Search results for 'Norman Burstein' (try it on Scholar)

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  45
    Norman Burstein (1971). Strawson on the Concept of a Person. Mind 80 (319):449-452.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  2. Norman Burstein (1974). Individuality. Dissertation, New York University
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  3.  4
    Richard Norman (2004). Can There Be a Just War?: Norman Can There Be a Just War? Think 3 (8):7-16.
    Richard Norman examines justifications for war that are rooted in the right of self-defence.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  4.  5
    Lorenzo Imbesi, Bruce Sterling, Donald Norman & Derrick de Kerckhove (2010). Technology, Crisis, and Interaction Design: A Conversation with Bruce Sterling, Donald Norman, and Derrick de Kerckhove. Mediatropes 2 (2):128-135.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  5. Richard Norman (1982). The Primacy of Practice: ‘Intelligent Idealism’ in Marxist Thought1: Richard Norman. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 13:155-179.
    The chief defect of all previous materialism is that things, reality, the sensible world, are conceived only in the form of objects of observation , but not as human sense activity , not as practical activity , not subjectively. Hence, in opposition to materialism, the active side was developed abstractly by idealism, which of course does not know real sense activity as such.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  6.  5
    E. Norman, M. Price, S. Duff & R. Mentzoni (2007). Gradations of Awareness in a Modified Sequence Learning Task. Consciousness and Cognition 16 (4):809-837.
    We argue performance in the serial reaction time task is associated with gradations of awareness that provide examples of fringe consciousness [Mangan, B. . Taking phenomenology seriously: the “fringe” and its implications for cognitive research. Consciousness and Cognition, 2, 89–108, Mangan, B. . The conscious “fringe”: Bringing William James up to date. In B. J. Baars, W. P. Banks & J. B. Newman , Essential sources in the scientific study of consciousness . Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.], and address limitations (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   18 citations  
  7.  24
    Richard Norman (1995). Ethics, Killing, and War. Cambridge University Press.
    Can war ever be justified? Why is it wrong to kill? In this new book Richard Norman looks at these and other related questions, and thereby examines the possibility and nature of rational moral argument. Practical examples, such as the Gulf War and the Falklands War, are used to show that, whilst moral philosophy can offer no easy answers, it is a worthwhile enterprise which sheds light on many pressing contemporary problems. A combination of lucid exposition and original argument (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   14 citations  
  8.  18
    Richard Norman (2004). Can There Be a Just War? Think 3 (8):7.
    Richard Norman examines justifications for war that are rooted in the right of self-defence.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  9.  10
    Richard Norman (2003). Swinburne's Arguments From Design. Think 2 (4):35.
    In issue one, Richard Swinburne presented two ingenious versions of the argument from design. Here, Richard Norman questions both arguments.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  10.  19
    Elisabeth Norman, Mark C. Price, Emma Jones & Zoltan Dienes (2011). Strategic Control in AGL is Not Attributable to Simple Letter Frequencies Alone. Consciousness and Cognition 20 (4):1933-1934.
    In Norman, Price, and Jones , we argued that the ability to apply two sets of grammar rules flexibly from trial to trial on a “mixed-block” AGL classification task indicated strategic control over knowledge that was less than fully explicit. Jiménez suggested that our results do not in themselves prove that participants learned – and strategically controlled – complex properties of the structures of the grammars, but that they may be accounted for by learning of simple letter frequencies. We (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  11.  5
    Richard Norman (1987). Free and Equal: A Philosophical Examination of Political Values. Oxford University Press.
