Search results for 'Richmond A. Thomason' (try it on Scholar)

155 found
Order:
  1.  31
    Richmond H. Thomason (1980). A Model Theory for Propositional Attitudes. Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (1):47 - 70.
    My chief aim has been to convey the thought that the application of model theoretic techniques to natural languages needn't force a distortion of intentional phenomena. I hope that at least I have succeeded in accomplishing this.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   17 citations  
  2.  14
    Richmond H. Thomason & Matthew Stone, Enlightened Update: A Computational Architecture for Presupposition and Other Pragmatic Phenomena.
    We relate the theory of presupposition accommodation to a computational framework for reasoning in conversation. We understand presuppositions as private commitments the speaker makes in using an utterance but expects the listener to recognize based on mutual information. On this understanding, the conversation can move forward not just through the positive effects of interlocutors’ utterances but also from the retrospective insight interlocutors gain about one anothers’ mental states from observing what they do. Our title, ENLIGHTENED UPDATE, highlights such cases. Our (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  3.  15
    Richmond H. Thomason & John F. Horty, A Clash of Intuitions: The Current State of Nonmonotonic Multiple Inheritance Systems.
    Early attempts at combining multiple inheritance with nonmonotonic reasoning were based on straightforward extensions of tree-structured inheritance systems, and were theoretically unsound. In The Mathcmat~'cs of Inheritance Systcrns, or TMOIS, Touretzky described two problems these systems cannot handle: reasoning in the presence of true but redundant assertions, and coping with ambiguity. TMOIS provided a definition and analysis of a theoretically sound multiple inheritance system, accom-.
    Translate
      Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  4. Richmond A. Thomason (1981). Deontic Logic and the Role of Freedom in Moral Deliberation. In Risto Hilpinen (ed.), New Studies in Deontic Logic.
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  5.  73
    Robert C. Stalnaker & Richmond H. Thomason (1970). A Semantic Analysis of Conditional Logic. Theoria 36 (1):23-42.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   27 citations  
  6.  18
    Richmond H. Thomason (1980). A Note on Syntactical Treatments of Modality. Synthese 44 (3):391 - 395.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   11 citations  
  7.  49
    Richmond Thomason & Anil Gupta (1980). A Theory of Conditionals in the Context of Branching Time. Philosophical Review 89 (1):65-90.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   9 citations  
  8.  1
    Richmond H. Thomason (1969). A Semantical Study of Constructible Falsity. Mathematical Logic Quarterly 15 (16‐18):247-257.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   5 citations  
  9. Richmond H. Thomason (1970). A Fitch-Style Formulation of Conditional Logic. Logique Et Analyse 52:397-412.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   4 citations  
  10.  5
    Richmond H. Thomason (1967). A Decision Procedure for Fitch's Propositional Calculus. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 8 (1-2):101-117.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  11.  19
    Richmond H. Thomason, Progress Towards a Formal Theory of Practical Reasoning: Problems and Prospects.
    From its beginnings in Aristotle, logic was intended to account not only for reasoning that is theoretical (or conclusion-oriented), but for reasoning that is practical (or actionoriented). However, despite an interest in the topic that continues to the present, the practical side of reasoning has remained broadly speculative. At least in some domains (mathematics, in particular), there are well developed proof-theoretic and semantic theories that yield quite detailed models of correct reasoning, and these models are useful for both theoretical and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  12.  3
    Richmond Thomason (1967). Review: Dag Prawitz, Natural Deduction. A Proof-Theoretical Study. [REVIEW] Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2):255-256.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  13.  10
    Nuel D. Belnap & Richmond H. Thomason (1963). A Rule-Completeness Theorem. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 4 (1):39-43.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  14.  1
    Jaime G. Carbonell, David A. Evans, Dana S. Scott & Richmond H. Thomason, Final Report on the Automated Classification and Retrieval Project : MedSORT-1.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  15.  1
    Richmond H. Thomason (1984). Review: Jon Barwise, Scenes and Other Situations; Jon Barwise, John Perry, Situations and Attitudes; Jon Barwise, John Perry, Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Howard K. Wettstein, Semantic Innocence and Uncompromising Situations. [REVIEW] Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1403-1406.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  16.  53
    Catharine Saint Croix & Richmond Thomason (2014). Chisholm's Paradox and Conditional Oughts. Lecture Notes in Computer Science 8554:192-207.
