Search results for 'Robert Gooding-Wiliams' (try it on Scholar)

999 found
Sort by:
  1. Jean-Dominique Robert (1981). ROBERT, Jean-Dominique, O.P., Philosophie Et Sciences Humaines. Laval Théologique Et Philosophique 37 (1):109-109.score: 80.0
  2. J. Robert & S. Whittle (1986). The Developmental Programme - Concept or Muddle?Programmes for Development, Genes, Chromosomes and Computer Models in Developmental Biology. Edited by Alma Swan, HERBERT Macgregor and Robert Ransom.J. Embryol. Exp. Morph. Volume 83 Supplement. The Company of Biologists Ltd, Cambridge, 1984. Pp. 369. �12.00, $23.00. [REVIEW] Bioessays 5 (2):91-92.score: 80.0
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  3. Judith Butler (1998). Reply to Robert Gooding-Williams. Constellations 5 (1):42-47.score: 42.0
  4. Ronald Robles Sundstrom (2012). In The Shadow of Du Bois: Afro-Modern Political Thought in America by Robert Gooding-Williams. Constellations 19 (1):139-145.score: 42.0
  5. Tobin Craig (2002). Robert Gooding-Williams, Zarathustra's Dionysian Modernism Reviewed By. Philosophy in Review 22 (3):185-188.score: 42.0
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  6. George Kateb (1998). Response to Robert Gooding-Williams. Constellations 5 (1):48-50.score: 42.0
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  7. Patricia J. Williams (1998). Seeing a Cohr-Blind Future: The Paradox of Race (New York: Farrar, Straus and GiroUX, 1997); Robert Gooding-Williams," Race. Multiculturalism, and Democracy,". Constellations 5:i8 - 41.score: 42.0
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  8. David Decosimo (2012). Intrinsic Goodness and Contingency, Resemblance and Particularity: Two Criticisms of Robert Adams's Finite and Infinite Goods. Studies in Christian Ethics 25 (4):418-441.score: 36.0
    Robert Adams’s Finite and Infinite Goods is one of the most important and innovative contributions to theistic ethics in recent memory. This article identifies two major flaws at the heart of Adams’s theory: his notion of intrinsic value and his claim that ‘excellence’ or finite goodness is constituted by resemblance to God. I first elucidate Adams’s complex, frequently misunderstood claims concerning intrinsic value and Godlikeness. I then contend that Adams’s notion of intrinsic value cannot explain what it could mean (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  9. Robert Gooding-Wiliams (1998). Race, Multiculturalism and Democracy. Constellations 5 (1):18-41.score: 29.0
  10. Candace Vogler (forthcoming). Some Remarks on Robert Audi's the Good in the Right. In Mark Timmons (ed.), Rationality and the Good. Oxford University Press.score: 25.0
    Robert Audi’s The Good in the Right undertakes the magisterial work of reviving the intuitionism of W.D. Ross, rescuing Ross from the overlapping shadows of Henry Sidgwick, G. E. Moore, and, to a lesser extent, H. A. Prichard, marrying Ross to Kant, and so working to produce "a full-scale moral philosophy providing both an account of moral principles and judgments—a metaethical account—and a set of basic moral standards" that might be employed in moral reasoning. The book is magnificent in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  11. Anthony Skelton (2007). Critical Notice of Robert Audi, The Good in the Right. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (2):305-325.score: 24.0
    Critical notice of Robert Audi's The Good in the Right in which doubts are raised about the epistemological and ethical doctrines it defends. It doubts that an appeal to Kant is a profitable way to defend Rossian normative intuitionism.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  12. Samuel Newlands & Larry M. Jorgensen (eds.) (2009). Metaphysics and the Good: Themes From the Philosophy of Robert Merrihew Adams. Oxford University Press.score: 24.0
    Throughout his philosophical career at Michigan, UCLA, Yale, and Oxford, Robert Merrihew Adams's wide-ranging contributions have deeply shaped the structure of debates in metaphysics, philosophy of religion, history of philosophy, and ethics. Metaphysics and the Good: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Merrihew Adams provides, for the first time, a collection of original essays by leading philosophers dedicated to exploring many of the facets of Adams's thought, a philosophical outlook that combines Christian theism, neo-Platonism, moral realism, metaphysical idealism, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  13. Sergio Morresi (2010). Política Cotidiana y Tolerancia en las obras de John Locke y Robert Nozick. Doispontos 7 (4).score: 24.0
    En 1974, Robert Nozick publicó *Anarquía, Estado y Utopía*, una obra que, por primera vez, otorgaba estatus teórico a una de las corrientes del pensamiento neoliberal: el libertarianismo. En buena medida, el texto de Nozick se reclama como una relectura en clave de filosofía analítica de la teoría política de John Locke. En este artículo se ofrecen algunos argumentos para mostrar que, aunque la perspectiva de Nozick presenta ciertas similitudes retóricas con la obra del filósofo inglés, en cada uno (...)
