Order:
Disambiguations
David Owens [51]D. Alfred Owens [4]David J. Owens [2]David John Owens [2]
Derek Owens [1]D. Owens [1]Dewi W. Owens [1]David C. Owens [1]

Not all matches are shown. Search with initial or firstname to single out others.

See also
David Owens
King's College London
  1. Shaping the Normative Landscape.David Owens - 2012 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Shaping the Normative Landscape is an investigation of the value of obligations and of rights, of forgiveness, of consent and refusal, of promise and request. David Owens shows that these are all instruments by which we exercise control over our normative environment.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  2. Reason Without Freedom: The Problem of Epistemic Normativity.David Owens - 2000 - New York: Routledge.
    We call beliefs reasonable or unreasonable, justified or unjustified. What does this imply about belief? Does this imply that we are responsible for our beliefs and that we should be blamed for our unreasonable convictions? Or does it imply that we are in control of our beliefs and that what we believe is up to us? Reason Without Freedom argues that the major problems of epistemology have their roots in concerns about our control over and responsibility for belief. David Owens (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  3. Does belief have an aim?David John Owens - 2003 - Philosophical Studies 115 (3):283-305.
    The hypothesis that belief aims at the truth has been used to explain three features of belief: (1) the fact that correct beliefs are true beliefs, (2) the fact that rational beliefs are supported by the evidence and (3) the fact that we cannot form beliefs.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  4. Testimony and Assertion.David Owens - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 130 (1):105-129.
    Two models of assertion are described and their epistemological implications considered. The assurance model draws a parallel between the ethical norms surrounding promising and the epistemic norms which facilitate the transmission of testimonial knowledge. This model is rejected in favour of the view that assertion transmits knowledge by expressing belief. I go on to compare the epistemology of testimony with the epistemology of memory.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  5. Epistemic Akrasia.David Owens - 2002 - The Monist 85 (3):381-397.
    One way of discerning what sort of control we have over our mental lives is to look at cases where that control is not exercised. This is one reason why philosophers have taken an interest in the phenomenon of akrasia, in an agent's ability to do, freely and deliberately, something that they judge they ought not to do. Akrasia constitutes a failure of control but not an absence of control. The akratic agent is not a compulsive; an akratic agent has (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  6. A simple theory of promising.David Owens - 2006 - Philosophical Review 115 (1):51-77.
    Why do human beings make and accept promises? What human interest is served by this procedure? Many hold that promising serves what I shall call an information interest, an interest in information about what will happen. And they hold that human beings ought to keep their promises because breaches of promise threaten this interest. On this view human beings take promises seriously because we want correct information about how other human beings are going to act. Some such view is taken (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  7.  68
    Causes and Coincidences.David Owens - 1992 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    In an important departure from theories of causation, David Owens proposes that coincidences have no causes, and that a cause is something which ensures that its effects are no coincidence. In Causes and Coincidences, he elucidates the idea of a coincidence as an event which can be analysed into constituent events, the nomological antecedents of which are independent of each other. He also suggests that causal facts can be analysed in terms of non-causal facts, including relations of necessity. Thus, causation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  8.  29
    A Simple Theory of Promising.David Owens - 2006 - Philosophical Review 115 (1):51-77.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  9.  25
    Causes and Coincidences.David Owens - 1990 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90 (1):49-64.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  10. Promising without Intending.David Owens - 2008 - Journal of Philosophy 105 (12):737-755.
    It is widely held that one who sincerely promises to do something must at least intend to do that thing: a promise communicates the intention to perform. In this paper, I argue that a promise need only communicate the intention to undertake an obligation to perform. I consider examples of sincere promisors who have no intention of performing. I argue that this fits well with what we want to say about other performatives - giving, commanding etc. Furthermore, it supports a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  11. The possibility of consent.David Owens - 2011 - Ratio 24 (4):402-421.
    Worries about the possibility of consent recall a more familiar problem about promising raised by Hume. To see the parallel here we must distinguish the power of consent from the normative significance of choice. I'll argue that we have normative interests, interests in being able to control the rights and obligations of ourselves and those around us, interests distinct from our interest in controlling the non-normative situation. Choice gets its normative significance from our non-normative control interests. By contrast, the possibility (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  12. Levels of explanation.David Owens - 1989 - Mind 98 (389):59-79.