    Since it was presented in 1963, Chisholm’s paradox has attracted constant attention in the deontic logic literature, but without the emergence of any definitive solution. We claim this is due to its having no single solution. The paradox actually presents many challenges to the formalization of deontic statements, including (1) context sensitivity of unconditional oughts, (2) formalizing conditional oughts, and (3) distinguishing generic from nongeneric oughts. Using the practical interpretation of ‘ought’ as a guideline, we propose a linguistically motivated logical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  17.  74
    Dustin Tucker & Richmond H. Thomason (2011). Paradoxes of Intensionality. Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):394-411.
    We identify a class of paradoxes that is neither set-theoretical nor semantical, but that seems to depend on intensionality. In particular, these paradoxes arise out of plausible properties of propositional attitudes and their objects. We try to explain why logicians have neglected these paradoxes, and to show that, like the Russell Paradox and the direct discourse Liar Paradox, these intensional paradoxes are recalcitrant and challenge logical analysis. Indeed, when we take these paradoxes seriously, we may need to rethink the commonly (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  18.  5
    Richmond H. Thomason (2011). Some Limitations to the Psychological Orientation in Semantic Theory. Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (1):1 - 14.
    The psychological orientation treats semantics as a matter of idealized computation over symbolic structures, and semantic relations like denotation as relations between linguistic expressions and these structures. I argue that results similar to Gödel's incompleteness theorems and Tarski's theorem on truth create foundational difficulties for this view of semantics.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  19.  43
    Robert C. Stalnaker & Richmond H. Thomason (1968). Abstraction in First-Order Modal Logic. Theoria 34 (3):203-207.
    The first amounts, roughly, to "It is necessarily the case that any President of the U.S. is a citizen of the U.S." But the second says, "the person who in fact is the President of the U.S, has the property of necessarily being a citizen of the U.S," Thus, while (2) is clearly true, it would be reasonable to consider (3) false.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   6 citations  
  20.  28
    Matthew Stone & Richmond H. Thomason, Context in Abductive Interpretation.
    This paper develops a general approach to contextual reasoning in natural language processing. Drawing on the view of natural language interpretation as abduction (Hobbs et al., 1993), we propose that interpretation provides an explanation of how an utterance creates a new discourse context in which its interpreted content is both true and promi- nent. Our framework uses dynamic theories of semantics and pragmatics, formal theories of context, and models of attentional state. We describe and illustrate a Prolog implementation.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  21.  6
    Jeremy Lent & Richmond H. Thomason (2015). Action Models for Conditionals. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 24 (2):211-231.
    Possible worlds semantics for conditionals leave open the problem of how to construct models for realistic domains. In this paper, we show how to adapt logics of action and change such as John McCarthy’s Situation Calculus to conditional logics. We illustrate the idea by presenting models for conditionals whose antecedents combine a declarative condition with a hypothetical action.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  22.  19
    Horacio Arló-Costa & Richmond H. Thomason (2001). Iterative Probability Kinematics. Journal of Philosophical Logic 30 (5):479-524.
    Following the pioneer work of Bruno De Finetti [12], conditional probability spaces (allowing for conditioning with events of measure zero) have been studied since (at least) the 1950's. Perhaps the most salient axiomatizations are Karl Popper's in [31], and Alfred Renyi's in [33]. Nonstandard probability spaces [34] are a well know alternative to this approach. Vann McGee proposed in [30] a result relating both approaches by showing that the standard values of infinitesimal probability functions are representable as Popper functions, and (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  23.  38
    Adam Rigoni & Richmond H. Thomason (2012). The Logic of Counterpart Theory with Actuality. Journal of Philosophical Logic (1):1-31.