    No categories
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  14. Dean Moyar (2012). How the Good Obligates in Hegel's Conception ofSittlichkeit: A Response to Robert Stern'sUnderstanding Moral Obligation. Inquiry 55 (6):584-605.score: 24.0
    Abstract In Understanding Moral Obligation: Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard, Robert Stern argues that Hegel has a social command view of obligation. On this view, there is an element of social command or social sanction that must be added to a judgment of the good in order to bring about an obligation. I argue to the contrary that Hegel's conception of conscience, and thus the individual's role in obligation, is more central to his account than the social dimension. While agreeing with (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  15. James Wetzel (2006). God in the Cave: A Look Back at Robert Merrihew Adams's "Finite and Infinite Goods". [REVIEW] Journal of Religious Ethics 34 (3):485 - 520.score: 24.0
    When "Finite and Infinite Goods" was published in 1999, it took its place as one of the few major statements of a broadly Augustinian ethical philosophy of the past century. By "broadly Augustinian" I refer to the disposition to combine a Platonic emphasis on a transcendent source of value with a traditionally theistic emphasis on the value-creating capacities of absolute will. In the form that this disposition takes with Robert Merrihew Adams, it is the resemblance between divine and a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  16. Robert Sokolowski, John J. Drummond & James G. Hart (eds.) (1996). The Truthful and the Good: Essays in Honor of Robert Sokolowski. Kluwer Academic Publishers.score: 24.0
    This book collects essays considering the full range of Robert Sokolowski's philosophical works: his vew of philosophy; his phenomenology of language and his account of the relation between language and being; his phenomenology of moral action; and his phenomenological theology of disclosure.
    No categories
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  17. Robert F. Allen (2005). Free Will and Indeterminism: Robert Kane's Libertarianism. Journal of Philosophical Research 30:341-355.score: 21.0
    Drawing on Aristotle’s notion of “ultimate responsibility,” Robert Kane argues that to be exercising a free will an agent must have taken some character forming decisions for which there were no sufficient conditions or decisive reasons.1 That is, an agent whose will is free not only had the ability to develop other dispositions, but could have exercised that ability without being irrational. To say it again, a person has a free will just in case her character is the product (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  18. Mark Timmons, John Greco & Alfred R. Mele (eds.) (2007). Rationality and the Good: Critical Essays on the Ethics and Epistemology of Robert Audi. Oxford University Press.score: 21.0
    For over thirty years, Robert Audi has produced important work in ethics, epistemology, and the theory of action. This volume features thirteen new critical essays on Audi by a distinguished group of authors: Fred Adams, William Alston, Laurence BonJour, Roger Crisp, Elizabeth Fricker, Bernard Gert, Thomas Hurka, Hugh McCann, Al Mele, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Raimo Tuomela, Candace Vogler, and Timothy Williamson. Audi's introductory essay provides a thematic overview interconnecting his views in ethics, epistemology, and philosophy of action. The volume concludes (...)
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  19. Robert H. Myers (2002). Robert Merrihew Adams, Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics:Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics. Ethics 112 (2):351-354.score: 21.0
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  20. Kenneth R. Westphal (1997). ‘Hegel, Formalism, and Robert Turner’s Ceramic Art’. Jahrbuch für Hegelforschung 3:259–283.score: 21.0
    Hegel’s aesthetic ideal is the perfect integration of form and content within a work of art. This ideal is incompatible with the predominant 20th-century principle of formalist criticism, that form is the sole important factor in a work of art. Although the formalist dichotomy between form and content has been criticized on philosophical grounds, that does not suffice to justify Hegel’s ideal. Justifying Hegel’s ideal requires detailed art criticism that shows how form and content are, and why they should be, (...)
