Search results for 'Law Congresses' (try it on Scholar)

1000+ found
Sort by:
  1. Aleksander Peczenik & Mikael M. Karlsson (eds.) (1995). Law, Justice and the State: Essays on Justice and Rights: Proceedings of the 16th World Congress of the International Association for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy (Ivr), Reykjavík, 26 May-2 June, 1993. [REVIEW] F. Steiner Verlag.score: 48.0
  2. Jyrki Uusitalo (ed.) (1983). Philosophical Foundations of the Legal and Social Sciences: The 11th World Congress on Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy: Abstracts of Congress Papers. Finnish Society for Philosophy of Law.score: 48.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  3. Antony Duff & N. E. Simmonds (eds.) (1984). Philosophy and the Criminal Law. Steiner.score: 39.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  4. Harold J. Johnson (ed.) (1987). The Medieval Tradition of Natural Law. Medieval Institute Publications, Western Michigan University.score: 39.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  5. George F. McLean (ed.) (1975). Philosophy and Civil Law. Office of the National Secretary of the Association, Catholic University of America.score: 39.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  6. Robert N. Moles (ed.) (1988). Law and Economics: Association for Legal and Social Philosophy, Fourteenth Annual Conference, the Queen's University of Belfast, 2-4 April 1987. [REVIEW] F. Steiner.score: 39.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  7. William L. Twining (ed.) (1983). Facts in Law: Association for Legal and Social Philosophy, Ninth Annual Conference at Hatfield College, University of Durham, 2nd-4th April 1982. [REVIEW] Steiner.score: 39.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  8. Ota Weinberger, Peter Koller & Alfred Schramm (eds.) (1988). Law, Politics, Society: Reports of the 12th International Wittgenstein-Symposium, 7th to 14th August 1987, Kirchberg Am Wechsel, Austria. [REVIEW] Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.score: 39.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  9. Werner Maihofer & Gerhard Sprenger (eds.) (1900). Praktische Vernunft Und Theorien Der Gerechtigkeit: Xv. Weltkongress Der Internationalen Vereinigung für Rechts- Und Sozialphilosophie, Göttingen, 18. Bis 24. August 1991. [REVIEW] F. Steiner.score: 33.0
    Vihjanen: Institutional Mercy u S. Harwood: Is Mercy Unjust? u K. Tuori: Critical Positivism and the Problem of the Legitimacy of Law u K. Sevon: The Practical ...
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  10. Stavros Panou (ed.) (1988). Theory and Systems of Legal Philosophy: Ivr 12th World Congress, Athens, 1985: Proceedings. F. Steiner.score: 33.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  11. J. Roland Pennock & John William Chapman (eds.) (1985). Criminal Justice. New York University Press.score: 33.0
    This, the twenty-seventh volume in the annual series of publications by the American Society for Political and Legal Philosophy, features a number of distinguised contributors addressing the topic of criminal justice. Part I considers "The Moral and Metaphysical Sources of the Criminal Law," with contributions by Michael S. Moore, Lawrence Rosen, and Martin Shapiro. The four chapters in Part II all relate, more or less directly, to the issue of retribution, with papers by Hugo Adam Bedau, Michael Davis, Jeffrie G. (...)
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  12. Maile-Gene Sagen (ed.) (1985). Ethics and the Law. Iowa Humanities Board.score: 33.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  13. André Laks & Malcolm Schofield (eds.) (1995). Justice and Generosity: Studies in Hellenistic Social and Political Philosophy: Proceedings of the Sixth Symposium Hellenisticum. Cambridge University Press.score: 30.0
    Hegel's often-echoed verdict on the apolitical character of philosophy in the Hellenistic age is challenged in this collection of new essays, originally presented at the sixth meeting of the Symposium Hellenisticum. An international team of leading scholars reveals a vigorous intellectual scene of great diversity: analyses of political leadership and the Roman constitution in Aristotelian terms; Cynic repudiation of the polis - but accommodation with its rulers; Stoic and Epicurean theories of justice as the foundation of society; Cicero's moral critique (...)
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  14. Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld & David Carlson (eds.) (1991). Hegel and Legal Theory. Routledge.score: 30.0
    The first collection of essays directed towards jurisprudence with a Hegelian theme. The editors are committed to the idea that Hegel is the future source of great energy and insight within the legal academy.