    The concepts of freedom and equality lie at the heart of much contemporary political debate. But how, exactly, are these concepts to be understood? And do they really represent desirable political values? Norman begins from the premise that freedom and equality are rooted in human experience, and thus have a real and objective content. He then argues that the attempt to clarify these concepts is therefore not just a matter of idle philosophical speculation, but also a matter of practical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   6 citations  
  12.  4
    Richard Norman (2004). On Humanism. Routledge.
    humanism /'hju:menizm/ n. an outlook or system of thought concerned with human rather than divine or supernatural matters. Albert Einstein, Isaac Asimov, E.M. Forster, Bertrand Russell, and Gloria Steinem all declared themselves humanists. What is humanism and why does it matter? Is there any doctrine every humanist must hold? If it rejects religion, what does it offer in its place? Have the twentieth century's crimes against humanity spelled the end for humanism? On Humanism is a timely and powerfully argued philosophical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  13.  30
    Richard Norman (2008). Good Without God. Think 7 (20):35-46.
    In the fifth of our articles on , Richard Norman explains why he believes we can be good without God.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  14. Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Judith Norman (eds.) (2001). Nietzsche: Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future. Cambridge University Press.
    Beyond Good and Evil is one of the most scathing and powerful critiques of philosophy, religion, science, politics and ethics ever written. In it, Nietzsche presents a set of problems, criticisms and philosophical challenges that continue both to inspire and to trouble contemporary thought. In addition, he offers his most subtle, detailed and sophisticated account of the virtues, ideas, and practices which will characterize philosophy and philosophers of the future. With his relentlessly energetic style and tirelessly probing manner, Nietzsche embodies (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  15. Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Judith Norman (eds.) (2012). Nietzsche: Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future. Cambridge University Press.
    Beyond Good and Evil is one of the most scathing and powerful critiques of philosophy, religion, science, politics and ethics ever written. In it, Nietzsche presents a set of problems, criticisms and philosophical challenges that continue both to inspire and to trouble contemporary thought. In addition, he offers his most subtle, detailed and sophisticated account of the virtues, ideas, and practices which will characterize philosophy and philosophers of the future. With his relentlessly energetic style and tirelessly probing manner, Nietzsche embodies (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  16. Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Judith Norman (eds.) (2001). Nietzsche: Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future. Cambridge University Press.
    Beyond Good and Evil is one of the most scathing and powerful critiques of philosophy, religion, science, politics and ethics ever written. In it, Nietzsche presents a set of problems, criticisms and philosophical challenges that continue both to inspire and to trouble contemporary thought. In addition, he offers his most subtle, detailed and sophisticated account of the virtues, ideas, and practices which will characterize philosophy and philosophers of the future. With his relentlessly energetic style and tirelessly probing manner, Nietzsche embodies (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  17. Richard Norman (2011). Ethics, Killing and War. Cambridge University Press.
    Can war ever be justified? Why is it wrong to kill? In this new book Richard Norman looks at these and other related questions, and thereby examines the possibility and nature of rational moral argument. Practical examples, such as the Gulf War and the Falklands War, are used to show that, whilst moral philosophy can offer no easy answers, it is a worthwhile enterprise which sheds light on many pressing contemporary problems. A combination of lucid exposition and original argument (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  18. Richard Norman (2012). Ethics, Killing and War. Cambridge University Press.
    Can war ever be justified? Why is it wrong to kill? In this new book Richard Norman looks at these and other related questions, and thereby examines the possibility and nature of rational moral argument. Practical examples, such as the Gulf War and the Falklands War, are used to show that, whilst moral philosophy can offer no easy answers, it is a worthwhile enterprise which sheds light on many pressing contemporary problems. A combination of lucid exposition and original argument (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  19. Richard Norman (2012). On Humanism. Routledge.
    What is humanism and why does it matter? Is there any doctrine every humanist must hold? If it rejects religion, what does it offer in its place? Have the twentieth century’s crimes against humanity spelled the end for humanism? On Humanism is a timely and powerfully argued philosophical defence of humanism. It is also an impassioned plea that we turn to ourselves, not religion, if we want to answer Socrates’ age-old question: what is the best kind of life to lead? (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  20. Richard Norman (2012). On Humanism. Routledge.