    Translate to English
    |
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  21. Robert Stalnaker (2002). Epistemic Consequentialism: Robert Stalnaker. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 76 (1):153–168.score: 18.0
    [Philip Percival] I aim to illuminate foundational epistemological issues by reflecting on 'epistemic consequentialism'-the epistemic analogue of ethical consequentialism. Epistemic consequentialism employs a concept of cognitive value playing a role in epistemic norms governing belief-like states that is analogous to the role goodness plays in act-governing moral norms. A distinction between 'direct' and 'indirect' versions of epistemic consequentialism is held to be as important as the familiar ethical distinction on which it is based. These versions are illustrated, respectively, by cognitive (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  22. Roksana Alavi (2005). Robert Kane, Free Will, and Neuro-Indeterminism. Philo 8 (2):95-108.score: 18.0
    In this paper I argue that Robert Kane’s defense of event-causal libertarianism, as presented in Responsibility, Luck, and Chance: Reflections on Free Will and Indeterminism, fails because his event-causal reconstruction is incoherent. I focus on the notions of efforts and self-forming actions essential to his defense.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  23. Kevin Carnahan (2013). Religion, and Not Just Religious Reasons, in the Public Square: A Consideration of Robert Audi's and Nicholas Wolterstorff's Religion in the Public Square. Philosophia 41 (2):397-409.score: 18.0
    For the last several decades, philosophers have wrestled with the proper place of religion in liberal societies. Usually, the debates among these philosophers have started with the articulation of various conceptions of liberalism and then proceeded to locate religion in the context of these conceptions. In the process, however, too little attention has been paid to the way religion is conceived. Drawing on the work of Robert Audi and Nicholas Wolterstorff, two scholars who are often read as holding opposing (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  24. Jose Filipe Silva & Juhana Toivanen (2011). The Active Nature of the Soul in Sense Perception: Robert Kilwardby and Peter Olivi. Vivarium 48 (3-4):245-278.score: 18.0
    This article discusses the theories of perception of Robert Kilwardby and Peter of John Olivi. Our aim is to show how in challenging certain assumptions of medieval Aristotelian theories of perception they drew on Augustine and argued for the active nature of the soul in sense perception. For both Kilwardby and Olivi, the soul is not passive with respect to perceived objects; rather, it causes its own cognitive acts with respect to external objects and thus allows the subject to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  25. Rachana Kamtekar (2010). Comments on Robert Adams, a Theory of Virtue: Excellence in Being for the Good. Philosophical Studies 148 (1):147 - 158.score: 18.0
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  26. Arthur Madigan (2010). Review of Robert Spaemann's Persons. [REVIEW] Journal of Religious Ethics 38 (2):373-392.score: 18.0
    This review presents the principal themes of Robert Spaemann's Persons: The Difference between ‘Someone’ and ‘Something.’ To be a person is not to be identical with one's teleological nature, but rather, to have that nature. Personal consciousness is necessarily temporal consciousness. Persons have a range of distinctively personal acts, such as recognizing and respecting one another, understanding their lives as wholes, making judgments of conscience, promising, and forgiving. All members of the human species, whatever their stage of development or (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  27. Paul Noordhof (2008). The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value - by Robert Audi. Philosophical Books 49 (2):175-178.score: 18.0
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  28. Ben Bradley (2007). Review of Robert Merrihew Adams, A Theory of Virtue: Excellence in Being for the Good. [REVIEW] Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2007 (5).score: 18.0
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  29. William Grassie (2012). Many Windows: Reflections on Robert Ulanowicz's Search for Meaning in Science. Axiomathes 22 (2):195-205.score: 18.0
    This paper is an extended discussion of Robert Ulanowicz’s critique of mechanistic and reductionistic metaphysics of science. He proposes “process ecology” as an alternative. In this paper I discuss four sets of question coming out of Ulanowicz’s proposal. First, I argue that universality remains one of the hallmarks of the scientific enterprise even with his new process metaphysics. I then discuss the Second Law of Thermodynamics in the interpretation of the history of the universe. I question Ulanowicz’s use of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  30. Russell Blackford (2012). Robots and Reality: A Reply to Robert Sparrow. [REVIEW] Ethics and Information Technology 14 (1):41-51.score: 18.0