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  15. J. L. M. Elders (ed.) (1984). Hugo Grotius, 1583-1983: Maastricht Hugo Grotius Colloquium, March 31, 1983. Van Gorcum.score: 30.0
  16. H. L. A. Hart & Ruth Gavison (eds.) (1987). Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy: The Influence of H.L.A. Hart. Oxford University Press.score: 30.0
    This is a collection of essays on themes of legal philosophy which have all been generated or affected by Hart's work. The topics covered include legal theory, responsibility, and enforcement of morals, with contributions from Ronald Dworkin, Rolf Sartorius, Neil MacCormach, David Lyons, Kent Greenawalt, Michael Moore, Joseph Raz, and C.L. Ten, among others.
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  17. Norman Howard-Jones & Zbigniew Bańkowski (eds.) (1979). Medical Experimentation and the Protection of Human Rights: Proceedings of the Xiith Cioms Round Table Conference, Cascais, Portugal, 30 November-1 December, 1978. [REVIEW] Who Publications Centre [Distributor].score: 30.0
  18. Pompeu Casanovas Romeu (ed.) (2007). Trends in Legal Knowledge: The Semantic Web and the Regulation of Electronic Social Systems: Papers From the B-4 Workshop on Artificial Intelligence and Law, May 25th- 27th 2005: Xxii World Congress of Philosophy Ivr '05 Granada, May 24th-29th 2005. [REVIEW] European Press Academic Pub..score: 24.0
  19. Imer B. Flores & Gülriz Uygur (eds.) (2010). Alternative Methods in the Education of Philosophy of Law and the Importance of Legal Philosophy in the Legal Education: Proceedings of the 23rd World Congress of the International Association for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy "Law and Legal Cultures in the 21st Century: Diversity and Unity" in Kraków, 2007. [REVIEW] Franz Steiner.score: 24.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  20. Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki & Mateusz Klinowski (eds.) (2010). Law, Liberty, Morality and Rights: 23rd World Congress of Legal and Social Philosophy, 2007, Cracow. Oficyna Wolters Kluwer Polska.score: 24.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  21. Thom Brooks (2007). Between Natural Law and Legal Positivism: Dworkin and Hegel on Legal Theory. Georgia State University Law Review 23 (3):513-60.score: 21.0
    In this article, I argue that - despite the absence of any clear influence of one theory on the other - the legal theories of Dworkin and Hegel share several similar and, at times, unique positions that join them together within a distinctive school of legal theory, sharing a middle position between natural law and legal positivism. In addition, each theory can help the other in addressing certain internal difficulties. By recognizing both Hegel and Dworkin as proponents of a position (...)
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  22. Robert C. Robinson (2010). The Role of Causation in Decision of Tort Law. Journal of Law, Development and Politics 1 (2).score: 21.0
    Tort law depends on three key concepts: causation, responsibility, and fault. However, I argue that the three key concepts are neither necessary, nor sufficient, for tort.
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  23. David Enoch (2011). Reason-Giving and the Law. In Leslie Green & Brian Leiter (eds.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law. Oxford University Press.score: 21.0
    A spectre is haunting legal positivists – and perhaps jurisprudes more generally – the spectre of the normativity of law. Whatever else law is, it is sometimes said, it is normative, and so whatever else a philosophical account of law accounts for, it should account for the normativity of law[1]. But law is at least partially a social matter, its content at least partially determined by social practices. And how can something social and descriptive in this down-to-earth kind of way (...)
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  24. Andrew Ashworth & Lucia Zedner (2008). Defending the Criminal Law: Reflections on the Changing Character of Crime, Procedure, and Sanctions. Criminal Law and Philosophy 2 (1):21-51.score: 21.0
    Recent years have seen mounting challenge to the model of the criminal trial on the grounds it is not cost-effective, not preventive, not necessary, not appropriate, or not effective. These challenges have led to changes in the scope of the criminal law, in criminal procedure, and in the nature and use of criminal trials. These changes include greater use of diversion, of fixed penalties, of summary trials, of hybrid civil–criminal processes, of strict liability, of incentives to plead guilty, and of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  25. Susan Haack (2008). Of Truth, in Science and in Law. Brooklyn Law Review 73 (2).score: 21.0
    Abstract: This paper responds to the question posed in the announcement of the conference at Brooklyn Law School at which it was presented: if and how [the inquiry into the reliability of proffered scientific testimony mandated by Daubert] relates to 'truth,' and whose view of the truth should prevail. The first step is to sketch the legal history leading up to Daubert, and to explore some of the difficulties Daubert brought in its wake; the next, to develop an account of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  26. Susan Haack (2009). Irreconcilable Differences? The Troubled Marriage of Science and Law. Law and Contemporary Problems 72 (1).score: 21.0
    Because its business is to resolve disputed issues, the law very often calls on those fields of science where the pressure of commercial interests is most severe. Because the legal system aspires to handle disputes promptly, the scientific questions to which it seeks answers will often be those for which all the evidence is not yet in. Because of its case-specificity, the legal system often demands answers of a kind science is not well-equipped to supply; and, for related reasons, constitutes (...)