    What is humanism and why does it matter? Is there any doctrine every humanist must hold? If it rejects religion, what does it offer in its place? Have the twentieth century’s crimes against humanity spelled the end for humanism? On Humanism is a timely and powerfully argued philosophical defence of humanism. It is also an impassioned plea that we turn to ourselves, not religion, if we want to answer Socrates’ age-old question: what is the best kind of life to lead? (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  21. Richard Norman (2012). On Humanism. Routledge.
    What is humanism and why does it matter? Is there any doctrine every humanist must hold? If it rejects religion, what does it offer in its place? Have the twentieth century’s crimes against humanity spelled the end for humanism? On Humanism is a timely and powerfully argued philosophical defence of humanism. It is also an impassioned plea that we turn to ourselves, not religion, if we want to answer Socrates’ age-old question: what is the best kind of life to lead? (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  22. Elisabeth Norman (2002). Subcategories of "Fringe Consciousness" and Their Related Nonconscious Contexts. Psyche 8 (15).
  23.  21
    Elisabeth Norman, Mark C. Price & Simon C. Duff (2006). Fringe Consciousness in Sequence Learning: The Influence of Individual Differences. Consciousness and Cognition 15 (4):723-760.
    We first describe how the concept of “fringe consciousness” can characterise gradations of consciousness between the extremes of implicit and explicit learning. We then show that the NEO-PI-R personality measure of openness to feelings, chosen to reflect the ability to introspect on fringe feelings, influences both learning and awareness in the serial reaction time task under conditions that have previously been associated with implicit learning . This provides empirical evidence for the proposed phenomenology and functional role of fringe consciousness in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   18 citations  
  24. Jianhui Zhang & Donald A. Norman (1994). Representations in Distributed Cognitive Tasks. Cognitive Science 18 (1):87-122.
  25.  6
    Nancie Fimbel & Jerome S. Burstein (1990). Defining the Ethical Standards of the High-Technology Industry. Journal of Business Ethics 9 (12):929 - 948.
    At least five sets of ethical standards influence business people's decisions: general cultural, company, personal, situational, and industry standards. Each has an official or espoused form encoded in written documents such as policy statements and codes of ethics and an unofficial form that develops as people use the espoused standards. (We call these unofficial standards values in action.) To determine whether the high-technology industry deserves its reputation for moral laxness, a pilot questionnaire was designed. It asked employees to rate the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   4 citations  
  26.  20
    Robert Norman (1970). Ryle on 'the Problem of the Self'. Philosophical Studies 19:220-235.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  27.  25
    Matthew Burstein (2007). Taking As: Experience & Judgment in the Life of Agents. Philosophical Explorations 10 (3):227 – 243.
    Although appearances may deceive them, agents are capable of achieving their ends; this success is frequently explained by the fact that the agents may, for example, see a stick in water as bent without believing that it is actually bent. Although the notion of 'seeing as' is supposed to both bridge the gap between experience and action and explain our reaction to illusions, such accounts break down because of their exclusive focus on visual episodes and their tendency to interpret the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  28.  21
    Alister Browne, Vincent P. Sweeney & Margaret G. Norman (1996). Ethics Committee Education: Report on a Canadian Project. [REVIEW] HEC Forum 8 (5):290-300.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  29.  35
    Joseph Lacey (2012). Climate Change and Norman Daniels' Theory of Just Health: An Essay on Basic Needs. [REVIEW] Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 15 (1):3-14.
    Norman Daniels, in applying Rawls’ theory of justice to the issue of human health, ideally presupposes that society exists in a state of moderate scarcity. However, faced with problems like climate change, many societies find that their state of moderate scarcity is increasingly under threat. The first part of this essay aims to determine the consequences for Daniels’ theory of just health when we incorporate into Rawls’ understanding of justice the idea that the condition of moderate scarcity can fail. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  30. Friedrich Hügel, Norman Kemp Smith & Lawrence F. Barmann (1981). The Letters of Baron Friedrich von Hügel and Professor Norman Kemp Smith. Monograph Collection (Matt - Pseudo).