  13. Duress, deception, and the validity of a promise.David Owens - 2007 - Mind 116 (462):293-315.
    An invalid promise is one whose breach does not wrong the promisee. I describe two different accounts of why duress and deception invalidate promises. According to the fault account duress and deception invalidate a promise just when it was wrong for the promisee to induce the promisor to promise in that way. According to the injury account, duress and deception invalidate a promise just when by inducing the promise in that way the promisee wrongs the promisor. I demonstrate that the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  14.  61
    Habitual agency.David Owens - 2017 - Philosophical Explorations 20 (sup2):93-108.
    It is often maintained that practical freedom is a capacity to act on our view of what we ought to do and in particular on our view of what it would be best to do. Here, I discuss an important exception to that claim, namely habitual agency. Acting out of habit is widely regarded as a form of reflex or even as compulsive behaviour but much habitual agency is both intentional and free. Still it is true that, in so far (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15. Deliberation and the first person.David Owens - 2008 - In Anthony Hatzimoysis (ed.), Self-Knowledge. Oxford University Press. pp. 261-277.
    Philosophers like Shoemaker and Burge argue that only self-conscious creatures can exercise rational control over their mental lives. In particular they urge that reflective rationality requires possession of the I-concept, the first person concept. These philosophers maintain that rational creatures like ourselves can exercise reflective control over belief as well as action. I agree that we have this sort of control over our actions and that practical freedom presupposes self-consciousness. But I deny that anything like this is true of belief.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  16.  16
    Normativity and Control.David J. Owens - 2017 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Do we control what we believe? Are we responsible for what we believe? In a series of ten essays David Owens explores various different forms of control we might have over belief, and the different forms of responsibility these forms of control generate.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17. A Lockean theory of memory experience.David Owens - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2):319-32.
    The paper aims to provide an account of the phenomenological differences between perception, recognition and recall. In the first section, recall is distinguished from non-experiential forms of memory. In the second section, it is argued that we can't distinguish perceptual experience from the experience of recall by means of perception's present tense content because it is possible to perceive as well as to recall the past. The Lockean theory of recall as a revival of previous perceptual experience is then introduced, (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  18.  64
    Wrong by Convention.David Owens - 2017 - Ethics 127 (3):553-575.
    Some acts (mala in se) are wrong prior to any social prohibition (e.g., murder). Other acts (mala prohibita) are wrong only once socially prohibited (e.g., traffic violations). This article considers certain obligations of care that parents owe to their children and children to their parents. Violations of these familial obligations are like paradigm mala prohibita in that they are wrongs created by social convention. But, it is argued, they are unlike paradigm mala prohibita in that their prohibition is not justified (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19.  50
    Disjunctive Laws?David Owens - 1989 - Analysis 49 (4):197-202.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  20. Rationalism about Obligation.David Owens - 2008 - European Journal of Philosophy 16 (3):403-431.
    In our thinking about what to do, we consider reasons which count for or against various courses of action. That having a glass of wine with dinner would be pleasant and make me sociable recommends the wine. That it will disturb my sleep and inhibit this evening’s work counts against it. I determine what I ought to do by weighing these considerations and deciding what would be best all things considered. A practical reason makes sense of a course of action (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  21. Self-Knowledge, Externalism, and Skepticism.Brian Mclaughlin & David Owens - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (74):93-142.
    In recent years, some philosophers have claimed that we can know a priori that certain external world skeptical hypotheses are false on the basis of a priori knowledge that we are in certain kinds of mental states, and a priori knowledge that those mental states are individuated by contingent environmental factors. Appealing to a distinction between weak and strong a priority, I argue that weakly a priori arguments of this sort would beg the question of whether the skeptical hypothesis under (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22.  89
    The Value of Duty.David Owens - 2012 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 86 (1):199-215.
    The obligations we owe to those with whom we share a valuable relationship (like friendship) cannot be reduced to the obligations we owe to others simply as fellow persons (e.g. the duty to reciprocate benefits received). Wallace suggests that this is because such valuable relationships are loving relationships. I instead propose that it is because, unlike general moral obligations, such valuable relationships (and their constitutive obligations) serve our normative interests. Part of what makes friendship good for us is that it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23. Promises and Conflicting Obligations.David Owens - 2016 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 11 (1):93-108.
    This paper addresses two questions. First can a binding promise conflict with other binding promises and thereby generate conflicting obligations? Second can binding promises conflict with other non-promissory obligations, so that we are obliged to keep so-called ‘wicked promises’? The answer to both questions is ‘yes’. The discussion examines both ‘natural right’ and ‘social practice’ approaches to promissory obligation and I conclude that neither can explain why we should be unable to make binding promises that conflict with our prior obligations. (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  47
    Freedom and practical judgement.David Owens - 2009 - In Lucy O'Brien & Matthew Soteriou (eds.), Mental actions. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 122-137.