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  27. Leslie P. Francis & John G. Francis (2010). Stateless Crimes, Legitimacy, and International Criminal Law: The Case of Organ Trafficking. [REVIEW] Criminal Law and Philosophy 4 (3):283-295.score: 21.0
    Organ trafficking and trafficking in persons for the purpose of organ transplantation are recognized as significant international problems. Yet these forms of trafficking are largely left out of international criminal law regimes and to some extent of domestic criminal law regimes as well. Trafficking of organs or persons for their organs does not come within the jurisdiction of the ICC, except in very special cases such as when conducted in a manner that conforms to the definitions of genocide or crimes (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  28. Douglas Husak (2010). Mistake of Law and Culpability. Criminal Law and Philosophy 4 (2):135-159.score: 21.0
    When does a defendant not deserve punishment because he is unaware that his conduct breaches a penal statute? Retributivists must radically rethink their answer to this question to do justice to our moral intuitions. I suggest that modest progress on this topic can be made by modeling our approach to ignorance of law on our familiar approach to ignorance of fact. We need to distinguish different levels of culpability in given mistakes and to differentiate what such mistakes may be about. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  29. David Dolinko (2012). Review of “Crime and Culpability: A Theory of Criminal Law”. [REVIEW] Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (1):93-102.score: 21.0
    This is a review of the challenging book in which Larry Alexander and Kimberly Ferzan propose sweeping revisions to the structure of substantive criminal law.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  30. Re'em Segev (forthcoming). Moral Rightness and the Significance of Law: Why, How and When Mistake of Law Matters. University of Toronto Law Journal, Forthcoming.score: 21.0
    The question of whether a mistake of law should negate or mitigate criminal liability is commonly considered to be pertinent to the culpability of the agent, often examined in light of the (epistemic) reasonableness of the mistake. I argue that this view disregards an important aspect of this question, namely whether a mistake of law affects the rightness of the action, particularly in light of the moral significance of the mistake. I argue that several plausible premises, regarding moral rightness under (...)
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  31. H. G. Callaway (2012). Review of Cassese, Five Masters of International Law. [REVIEW] Law and Politics Book Review 22 (1):154-161.score: 21.0
    Focused on five prominent scholars of international law, and casting light on the related institutions which frequently engaged them, the present book provides insight into chief currents of international law during the last decades of the twentieth century. Spanning the gap, in some degree, between Anglo-American and continental approaches to international law, the volume consists of short intellectual portraits, combined with interviews, of selected specialists in international law. The interviews were conducted by the editor, Antonio Cassese, between 1993 and 1995 (...)
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  32. Despina Dokoupilova (2013). Creating Legal Subjectivity Through Language and the Uses of the Legal Emblem: Children of Law and the Parenthood of the State. [REVIEW] International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 26 (2):315-339.score: 21.0
    This paper constitutes a critical exploration of the functional features underpinning the unconscious of institutional attachment—namely an attachment which is understood in terms of the subject-infant’s love for his institutional parent-power holder, and the indefinite need for a subject to remain within its infantile condition under the parenthood of the State. We venture beyond the Paternal metaphor and move towards the neglected metaphor of the Mother, so focal in the individual process of identification, assumption of language and the permanent attachment (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  33. René Foqué (2008). Criminal Justice in a Democracy: Towards a Relational Conception of Criminal Law and Punishment. [REVIEW] Criminal Law and Philosophy 2 (3):207-227.score: 21.0
    This article starts from the observation that in classical Athens the discovery of democracy as a normative model of politics has been from the beginning not only a political and a legal but at the same time a philosophical enterprise. Reflections on the concept of criminal law and on the meaning of punishment can greatly benefit from reflections on Athenian democracy as a germ for our contemporary debate on criminal justice in a democracy. Three main characteristics of the Athenian model (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  34. Roger A. Shiner (2009). Theorizing Criminal Law Reform. Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (2):167-186.score: 21.0
    How are we to understand criminal law reform? The idea seems simple—the criminal law on the books is wrong: it should be changed. But 'wrong’ how? By what norms 'wrong’? As soon as one tries to answer those questions, the issue becomes more complex. One kind of answer is that the criminal law is substantively wrong: that is, we assume valid norms of background political morality, and we argue that doctrinally the criminal law on the books does not embody those (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  35. Seth Lazar (2012). The Morality and Law of War. In Andrei Marmor (ed.), Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Law. Routledge.score: 21.0
    The revisionist critique of conventional just war theory has undoubtedly scored some important victories. Walzer’s elegantly unified defense of combatant legal equality and noncombatant immunity has been seriously undermined. This critical success has not, however, been matched by positive arguments, which when applied to the messy reality of war would deprive states and soldiers of the permission to fight wars that are plausibly thought to be justified. The appeal to law that is sought to resolve this objection by casting it (...)