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  31.  64
    Ludwig Wittgenstein, G. E. Moore, Norman Malcolm & Gabriel Citron (2015). A Discussion Between Wittgenstein and Moore on Certainty : From the Notes of Norman Malcolm. Mind 124 (493):73-84.
    In April 1939, G. E. Moore read a paper to the Cambridge University Moral Science Club entitled ‘Certainty’. In it, amongst other things, Moore made the claims that: the phrase ‘it is certain’ could be used with sense-experience-statements, such as ‘I have a pain’, to make statements such as ‘It is certain that I have a pain’; and that sense-experience-statements can be said to be certain in the same sense as some material-thing-statements can be — namely in the sense that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  32. Andrew Crane & Dirk Matten (2008). Incorporating the Corporation in Citizenship: A Response to Néron and Norman. Business Ethics Quarterly 18 (1):27-33.
    This article presents a response to Néron and Norman’s contention that the language of citizenship is helpful in thinking about the political dimensions of corporate responsibilities. We argue that Néron and Norman’s main conclusions are valid but offer an extension of their analysis to incorporate extant streams of literature dealing with the political role of the corporation. We also propose that the perspective on citizenship adopted by Néron and Norman is rather narrow, andtherefore provide some alternative ways (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   9 citations  
  33.  9
    Harmen Ghijsen (2016). Norman and Truetemp Revisited Reliabilistically: A Proper Functionalist Defeat Account of Clairvoyance. Episteme 13 (1):89-110.
    The cases of Norman the Clairvoyant and Mr. Truetemp form classic counterexamples to the process reliabilist's claim that reliability is sufficient for prima facie justification. I discuss several ways in which contemporary reliabilists have tried to deal with these counterexamples, and argue that they are all unsuccessful. Instead, I propose that the most promising route lies with an appeal to a specific kind of higher-order defeat that is best cashed out in terms of properly functioning monitoring mechanisms.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  34.  11
    Kristjan Laasik (2015). Norman Sieroka: Leibniz, Husserl, and the Brain. [REVIEW] Phenomenological Reviews.
    Norman Sieroka’s book is about “the systematic, structural relations between phenomenological and (neuro)physiological aspects of perception, consciousness, and time, with a specific focus on hearing” (p. 4), based on Leibniz’s and Husserl’s views. While Sieroka displays a great depth of knowledge in his discussions of these two philosophers, his main aims are not exegetic, but consist, rather, in casting new light on the said philosophical and interdisciplinary issues. However, the scope of his interpretative project is ambitious. There is, on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  35.  20
    Qiufang Fu, Zoltán Dienes & Xiaolan Fu (2010). The Distinction Between Intuition and Guessing in the SRT Task Generation: A Reply to Norman and Price. Consciousness and Cognition 19 (1):478-480.
    We investigated the extent to which people could generate sequences of responses based on knowledge acquired from the Serial Reaction Time task, depending on whether it felt subjectively like the response was based on pure guessing, intuition, conscious rules or memories. Norman and Price argued that in the context of our task, intuition responses were the same as guessing responses. In reply, we argue that not only do subjects apparently claim to be experiencing different phenomenologies when saying intuition versus (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  36.  13
    Eleonore Stump & Norman Kretzmann (eds.) (1993). Reasoned Faith: Essays in Philosophical Theology in Honor of Norman Kretzmann. Cornell University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   8 citations  
  37.  11
    T. M. Wilkinson (2008). Norman Daniels. Just Health. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008. 397 + Ix Pp. Public Health Ethics 1 (3):phn028.