    Unlike many other animals, human beings enjoy freedom of action. They are capable of acting freely because they have certain psychological capacities which other animals lack. In this paper, I argue that the crucial capacity here is our ability to make practical judgements; to make judgements about what we ought to do. A number of other writers share this view but they treat practical judgement as a form of belief. Since, as I argue, we don't control our beliefs, that undermines (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  25.  19
    Self-Knowledge, Externalism, and Skepticism.Brian P. Mclaughlin & David Owens - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74:93-142.
    [Brian P. McLaughlin] In recent years, some philosophers have claimed that we can know a priori that certain external world skeptical hypotheses are false on the basis of a priori knowledge that we are in certain kinds of mental states, and a priori knowledge that those mental states are individuated by contingent environmental factors. Appealing to a distinction between weak and strong a priority, I argue that weakly a priori arguments of this sort would beg the question of whether the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  26.  41
    Does a Promise Transfer a Right?David Owens - 2014 - In George Letsas, Prince Saprai & Gregory Klass (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Contract Law. Oxford University Press. pp. 78-95.
    A number of authors from Grotius onwards have proposed that a binding promise transfers a right from promisor to promisee. The promisee now has the right, previously possessed by the promisor, to determine whether the promisor performs the act mentioned in their promise. This proposal runs into problems of detail. The chapter first reformulates the theory so as to avoid these problems. It then considers a more fundamental difficulty raised by Hume and argues that the reformulated theory succumbs to Hume’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  27.  46
    Property and Authority.David Owens - 2019 - Journal of Political Philosophy 27 (3):271-293.
    Journal of Political Philosophy, EarlyView.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  93
    The authority of memory.David Owens - 1999 - European Journal of Philosophy 7 (3):312-329.
  29.  17
    Rationalism about Obligation.David Owens - 2008 - European Journal of Philosophy 16 (3):403-431.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30. Disenchantment.David Owens - 2010 - In Louise M. Antony (ed.), Philosophers Without Gods: Meditations on Atheism and the Secular Life. Oup Usa.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  31.  44
    II—David Owens: The Value of Duty.David Owens - 2012 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 86 (1):199-215.
    The obligations we owe to those with whom we share a valuable relationship (like friendship) cannot be reduced to the obligations we owe to others simply as fellow persons (e.g. the duty to reciprocate benefits received). Wallace suggests that this is because such valuable relationships are loving relationships. I instead propose that it is because, unlike general moral obligations, such valuable relationships (and their constitutive obligations) serve our normative interests. Part of what makes friendship good for us is that it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  30
    Shiffrin on Coerced Promises.David Owens - forthcoming - Mind.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  8
    Individual differences in analytical thinking and complexity of inference in conditional reasoning.Robert B. Ricco, Hideya Koshino, Anthony Nelson Sierra, Jasmine Bonsel, Jay Von Monteza & Da’Nae Owens - forthcoming - Thinking and Reasoning:1-31.
    An outstanding question for Hybrid dual process models of reasoning is whether both basic and more complex forms of conditional inference result...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  24
    II—David Owens: The Value of Duty.David Owens - 2012 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 86 (1):199-215.
    The obligations we owe to those with whom we share a valuable relationship (like friendship) cannot be reduced to the obligations we owe to others simply as fellow persons (e.g. the duty to reciprocate benefits received). Wallace suggests that this is because such valuable relationships are loving relationships. I instead propose that it is because, unlike general moral obligations, such valuable relationships (and their constitutive obligations) serve our normative interests. Part of what makes friendship good for us is that it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. Knowing your own mind.David Owens - 2003 - Dialogue 42 (4):791-798.
    What is it to “know your own mind”? In ordinary English, this phrase connotes clear headed decisiveness and a firm resolve but in the language of contemporary philosophy, the indecisive and the susceptible can know their own minds just as well as anybody else. In the philosopher’s usage, “knowing your own mind” is just a matter of being able to produce a knowledgeable description of your mental state, whether it be a state of indecision, susceptibility or even confusion. What exercises (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36.  98
    The problem with promising.David Owens - 2011 - In H. Sheinman (ed.), Promises and Agreements: Philosophical Essays. pp. 58-79.