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  36. Anthony Reeves (2014). The Binding Force of Nascent Norms of International Law. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 28 (1):145-166.score: 21.0
    Demonstrating that a developing norm is not yet well established in international law is frequently thought to show that states are not bound by the norm as law. More precisely, showing that a purported international legal norm has only limited support from well-established international legal sources is normally seen as sufficient to rebut an obligation on the part of subjects to comply with the norm in virtue of its legal status. I contend that this view is mistaken. Nascent norms of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  37. Jonathan Witmer-Rich (2011). It's Good to Be Autonomous: Prospective Consent, Retrospective Consent, and the Foundation of Consent in the Criminal Law. [REVIEW] Criminal Law and Philosophy 5 (3):377-398.score: 21.0
    What is the foundation of consent in the criminal law? Classically liberal commentators have offered at least three distinct theories. J.S. Mill contends we value consent because individuals are the best judges of their own interests. Joel Feinberg argues an individual’s consent matters because she has a right to autonomy based on her intrinsic sovereignty over her own life. Joseph Raz also focuses on autonomy, but argues that society values autonomy as a constituent element of individual well-being, which it is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  38. Darryl Brown (2009). History's Challenge to Criminal Law Theory. Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (3):271-287.score: 21.0
    After briefly sketching an historical account of criminal law that emphasizes its longstanding reach into social, commercial and personal life outside the core areas of criminal offenses, this paper explores why criminal law theory has never succeeded in limiting the content of criminal codes to offenses that fit the criteria of dominant theories, particularly versions of the harm principle. Early American writers on criminal law endorsed no such limiting principles to criminal law, and early American criminal law consequently was substantively (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  39. L. Morawski (1999). Law, Fact and Legal Language. Law and Philosophy 18 (5):461-473.score: 21.0
    This paper discusses the difference between the factual and the legal, both as to terms and as to statements, on the analogy of the methodologists' distinction of the observational and the theoretical. No absolute distinction exists, and pure `brute facts' do not exist in law because of the socialisation of physical world and juridification of the social world.; also, the effect of evidentiary constraints. Law/fact distinction depends on `applicability rules'. The problem of `mixed terms' is partly a matter of judicial (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  40. Douglas Husak (2013). The Philosophy of Criminal Law: Extending the Debates. [REVIEW] Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (2):351-365.score: 21.0
    Larry Alexander and Peter Westen each critically examine different topics from my recent collection of essays, The Philosophy of Criminal Law. Alexander focuses on my “Rapes Without Rapists,” “Mistake of Law and Culpability,” and “Already Punished Enough.” Westen offers a more extended commentary on my “Transferred Intent.” I briefly reply to each critic in turn and try to extend the debates in new directions.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  41. Anthony Reeves (2010). The Moral Authority of International Law. APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Law 10 (1):13-18.score: 21.0
    How should international law figure into the practical reasoning of agents who fall under its jurisdiction? How should the existence of an international legal norm regulating some activity affect a subject’s decision-making about that activity? This is a question concerning the general moral authority of international law. It concerns not simply the kind of authority international law claims, but the character of the authority it actually has. An authority, as I will use the term, is moral obligation producing: if x (...)