    Just Health, by the well-known American philosopher Norman Daniels, has the ambitious goal of presenting `an integrated theory of justice and population health, to address a set of theoretical and real-world challenges to that theory, and to demonstrate that the theory can guide our practice with regard to health both here and abroad.’ (1)1 Daniels's fundamental question is what we owe each other in the way of the protection and promotion of health. He thinks this is fruitfully dealt with (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  38.  77
    Michele Loi, What Concept of Disease Should Politicians Use? Norman Daniels and the Unjustifiable Appeal of Naturalistic Analyses of Health.
    Norman Daniels argues that health is important for justice because it affects the distribution of opportunities. He claims that a just society should guarantee fair opportunities by promoting and restoring the “normal functioning” of its citizens, that is, their health. The scope of citizens' mutual obligations with respect to health is defined by a reasonable agreement that, according to Daniels, should be based on the distinction between normal functioning and pathology drawn by the biomedical sciences. This paper deals with (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  39.  25
    Andrew C. Wicks (1990). Norman Bowie and Richard Rorty on Multinationals: Does Business Ethics Need 'Metaphysical Comfort?'. [REVIEW] Journal of Business Ethics 9 (3):191 - 200.
    Norman Bowie wrote an article on the moral obligations of multinational corporations in 1987. This paper is a response to Bowie, but more importantly, it is designed to articulate the force and substance of the pragmatist philosophy developed by Richard Rorty. In his article, Bowie suggested that moral universalism (which he endorses) is the only credible method of doing business ethics across cultures and that cultural relativism and ethnocentrism are not. Bowie, in a manner surprisingly common among contemporary philosophers, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   6 citations  
  40.  53
    John F. Wippel (2003). Norman Kretzmann on Aquinas's Attribution of Will and of Freedom to Create to God. Religious Studies 39 (3):287-298.
    The purpose of this paper is to discuss Norman Kretzmann's account of Aquinas's discussion of will in God. According to Kretzmann, Aquinas's reasoning seems to leave no place for choice on God's part, since, on Aquinas's account, God is not free not to will Himself. And so this leads to the problem about God's willing things other than Himself. On this, Kretzmann finds serious problems with Thomas's position. Kretzmann argues that Aquinas should have drawn necessitarian conclusions from his account (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  41.  8
    Bruce R. O'Brien (1996). From Morðor to Murdrum: The Preconquest Origin and Norman Revival of the Murder Fine. Speculum 71 (2):321-357.
    What was the English opinion of the Normans who had conquered them in 1066? Perhaps it makes better sense to ask, What did they see when they beheld one of their new Norman lords? Were the Normans seen as oppressive? If so, in what way and with what result? Can it be said that the Normans' treatment of their new subjects was any different from the treatment ceorlas had received from eorlas and thegnas before 1066? There can be no (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  42.  14
    T. M. Wilkinson (2008). Norman Daniels. Just Health. Public Health Ethics 1 (3):268-272.
    Just Health, by the well-known American philosopher Norman Daniels, has the ambitious goal of presenting ‘an integrated theory of justice and population health, to address a set of theoretical and real-world challenges to that theory, and to demonstrate that the theory can guide our practice with regard to health both here and abroad.’ (1)1 Daniels's fundamental question is what we owe each other in the way of the protection and promotion of health. He thinks this is fruitfully dealt with (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  43.  18
    S. Brauer (2009). Age Rationing and Prudential Lifespan Account in Norman Daniels' Just Health. Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (1):27-31.
    Could age be a valid criterion for rationing? In Just health, Norman Daniels argues that under certain circumstances age rationing is prudent, and therefore a morally permissible strategy to tackle the problem of resource scarcity. Crucial to his argument is the distinction between two problem-settings of intergenerational equity: equity among age groups and equity among birth cohorts. While fairness between age groups can involve unequal benefit treatment in different life stages, fairness between birth cohorts implies enjoying approximate equality in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  44.  41
    Matt Lamkin (2011). Racist Appearance Standards and the Enhancements That Love Them: Norman Daniels and Skin-Lightening Cosmetics. Bioethics 25 (4):185-191.