    It has been claimed that counterpart theory cannot support a theory of actuality without rendering obviously invalid formulas valid or obviously valid formulas invalid. We argue that these claims are not based on logical flaws of counterpart theory itself, but point to the lack of appropriate devices in first-order logic for “remembering” the values of variables. We formulate a mildly dynamic version of first-order logic with appropriate memory devices and show how to base a version of counterpart theory with actuality (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  24.  49
    Richmond H. Thomason, Ability, Action, and Context.
    This paper proposes a formalization of ability that is motivated in part by linguistic considerations and by the philosophical literature in action theory and the logic of ability, but that is also meant to match well with planning formalisms, and so to provide an account of the role of ability in practical reasoning. Some of the philosophical literature concerning ability, and in particular [Austin, 1956], suggests that some ways of talking about ability are context-dependent. I propose a way of formalizing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  25.  33
    Richmond H. Thomason, Ability and Action.
    This is part of a larger project that is motivated in part by linguistic considerations and by the philosophical literature in action theory and the logic of ability, but that is also meant to suggest ways in which planning formalisms could be modified to provide an account of the role of ability in planning and practical reasoning.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  26.  33
    G. Aldo Antonelli & Richmond H. Thomason (2002). Representability in Second-Order Propositional Poly-Modal Logic. Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (3):1039-1054.
    A propositional system of modal logic is second-order if it contains quantifiers ∀p and ∃p, which, in the standard interpretation, are construed as ranging over sets of possible worlds (propositions). Most second-order systems of modal logic are highly intractable; for instance, when augmented with propositional quantifiers, K, B, T, K4 and S4 all become effectively equivalent to full second-order logic. An exception is S5, which, being interpretable in monadic second-order logic, is decidable.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  27.  28
    Richmond H. Thomason, Defeasibly Successful Action.
    “Philosophy of action” is a recognized specialty in contemporary philosophy, and the literature on action is fairly extensive: see, for instance, (Care & Landesman 1968; Goldman 1970; Hornsby 1980). The relation of actions to their effects is formulated most clearly in the more specialized literature on the logic of action; see (Belnap & Perloff 1988; Chellas 1992; Czelakowski 1996; Segerberg 1982).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  28.  21
    Matthew Stone & Richmond H. Thomason, Coordinating Understanding and Generation in an Abductive Approach.
    We use a dynamic, context-sensitive approach to abductive interpretation to describe coordinated processes of understanding, generation and accommodation in dialogue. The agent updates the dialogue uniformly for its own and its interlocutors’ utterances, by accommodating a new context, inferred abductively, in which utterance content is both true and prominent. The generator plans natural and comprehensible utterances by exploiting the same abductive preferences used in understanding. We illustrate our approach by formalizing and implementing some interactions between information structure and the form (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  29.  14
    Richmond H. Thomason, Logical Semantics for Causal Constructions.
    Montague’s framework for semantic interpretation has always been less well adapted to the interpretation of words than of syntactic constructions. In the late 1970s, David Dowty addressed this problem, concentrating on the interpretation of tense, aspect, inchoatives, and causatives in an extension of Montague’s Intensional Logic. In this paper I will try to revive this project, conceiving it as part of a larger task aiming at the interpretation of derivational morphology. I will try to identity some obstacles arising in Dowty’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  30.  16
    Richmond H. Thomason, Non-Monotonic Formalisms.
    I will try to do three things in this paper. First, I want to situate certain problems in natural language semantics with respect to larger trends in logicism, including: (i) Attempts by positivist philosophers earlier in this century to provide a logical basis for the physical sciences; (ii) Attempts by linguists and logicians to develop a “natural language ontology” (and, presumably, a logical language that is related to this ontology by formally explicit rules) that would serve as a framework for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  31.  9
    Richmond H. Thomason, Mixing Strict and Defeasible Inheritance.
    rich domain involves an intricate mixture of strict and defeasible information. The importance of representing defeasible information in an inheritance system has been widely recognized, but it is not enough for a sys-.
    No categories
    Translate
      Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  32.  11
    Richmond H. Thomason, Formalizing the Semantics of Derived Words.