    Why have philosophers since Hume regarded promising as problematic? I distinguish two problems raised by Hume. The problem of the bare wrong is the problem of how it can make sense to avoid a wrong when the wrong does not affect any intelligible human interest. The problem of normative power is the problem of how something can be a wrong simply because it has been declared to be a wrong. I argue that the problem of the bare wrong is more (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37.  47
    Should Blackmail Be Banned?David Owens - 1988 - Philosophy 63 (246):501-514.
    There is no right to blackmail. So says the law and so say most moral observers. A few libertarian voices have been raised in defence of blackmail but such a defence is liable to be treated as a reductio of the defender's own free market philosophy. However, it is surprisingly difficult to say just what is wrong with blackmail.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  20
    Exploring the Complexity of Students’ Scientific Explanations and Associated Nature of Science Views Within a Place-Based Socioscientific Issue Context.Benjamin C. Herman, David C. Owens, Robert T. Oertli, Laura A. Zangori & Mark H. Newton - 2019 - Science & Education 28 (3-5):329-366.
    In addition to considering sociocultural, political, economic, and ethical factors, effectively engaging socioscientific issues requires that students understand and apply scientific explanations and the nature of science. Promoting such understandings can be achieved through immersing students in authentic real-world contexts where the SSI impacts occur and teaching those students about how scientists comprehend, research, and debate those SSI. This triangulated mixed-methods investigation explored how 60 secondary students’ trophic cascade explanations changed through their experiencing place-based SSI instruction focused on the Yellowstone (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  25
    From the business ethics course to the sustainable curriculum.Derek Owens - 1998 - Journal of Business Ethics 17 (15):1765 - 1777.
    Universities want to prepare students intellectually so that they might eventually find successful, fulfilling work. Since work is synonymous with business – no work ever exists outside of business – one of the academy's primary goals is to help students enter the world of business, regardless of their majors. Many universities also declare within their mission statements a desire to cultivate a student body capable of making ethically informed decisions. Consequently we might conceptualize "business ethics" as not simply one field (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  34
    Seeing where we look: Fixation as extraretinal information.D. Alfred Owens & Edward S. Reed - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):271-272.
  41.  48
    Publishing web‐based guidelines using interactive decision models.Gillian D. Sanders, Robert F. Nease & Douglas K. Owens - 2001 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 7 (2):175-189.
  42. Ramsey 311,314 Rembrandt 388 Rosenberg, Alexander xxi Ross, WD. 274.Nathan Salmon, Andrew Melnyk, Trenton Merricks, John Stuart Mill, Matt Millen, Ruth G. Millikan, Piet Mondrian, Isaac Newton, David Owens & David Papineau - 2002 - In Jaegwon Kim (ed.), Supervenience. Ashgate. pp. 397.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  18
    Self-knowledge, Externalism and Scepticism, II.David Owens - 2000 - Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74 (1):119-142.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  8
    The Possibility of Consent.David Owens - 2012 - In Brad Hooker (ed.), Developing Deontology. Malden, MA: Wiley. pp. 53–72.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Problem of Normative Power Consent and Choice Promise, Consent and Normative Interests Permissive Interests.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  46
    The Moral Nexus, by R. Jay Wallace.David Owens - 2022 - Mind 131 (521):277-284.
    _ The Moral Nexus _, by WallaceR. Jay. Princeton N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2019. Pp. xiii + 306.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  11
    Bound by convention: obligation and social rules.David Owens - 2022 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    How should we assess the social structures that govern human conduct and settle whether we are bound by their rules? One approach is to ask whether those social arrangements reflect pre-conventional facts about our nature. If they do, compliance will serve our interests because these rules are not just conventions. Another approach is to ask whether following a convention has desirable consequences. For example, the rule which makes the dollar bill legal tender is a convention and the great usefulness of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  11
    Critical Notice: Mental Content by Colin McGinn.David Owens - 1990 - Mind 99 (393):113-122.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  28
    Descartes's Use of Doubt.David Owens - 2007 - In Janet Broughton & John Carriero (eds.), A Companion to Descartes. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 164–178.
    This chapter contains section titled: The Role of Reflection The Need for Certainty Descartes's Conjectures Descartes's Suppositions Note References and Further Reading.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Externalis, Davidson, and knowledge of comparative content.David J. Owens - 2003 - In Susana Nuccetelli (ed.), New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge. MIT Press.
  50.  23
    Effects of luminance, blur, and age on nighttime visual guidance: A test of the selective degradation hypothesis.D. Alfred Owens & Richard A. Tyrrell - 1999 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 5 (2):115.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 64