group Homomorphisms. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 15 (2):184-214.
    We survey various aspects of the problem of automatic continuity of homomorphisms between Polish groups.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  32.  16
    Fredrik Bragesjö, Aant Elzinga & Dick Kasperowski (2012). Continuity or Discontinuity? Scientific Governance in the Pre-History of the 1977 Law of Higher Education and Research in Sweden. Minerva 50 (1):65-96.
    The objective of this paper is to balance two major conceptual tendencies in science policy studies, continuity and discontinuity theory. While the latter argue for fundamental and distinct changes in science policy in the late 20th century, continuity theorists show how changes do occur but not as abrupt and fundamental as discontinuity theorists suggests. As a point of departure, we will elaborate a typology of scientific governance developed by Hagendijk and Irwin ( 2006 ) and apply it to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  33.  9
    Klaus Petrus (1996). Naturgemässe Klassifikation Und Kontinuität Wissenschaft Und GeschichteNatural Classification and Continuity, Science and History. Some Reflections on Pierre Duhem. Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 27 (2):307-323.
    Duhem is commonly held to have founded his view of history of science as continuous on the ‘metaphsical assertion’ of natural classification. With the help of a strict distinction between formal and material characterization of natural classification I try to show that this imputation is problematic, if not simply incorrect. My analysis opens alternative perspectives on Duhem's talk of continuity, the ideal form of theories, and the rôle of ‘bon sens’; moreover it emphasizes some aspects of Duhem's realism that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  34.  2
    Douglas S. Bridges (1993). Sequential, Pointwise, and Uniform Continuity: A Constructive Note. Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):55-61.
    The main result of this paper is a weak constructive version of the uniform continuity theorem for pointwise continuous, real-valued functions on a convex subset of a normed linear space. Recursive examples are given to show that the hypotheses of this theorem are necessary. The remainder of the paper discusses conditions which ensure that a sequentially continuous function is continuous. MSC: 03F60, 26E40, 46S30.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  35.  3
    J. F. Donnelly (2006). Continuity, Stability and Community in Teaching. Educational Philosophy and Theory 38 (3):311–325.
    This article is concerned with understanding continuity and stability in teaching, and their significance. It looks particularly at the work of Anthony Giddens on structure and agency, that of Martin Heidegger on the limits of discursive and theoretical analysis, and the communitarian strand within ethics. It applies this discussion to understandings of teachers’ work in the context especially of policy and agendas for change, arguing that continuity and the notion of a community of practitioners is critical to maintaining (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  36. S. Seth Bordner (forthcoming). If We Stop Thinking About Berkeley's Problem of Continuity, Will It Still Exist? Journal of the History of Philosophy.
    Berkeley holds that the esse of sensible objects is percipi. So, sensible objects cannot exist unperceived. Naturally, this has invited questions about the existence of sensible objects when unperceived by finite minds. This is sometimes called the Problem of Continuity. It is frequently said that Berkeley solves the problem by invoking God’s ever-present perception to ensure that sensible objects maintain a continuous existence. Problems with this line of response have led some to a phenomenalist interpretation. This paper argues that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  37. Robert Francescotti (2010). Psychological Continuity and the Necessity of Identity. American Philosophical Quarterly 47 (4):337-350.
    In attempting to understand personal identity, it is common practice to imagine a person existing at some time t and a person existing at a time t* , and then to ask, What does it take for person x at t to be the same person as person y at t*?The Psychological Continuity Approach answers: there is a relation, R, of psychological continuity such that person x at t is the same person as person y at t* if (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  38.  79
    Robert Lane (2011). The Final Incapacity: Peirce on Intuition and the Continuity of Mind and Matter, Part I. Cognitio 12 (1).
    This is the first of two papers that examine Charles Peirce’s denial that human beings have a faculty of intuition. The semiotic and epistemo-logical aspects of that denial are well-known. My focus is on its neglected metaphysical aspect, which I argue amounts to the doctrine that there is no determinate boundary between the internal world of the cognizing subject and the external world that the subject cognizes. In the second paper, I will argue that the “objective idealism” of Peirce’s 1890s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  39. Robert Elliot (1991). Personal Identity and the Causal Continuity Requirement. Philosophical Quarterly 41 (January):55-75.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  40.  3
    Thomas A. Farmer, Sarah A. Cargill, Nicholas C. Hindy, Rick Dale & Michael J. Spivey (2007). Tracking the Continuity of Language Comprehension: Computer Mouse Trajectories Suggest Parallel Syntactic Processing. Cognitive Science 31 (5):889-909.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  41.  89
    Sydney Shoemaker (1992). Unger's Psychological Continuity Theory. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1):139-143.
  42.  43
    Kim Sawyer, Howard Sankey & Ric Lombardo (2013). Measurability Invariance, Continuity and a Portfolio Representation. Measurement 46 (1):89-96.
    Translate
      Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  43.  78
    G. C. Nerlich (1958). Sameness, Difference, and Continuity. Analysis 18 (June):144-149.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  44.  3
    Douglas S. Bridges (2008). Uniform Continuity Properties of Preference Relations. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 49 (1):97-106.
    The anti-Specker property, a constructive version of sequential compactness, is used to prove constructively that a pointwise continuous, order-dense preference relation on a compact metric space is uniformly sequentially continuous. It is then shown that Ishihara's principle BD-ℕ implies that a uniformly sequentially continuous, order-dense preference relation on a separable metric space is uniformly continuous. Converses of these two theorems are also proved.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  45.  18
    Norman Kretzmann (ed.) (1982). Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought. Cornell University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  46.  16
    Rajeev Rajaram & Brian Castellani (2012). Modeling Complex Systems Macroscopically: Case/Agent‐Based Modeling, Synergetics, and the Continuity Equation. Complexity 18 (2):8-17.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  47.  44
    Emmett L. Holman (1984). Continuity and the Metaphysics of Dualism. Philosophical Studies 45 (March):197-204.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  48.  38
    H. G. Callaway (1995). Intentionality Naturalized: Continuity, Reconstruction, and Instrumentalism. Dialectica 49 (2-4):147-68.
    This paper explicates and defends a social-naturalist conception of internationality and intentions, where internationality of scientific expressions is fundamental. Meanings of expressions are a function of their place in language-systems and of the relations of systems to object-level evidence and associated community activities-including deliberation and experiment. Naturalizing internationality requires social-intellectual reconstruction exemplified by the scientific community at its best. This approach emphasizes normative elements of pragmatic conceptions of meaning and their function in orientation. It requires social conditions and intellectual practices (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  49.  3
    Lyne Starling Reid (1953). The Development of Noncontinuity Behavior Through Continuity Learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology 46 (2):107.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  50.  5
    Carl Van Walraven, Natalie Oake, Alison Jennings & Alan J. Forster (2010). The Association Between Continuity of Care and Outcomes: A Systematic and Critical Review. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 16 (5):947-956.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
1 — 50 / 1000