    Darker skin correlates with reduced opportunities and negative health outcomes. Recent discoveries related to the genes associated with skin tone, and the historical use of cosmetics to conform to racist appearance standards, suggest effective skin-lightening products may soon become available. This article examines whether medical interventions of this sort should be permitted, subsidized, or restricted, using Norman Daniels's framework for determining what justice requires in terms of protecting health. I argue that Daniels's expansive view of the requirements of justice (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  45.  7
    C. W. Freeman (1996). What Shall We Do with Norman? An Experiment in Communal Discernment. Christian Bioethics 2 (1):16-41.
    We were a group of Christian friends searching for affirmations that lay at the heart of our faith and reached to the limits of our existence and moral authority. As we have reflected on our role in deciding whether and to what extent we could assist in allowing our terminally ill friend, seventy-nine-year-old, Norman to die, we were deeply troubled by the moral ambiguity of our involvement. Through a careful process of authority through communal discernment, our responsibility for (...) became clear: we were to assist him in living the life he embraced in baptism — a life which included a destiny that was conformed to the crucified and risen one. That was not the destiny we chose for Norman; it was the destiny he owned. We recognized with Norman that our lives are not our own to be guided by autonomy and liberty, but rather to be lived for the glory of Jesus the Christ. (shrink)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  46.  12
    Constance B. Hieatt & Robin F. Jones (1986). Two Anglo-Norman Culinary Collections Edited From British Library Manuscripts Additional 32085 and Royal 12.C.Xii. Speculum 61 (4):859-882.
    The earliest English culinary recipes occur in two Anglo-Norman manuscripts, both in the British Library: Additional 32085 and Royal 12.C.xii. A transcription of the latter, with a few footnotes citing recipes in the former, was published by Paul Meyer in 1893 . Meyer proposed to publish a full version of the earlier manuscript at a later date, but he never did. No new Anglo-Norman collections have turned up since that time, although we have searched in a great number (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  47.  19
    Norman Kretzmann, Scott MacDonald & Eleonore Stump (eds.) (1998). Aquinas's Moral Theory: Essays in Honor of Norman Kretzmann. Cornell University Press.
    This volume explores the ethical dimensions of a wide selection of philosophical and theological topics in Aquinas's texts.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  48.  20
    T. Wilkinson (2008). Norman Daniels. Just Health. Public Health Ethics 1 (3):268-272.
    Just Health, by the well-known American philosopher Norman Daniels, has the ambitious goal of presenting ‘an integrated theory of justice and population health, to address a set of theoretical and real-world challenges to that theory, and to demonstrate that the theory can guide our practice with regard to health both here and abroad.’ (1)1 Daniels's fundamental question is what we owe each other in the way of the protection and promotion of health. He thinks this is fruitfully dealt with (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  49.  21
    F. Janet (2007). Review of J. Norman, After Euclid: Visual Reasoning and the Epistemology of Diagrams. [REVIEW] Philosophia Mathematica 15 (1):116-121.
    This monograph treats the important topic of the epistemology of diagrams in Euclidean geometry. Norman argues that diagrams play a genuine justificatory role in traditional Euclidean arguments, and he aims to account for these roles from a modified Kantian perspective. Norman considers himself a semi-Kantian in the following broad sense: he believes that Kant was right that ostensive constructions are necessary in order to follow traditional Euclidean proofs, but he wants to avoid appealing to Kantian a priori intuition (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  50.  15
    Dennis Mckerlie (1989). Justice Between Age-Groups: A Comment on Norman Daniels. Journal of Applied Philosophy 6 (2):227-234.
    ABSTRACT Norman Daniels suggests that the just distribution of resources between different age‐groups is determined by the choice a prudential agent would make in budgeting resources over the different temporal stages of a single life. He calls this view the “prudential lifespan account” of justice between age‐groups. Daniels thinks that the view recommends a rough kind of equality in resources between age‐groups. I argue that in the case of a single life prudence would choose an unequal distribution of resources. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000