    I believe that this approach leads to a wider problem that brings together elements of linguistics and philosophy in an illuminating way. But the single case study that I provide here, while it may be suggestive, does not go far enough to make a good case for the more general point. This paper is extracted from a larger collection of documents, and is intended to motivate and illustrate the ideas.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  33.  11
    Richmond H. Thomason (1985). Note on Tense and Subjunctive Conditionals. Philosophy of Science 52 (1):151-153.
    I argue that a counterexample proposed by donald nute shows only that past tenses involve indexical restriction to a limited domain of times. The purpose of this note is to defend the thesis that there is a single conditional connective figuring in both indicative and 'had'--'would' connectives, And that the differences in logical form between the two sorts of english conditional expressions have to do with tense.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  34.  2
    J. Wight Duff (1934). The Priapea and Ovid Richmond Frederick Thomason, Ph.D.: The Priapea and Ovid: A Study of the Language of the Poems. Pp. Viii + 100. Nashville, Tennessee: George Peabody College for Teachers, 1931. Paper. [REVIEW] The Classical Review 48 (06):227-228.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  35.  12
    J. F. Horty, R. H. Thomason & D. S. Touretzky (1990). A Sceptical Theory of Inheritance in Nonmonotonic Semantic Networks. Artificial Intelligence 42:311-348.
    inheritance reasoning in semantic networks allowing for multiple inheritance with exceptions. The approach leads to a definition of iaheritance that is..
    Translate
      Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   7 citations  
  36.  19
    R. H. Thomason (1972). A Semantic Theory of Sortal Incorrectness. Journal of Philosophical Logic 1 (2):209 - 258.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   7 citations  
  37.  70
    Neil Thomason (1994). The Power of ARCHED Hypotheses: Feyerabend's Galileo as a Closet Rationalist. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (1):255-264.
  38.  6
    Neil Thomason (1996). Elk Theories—A Galilean Strategy for Validating a New Scientific Discovery. In P. Riggs (ed.), Natural Kinds, Laws of Nature and Scientific Methodology. Kluwer Academic Publishers 123--144.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  39.  4
    Steven K. Thomason (1973). A New Representation of $S5$. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 14 (2):281-284.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  40.  6
    R. H. Thomason & H. LeBlanc (1967). All or None: A Novel Choice of Primitives for Elementary Logic. Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (3):345-351.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  41.  12
    Moriah E. Thomason (2009). Children in Non-Clinical Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (Fmri) Studies Give the Scan Experience a “Thumbs Up”. American Journal of Bioethics 9 (1):25 – 27.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  42.  5
    S. K. Thomason (1970). A Theorem on Initial Segments of Degrees. Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):41-45.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  43.  0
    J. L. Thomason (2012). Choosing a Medical Specialty. Epiphany, Where Are You? The Pharos of Alpha Omega Alpha-Honor Medical Society. Alpha Omega Alpha 75 (1):14.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  44. S. Thomason (1984). D.A. Gillies, Frege, Dedekind And Peano On The Foundations Of Arithmetic. [REVIEW] Philosophy in Review 4:111-113.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  45.  0
    S. K. Thomason (1973). Review: David Makinson, A Generalisation of the Concept of a Relational Model for Modal Logic. [REVIEW] Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (3):520-520.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  46. Michael V. R. Thomason (1997). To Remember a Vanishing World: D. L. Hightower's Photographs of Barbour County, Alabama, C. 1930-1965. University Alabama Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  47.  61
    Richmond H. Thomason (1970). Indeterminist Time and Truth-Value Gaps. Theoria 36 (3):264-281.
  48.  91
    Richmond H. Thomason & Robert C. Stalnaker (1968). Modality and Reference. Noûs 2 (4):359-372.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   8 citations  
  49.  5
    Richmond H. Thomason (2007). Three Interactions Between Context and Epistemic Locutions. In D. C. Richardson B. Kokinov (ed.), Modeling and Using Context. Springer 467--481.
  50. Richmond H. Thomason (ed.) (1974). Formal Philosophy. Yale University Press.
    No categories
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   7 citations  
1 — 50 / 155