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  42. Larry Alexander (2009). Facts, Law, Exculpation, and Inculpation: Comments on Simons. Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (3):241-245.score: 21.0
    Orthodox criminal law doctrine treats mistakes of law and mistakes of fact differently for purposes of both exculpation and inculpation. Kenneth Simons’ paper in general defends this orthodoxy. I have earlier criticized the criminal law’s attempt to distinguish mistakes of law from mistakes of fact, and I continue to maintain, in opposition to Simons, that the distinction is problematic.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  43. Andrew Botterell (2013). Review of Douglas Husak, Philosophy of Criminal Law: Selected Essays. [REVIEW] University of Toronto Law Journal 63 (1):152-158.score: 21.0
    A review of Douglas Husak, Philosophy of Criminal Law: Selected Essays (Oxford University Press, 2010).
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  44. Donald A. Dripps (2009). The Priority of Politics and Procedure Over Perfectionism in Penal Law, or, Blackmail in Perspective. Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (3):247-260.score: 21.0
    Criminal law theory concerns itself with the justification of punishment. Conflicting moral theories of punishment will be held in liberal democracies. The positive law therefore neither will nor should reflect exclusively a single moral theory of punishment. Like the institutions for making law, the institutions for enforcing it will cause punishments imposed to deviate from what pure moral theory might prescribe. These claims are illustrated by the debate over blackmail prohibition. The best rationale for prohibition is not the moral argument (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  45. Matthew Lister (2011). The Legitimating Role of Consent in International Law. Chicago Journal of International Law 11 (2).score: 21.0
    According to many traditional accounts, one important difference between international and domestic law is that international law depends on the consent of the relevant parties (states) in a way that domestic law does not. In recent years this traditional account has been attacked both by philosophers such as Allen Buchanan and by lawyers and legal scholars working on international law. It is now safe to say that the view that consent plays an important foundational role in international law is a (...)
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  46. Makoto Usami (2008). Law as Public Policy: Combining Justice with Interest. In Tadeusz Biernat & Marek Zirk-Sadowski (eds.), Politics of Law and Legal Policy: Between Modern and Post-Modern Jurisprudence. Wolters Kluwer Polska. 292--315.score: 21.0
    In newly emerging democracies, succeeding governments have numerous policy tasks for the purpose of developing the free market and the democratic process. In such legal systems, policy-oriented views of law, which regard law as a policy tool for diminishing public problems, seem descriptively pertinent and prescriptively helpful. This is also the case in mature democratic legal systems, where the public problems faced by governments become more and more complex. Policy-directional views of law do not necessarily imply that law is a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  47. Mireille Hildebrandt (2007). European Criminal Law and European Identity. Criminal Law and Philosophy 1 (1):57-78.score: 21.0
    This contribution aims to explain how European Criminal Law can be understood as constitutive of European identity. Instead of starting from European identity as a given, it provides a philosophical analysis of the construction of self-identity in relation to criminal law and legal tradition. The argument will be that the self-identity of those that share jurisdiction depends on and nourishes the legal tradition they adhere to and develop, while criminal jurisdiction is of crucial importance in this process of mutual constitution. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  48. Anél Boshoff (2013). Law and Its Rhetoric of Violence. International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 26 (2):425-437.score: 21.0
    This article explores the manner in which politico-legal language makes use of metaphors of violence and destruction in order to describe state/legal functions and actions. It argues that although such use of a militaristic hyperbole is generally regarded as normal and appropriate, it is in fact harmful in the way that it presents complex and specific problems as being simple and abstract. From a semiotic point of view, and using the work of Roland Barthes, law is regarded as a system (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  49. C. Richmond (1997). Preserving the Identity Crisis: Autonomy, System and Sovereignty in European Law. [REVIEW] Law and Philosophy 16 (4):377-420.score: 21.0
    This article uses Hans Kelsen's theory of a legal system to take a fresh look at European Community law, and the relationship between the European Community, its Member States, and international law. It argues that the basis of the Community's legal legitimacy is indeterminate, and offers a model to accommodate that indeterminacy. This model is founded on a constructivist approach suggested to be particularly useful in the EC context. Using this approach, it is argued that the concepts of system, autonomy (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  50. Trevor Bench-Capon (1997). Argument in Artificial Intelligence and Law. Artificial Intelligence and Law 5 (4):249-261.score: 21.0
    In this paper I shall discuss the notion of argument, and the importanceof argument in AI and Law. I shall distinguish four areas where argument hasbeen applied: in modelling legal reasoning based on cases; in thepresentation and explanation of results from a rule based legal informationsystem; in the resolution of normative conflict and problems ofnon-monotonicity; and as a basis for dialogue games to support the modellingof the process of argument. The study of argument is held to offer prospectsof real progress (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
1 — 50 / 1000