    We commonly identify something seriously defective in a human life that is lived in ignorance of important but unpalatable truths. At the same time, some degree of misapprehension of reality may be necessary for individual health and success. Morally speaking, it is unclear just how insistent we should be about seeking the truth. Robert Sparrow has considered such issues in discussing the manufacture and marketing of robot ‘pets’, such as Sony’s doglike ‘AIBO’ toy and whatever more advanced devices may (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  31. Rauno Huttunen (2012). Hegelians Axel Honneth and Robert Williams on the Development of Human Morality. Studies in Philosophy and Education 31 (4):339-355.score: 18.0
    An individual is in the lowest phase of moral development if he thinks only of his own personal interest and has only his own selfish agenda in his mind as he encounters other humans. This lowest phase corresponds well with sixteenth century British moral egoism which reflects the rise of the new economic order. Adam Smith (1723–1790) wanted to defend this new economic order which is based on economic exchange between egoistic individuals. Nevertheless, he surely did not want to support (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  32. Isabelle Travis (2011). 'Is Getting Well Ever An Art?': Psychopharmacology and Madness in Robert Lowell's Day by Day. [REVIEW] Journal of Medical Humanities 32 (4):315-324.score: 18.0
    On the publication of Robert Lowell’s Life Studies in 1959, some critics were shocked by the poet’s use of seemingly frank autobiographical material, in particular the portrayal of his hospitalizations for bipolar disorder. During the late fifties and throughout the sixties, a rich vein, influenced by Lowell , developed in American poetry. Also during this time, the nascent science of psychopharmacology competed with and complemented the more established somatic treatments, such as psychosurgery, shock treatments, and psychoanalytical therapies. The development (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  33. Franck Varenne (2013). Théorie mathématique des catégories en biologie et notion d’équivalence naturelle chez Robert Rosen. Revue d'Histoire des Sciences 66 (1):167-197.score: 18.0
    The aim of this paper is to describe and analyze the epistemological justification of a proposal initially made by the bio-mathematician Robert Rosen in 1958. In this theoretical proposal, Rosen suggests using the mathematical concept of « category » and the correlative concept of « natural equivalence » in mathematical modeling applied to living beings. Our questions are the following: according to Rosen, to what extent does the mathematical notion of category give access to more « natural » formalisms (...)
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  34. Bart Streumer (2005). Review of Robert Audi, The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. [REVIEW] Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2005.score: 18.0
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  35. Walter Feinberg (2007). Grappling with the Good: Talking About Religion and Morality in Public Schools - by Robert Kunzman. Educational Philosophy and Theory 39 (7):783–786.score: 18.0
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  36. Scott Sehon (2008). Review of Mark Timmons, John Greco, Alfred R. Mele (Eds.), Rationality and the Good: Critical Essays on the Ethics and Epistemology of Robert Audi. [REVIEW] Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2008 (3).score: 18.0
  37. Michael Ruse (2004). The Romantic Conception of Robert J. Richards. Journal of the History of Biology 37 (1):3 - 23.score: 18.0
    In his new book, "The Romantic Conception of Life: Science and Philosophy in the Age of Goethe," Robert J. Richards argues that Charles Darwin's true evolutionary roots lie in the German Romantic biology that flourished around the beginning of the nineteenth century. It is argued that Richards is quite wrong in this claim and that Darwin's roots are in the British society within which he was born, educated, and lived.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  38. Mark Cresswell & Zulfia Karimova (2013). 'Misfortune's Image': The Cinematic Representation of Trauma in Robert Bresson's Mouchette (1967). Film-Philosophy 17 (1):154-176.score: 18.0
    This paper asks questions about 'trauma' and its cultural representation specifically, trauma's representation in the cinema. In this respect, it compares and contrasts the work of Robert Bresson, in particular his 1967 masterpiece, Mouchette , with contemporary Hollywood film. James Mangold's 1999 'Oscar-winning' Girl, Interrupted offers an interesting example for cultural comparison. In both Mouchette and Girl, Interrupted the subject matter includes, amongst other traumatic experiences, rape, childhood abuse and suicide. The paper ponders the question of whether such aspects (...)
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  39. Matthias Perkams (2012). Bernhard von Clairvaux, Robert von Melun und die Anfange des mittelalterlichen Voluntarismus. Vivarium 50 (1):1-32.score: 18.0
    Abstract Two distinguishing marks of voluntaristic conceptions of human action can be found already in the 12th century, not only in the work of Bonaventura's successors: 1. the will is free to act against reasons's dictates; 2. moral responsibility depends on this conception of the will's freedom. A number of theologians from the 1130s to the 1170s accepted those claims, which have been originally formulated by Bernard of Clairvaux. Robert of Melun elaborated them in a systematical way and coined (...)
    Translate to English
    | Direct download (5 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  40. Sean D. McKeever (2006). Robert Audi, The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value:The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Ethics 116 (2):403-405.score: 18.0
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  41. Russ Shafer-Landau (2007). The Good in the Right by Robert Audi. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (1):250-261.score: 18.0
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  42. Dale Jamieson (2006). Robert A. Hinde , Why Good is Good: The Sources of Morality (London: Routledge, 2002), Pp. Xiv + 241. Utilitas 18 (02):196-.score: 18.0
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  43. Daniel Jacobson (2002). Review of Robert Hinde, Why Good is Good: The Sources of Morality. [REVIEW] Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2002 (9).score: 18.0
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  44. Hendrik Wortmann (2013). Re-Reading Robert E. Park on Social Evolution: An Early Darwinian Conception of Society. Biological Theory 7 (1):69-79.score: 18.0
    Although Darwinian concepts have largely been banned from the social sciences of the last century, they have recently seen a revival in several disciplines such as sociology, anthropology, or economics. Most of the current proponents of evolutionary theorizing in the social sciences avoid references to the older literature on social evolution. On that background, this article presents a contribution to Darwinist thinking in early American sociology that has mainly been overlooked in the literature. As the leading figure of the Human (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  45. Daniel Moseley (forthcoming). Review of Robert Kane, "Ethics and the Quest for Wisdom.&Quot;. [REVIEW] Journal of Moral Philosophy.score: 16.0
    Kane's ambitious and bold book presents a sustained argument for an ethical theory that gives an account of right action and the good life. The general structure of the main argument is presented and specific points are critically discussed.
    Translate to English
    | Direct download  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  46. A. H. Louie & Stephen W. Kercel (2007). Topology and Life Redux: Robert Rosen's Relational Diagrams of Living Systems. [REVIEW] Axiomathes 17 (2):109-136.score: 15.0
    Algebraic/topological descriptions of living processes are indispensable to the understanding of both biological and cognitive functions. This paper presents a fundamental algebraic description of living/cognitive processes and exposes its inherent ambiguity. Since ambiguity is forbidden to computation, no computational description can lend insight to inherently ambiguous processes. The impredicativity of these models is not a flaw, but is, rather, their strength. It enables us to reason with ambiguous mathematical representations of ambiguous natural processes. The noncomputability of these structures means computerized (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  47. Ronald Loeffler (2005). Normative Phenomenalism: On Robert Brandom's Practice-Based Explanation of Meaning. European Journal of Philosophy 13 (1):32-69.score: 15.0
  48. Thaddeus Metz (2013). 'The Meaning of Life Lies in the Search': Robert Kane's New Justification of Objective Values. Social Theory and Practice 39 (2):313-27.score: 15.0
    Part of Robert Kane’s response to the contemporary cultural condition of pluralism is to attempt to ground morality in the _search_ for wisdom about how to live. With regard to the right, Kane argues, roughly, that a new principle capturing what all morally permissible actions have in common warrants belief on the part of all inquirers, even in the face of reasonable uncertainty, because it is justified as an essential means to ascertaining wisdom. Upon embarking for wisdom, one quickly (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  49. Robert Lockie (2006). Response to Anders Tolland's 'Iterated Non-Refutation: Robert Lockie on Relativism'. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 14 (2):245 – 254.score: 15.0
    This Article is a short response to Anders Tolland's "Iterated Non-Refutation: Robert Lockie on Relativism", International Journal of Philosophical Studies Vol. 14, no. 2, 245-254, 2006. Tolland's article was itself a response to Lockie, R (2003) "Relativism and Reflexivity", International Journal of Philosophical Studies Vol. 11, no. 3, 319-339.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    My bibliography  
     
    Export citation  
  50. Alan Ryan (1992). Book Review: Robert Nozick: Property, Justice, and the Minimal State. Jonathan Wolff. [REVIEW] Ethics 103 (1):154-.score: 15.0
1 — 50 / 999