14 found
Order:
See also:
Profile: Noa Latham (University of Calgary)
  1. Noa Latham (2003). Are There Any Nonmotivating Reasons for Action? In Sven Walter & Heinz-Dieter Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation. Imprint Academic 273.
    When performing an action of a certain kind, an agent typically has se- veral reasons for doing so. I shall borrow Davidson’s term and call these rationalising reasons (Davidson 1963, 3). These are reasons that allow us to understand what the agent regarded as favourable features of such an action. (There will also be reasons against acting, expressing unfavour- able features of such an action, from the agent’s point of view.) I shall say that R is a rationalising reason of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  2. Noa Latham (1999). Davidson and Kim on Psychophysical Laws. Synthese 118 (2):121-44.
    Nearly 30 years have passed since Donald Davidson first presented his ar- gument against the possibility of psychophysical laws in “Mental Events”. The argument applies to intentional rather than phenomenal properties, so whenever I refer to mental properties and to psychophysical laws it should be understood that I mean intentional properties and laws relating them to physical properties. No consensus has emerged over what the argument actually is, and the subsequent versions of it presented by Davidson show significant differences. But (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  3.  27
    Noa Latham (2016). Meditation and Self-Control. Philosophical Studies 173 (7):1779-1798.
    This paper seeks to analyse an under-discussed kind of self-control, namely the control of thoughts and sensations. I distinguish first-order control from second-order control and argue that their central forms are intentional concentration and intentional mindfulness respectively. These correspond to two forms of meditation, concentration meditation and mindfulness meditation, which have been regarded as central both in the traditions in which the practices arose and in the scientific literature on meditation. I analyse them in terms of their characteristic intentions, distinguish (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  4. Noa Latham (2011). Are Fundamental Laws Necessary or Contingent? In Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & Matthew H. Slater (eds.), Carving Nature at its Joints. MIT Press 97-112.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  5. Noa Latham (2004). Determinism, Randomness, and Value. Philosophical Topics 32 (1-2):153-167.
    What values, if any, would be undermined by determinism?[i] Traditionally this question has been tackled by asking whether determinism is compatible with free will or whether it is compatible with moral responsibility. Compatibilists say that determinism would not threaten free will or moral responsibility, and hence that people’s values should not be influenced by whether or not they believe in determinism. Incompatibilists say that determinism would undermine free will or moral responsibility, and hence that a belief in determinism should have (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  6. Noa Latham (2003). What is Token Physicalism? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 84 (3):270-290.
    The distinction between token and type physicalism is a familiar feature of discussion of psychophysical relations. Token physicalism, or ontological physicalism, is the view that every token, or particular, in the spatiotemporal world is a physical particular. It is contrasted with type physicalism, or property physicalism -- the view that every first-order type, or property, instantiated in the spatiotemporal world is a physical property. Token physicalism is commonly viewed as a clear thesis, strictly weaker than property physicalism, strictly stronger than (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  7.  74
    Noa Latham (1987). Singular Causal Statements and Strict Deterministic Laws. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 68 (1):29-43.
  8. Noa Latham (2002). Spatiotemporal and Spatial Particulars. Croatian Journal of Philosophy 2 (1):17-35.
    The aim of this paper is to offer a classification of particulars in terms of their relations to spatiotemporal and spatial regions. It begins with an examination of spatiotemporal particulars, and then explores the extent to which a parallel account can be offered of continuants, or spatial particulars that can endure and change over time, assuming such particulars exist. For every spatial particular there are spatiotemporal particulars that can be described as its life and parts thereof. But not every time-slice (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  9.  91
    Noa Latham (1998). Chalmers on the Addition of Consciousness to the Physical World. Philosophical Studies 98 (1):71-97.
  10.  93
    Noa Latham (2001). Substance Physicalism. In Carl Gillett & Barry M. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and its Discontents. Cambridge University Press
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  11.  47
    Noa Latham (1994). Causally Irrelevant Reasons and Action Solely From the Motive of Duty. Journal of Philosophy 91 (11):599-618.
  12.  41
    Noa Latham (2006). Three Compatible Theories of Desire. Dialogue 45 (1):131-138.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  13. Noa Latham (1994). Causally Irrelevant Reasons and Action Solely From the Motive of Duty. Journal of Philosophy 91 (11):599-618.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  14. Noa Latham (1999). Cdd: 12j. 5 the Relevance of Libertarian Freedom. Manuscrito 22:173.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography