86 found
Order:
Disambiguations:
Robert C. Richardson [60]Robert Richardson [8]Robert D. Richardson [6]Robert P. Richardson [5]
Robert K. Richardson [3]Robert A. Richardson [1]Robert C. Richardson [1]Robert Richardson Jr [1]

Not all matches are shown. Search with initial or firstname to single out others.

See also:
Profile: Robert Neville Richardson (University of KwaZulu-Natal)
  1. William Bechtel & Robert C. Richardson (1993). Discovering Complexity Decomposition and Localization as Strategies in Scientific Research. Princeton.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   191 citations  
  2.  2
    Robert C. Richardson (2007). Evolutionary Psychology as Maladapted Psychology. A Bradford Book.
    Human beings, like other organisms, are the products of evolution. Like other organisms, we exhibit traits that are the product of natural selection. Our psychological capacities are evolved traits as much as are our gait and posture. This much few would dispute. Evolutionary psychology goes further than this, claiming that our psychological traits -- including a wide variety of traits, from mate preference and jealousy to language and reason -- can be understood as specific adaptations to ancestral Pleistocene conditions. In (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   22 citations  
  3. William Bechtel, Robert C. Richardson & Scott A. Kleiner (1996). Discovering Complexity. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 18 (3):363-382.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   29 citations  
  4. F. C. Boogerd, F. J. Bruggeman, Robert C. Richardson, Achim Stephan & H. Westerhoff (2005). Emergence and Its Place in Nature: A Case Study of Biochemical Networks. Synthese 145 (1):131 - 164.
    We will show that there is a strong form of emergence in cell biology. Beginning with C.D. Broad's classic discussion of emergence, we distinguish two conditions sufficient for emergence. Emergence in biology must be compatible with the thought that all explanations of systemic properties are mechanistic explanations and with their sufficiency. Explanations of systemic properties are always in terms of the properties of the parts within the system. Nonetheless, systemic properties can still be emergent. If the properties of the components (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   23 citations  
  5.  93
    Robert C. Richardson (2008). Autonomy and Multiple Realization. Philosophy of Science 75 (5):526-536.
    Multiple realization historically mandated the autonomy of psychology, and its principled irreducibility to neuroscience. Recently, multiple realization and its implications for the reducibility of psychology to neuroscience have been challenged. One challenge concerns the proper understanding of reduction. Another concerns whether multiple realization is as pervasive as is alleged. I focus on the latter question. I illustrate multiple realization with actual, rather than hypothetical, cases of multiple realization from within the biological sciences. Though they do support a degree of autonomy (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   6 citations  
  6. Robert C. Richardson (1997). Natural and Artificial Complexity. Philosophy of Science 64 (4):267.
    Genetic regulatory networks are complex, involving tens or hundreds of genes and scores of proteins with varying dependencies and organizations. This invites the application of artificial techniques in coming to understand natural complexity. I describe two attempts to deploy artificial models in understanding natural complexity. The first abstracts from empirically established patterns, favoring random architectures and very general constraints, in an attempt to model developmental phenomena. The second incorporates detailed information concerning the genetic structure, organization, and dependencies in actual systems (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  7. Robert C. Richardson (1990). The "Tally Argument" and the Validation of Psychoanalysis. Philosophy of Science 57 (4):668-676.
    The classic charge against Freudian theory is that the therapeutic success of psychoanalysis can be explained without appeal to the mechanisms of repression and insight. Whatever therapeutic success psychoanalysis might enjoy would then provide no support for the diagnostic claim that psychological disorders are due to repressed desires or for the therapeutic claim that the gains in psychoanalysis are due to insight into repressed causes. Adolf Grünbaum has repeated the charge in The Foundations of Psychoanalysis (1984), arguing that Freud's response (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  8.  96
    Robert C. Richardson (1996). The Prospects for an Evolutionary Psychology: Human Language and Human Reasoning. [REVIEW] Minds and Machines 6 (4):541-557.
    Evolutionary psychology purports to explain human capacities as adaptations to an ancestral environment. A complete explanation of human language or human reasoning as adaptations depends on assessing an historical claim, that these capacities evolved under the pressure of natural selection and are prevalent because they provided systematic advantages to our ancestors. An outline of the character of the information needed in order to offer complete adaptation explanations is drawn from Robert Brandon (1990), and explanations offered for the evolution of language (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   8 citations  
  9. Robert C. Richardson (1982). The 'Scandal' of Cartesian Interactionism. Mind 91 (January):20-37.
  10. Robert C. Richardson (1984). Biology and Ideology: The Interpenetration of Science and Values. Philosophy of Science 51 (3):396-420.
    The mutual influence of science and values in biology is exhibited in several cases from the biological literature. It is argued in a number of cases, from R. A. Fisher's argument for the optimality of a 50:50 sex ratio to A. Jensen's defense of a genetic basis for intelligence, and including work on the evolution of sexual dimorphism and muted aggression, that the credence accorded the views is disproportionate with their theoretical and empirical warrant. It is, furthermore, suggested that the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  11.  89
    Robert C. Richardson (2009). Multiple Realization and Methodological Pluralism. Synthese 167 (3):473 - 492.
    Multiple realization was once taken to be a challenge to reductionist visions, especially within cognitive science, and a foundation of the “antireductionist consensus.” More recently, multiple realization has come to be challenged on naturalistic grounds, as well as on more “metaphysical” grounds. Within cognitive science, one focal issue concerns the role of neural plasticity for addressing these issues. If reorganization maintains the same cognitive functions, that supports claims for multiple realization. I take up the reorganization involved in language dysfunctions to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  12.  77
    Robert C. Richardson & Achim Stephan (2007). Emergence. Biological Theory 2 (1):91-96.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  13.  15
    Robert P. Richardson (1932). Preludes to Philosophy. The Monist 42 (4):508-519.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  14.  54
    Robert C. Richardson (1979). Functionalism and Reductionism. Philosophy of Science 46 (4):533-58.
    It is here argued that functionalist constraints on psychology do not preclude the applicability of classic forms of reduction and, therefore, do not support claims to a principled, or de jure, autonomy of psychology. In Part I, after isolating one minimal restriction any functionalist theory must impose on its categories, it is shown that any functionalism imposing an additional constraint of de facto autonomy must also be committed to a pure functionalist--that is, a computationalist--model for psychology. Using an extended parallel (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   9 citations  
  15.  22
    Robert C. Richardson (2006). Chance and the Patterns of Drift: A Natural Experiment. Philosophy of Science 73 (5):642-654.
    Evolutionary models can explain the dynamics of populations, how genetic, genotypic, or phenotypic frequencies change with time. Models incorporating chance, or drift, predict specific patterns of change. These are illustrated using classic work on blood types by Cavalli-Sforza and his collaborators in the Parma Valley of Italy, in which the theoretically predicted patterns are exhibited in human populations. These data and the models display properties of ensembles of populations. The explanatory problem needs to be understood in terms of how likely (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   4 citations  
  16.  13
    Robert C. Richardson (1980). On Sociobiology. Teaching Philosophy 3 (4):479-489.
  17.  40
    Fred C. Boogerd, Frank J. Bruggeman & Robert C. Richardson (2013). Mechanistic Explanations and Models in Molecular Systems Biology. Foundations of Science 18 (4):725-744.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  18.  72
    Anthony Landreth & Robert C. Richardson (2004). Localization and the New Phrenology: A Review Essay on William Uttal's the New Phrenology. [REVIEW] Philosophical Psychology 17 (1):107-123.
    William Uttal's The new phrenology is a broad attack on localization in cognitive neuroscience. He argues that even though the brain is a highly differentiated organ, "high level cognitive functions" should not be localized in specific brain regions. First, he argues that psychological processes are not well-defined. Second, he criticizes the methods used to localize psychological processes, including imaging technology: he argues that variation among individuals compromises localization, and that the statistical methods used to construct activation maps are flawed. Neither (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  19.  39
    Robert C. Richardson (2001). Complexity, Self-Organization and Selection. Biology and Philosophy 16 (5):653-682.
    Recent work on self organization promises an explanation of complex order which is independent of adaptation. Self-organizing systems are complex systems of simple units, projecting order as a consequence of localized and generally nonlinear interactions between these units. Stuart Kauffman offers one variation on the theme of self-organization, offering what he calls a ``statistical mechanics'' for complex systems. This paper explores the explanatory strategies deployed in this ``statistical mechanics,'' initially focusing on the autonomy of statistical explanation as it applies in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  20.  7
    Richard M. Burian, Robert C. Richardson & Wim J. Van der Steen (1996). Against Generality: Meaning in Genetics and Philosophy. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 27 (1):1-29.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   7 citations  
  21.  73
    Robert C. Richardson (1999). Cognitive Science and Neuroscience: New Wave Reductionism. Philosopical Psychology 12 (3):297-307.
    John Bickle's Psychoneural reduction: the new wave (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998) aims to resurrect reductionism within philosophy of mind. He develops a new model of scientific reduction, geared to enhancing our understanding of how theories in neuroscience and cognitive science are interrelated. I put this discussion in context, and assess the prospects for new wave reductionism, both as a general model of scientific reduction and as an attempt to defend reductionism in the philosophy of mind.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  22.  72
    William P. Bechtel & Robert C. Richardson (1983). Consciousness and Complexity: Evolutionary Perspectives on the Mind-Body Problem. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (December):378-95.
    (1983). Consciousness and complexity: Evolutionary perspectives on the mind-body problem. Australasian Journal of Philosophy: Vol. 61, No. 4, pp. 378-395.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  23.  13
    Robert P. Richardson (1929). Relativity and its Precursors. The Monist 39 (1):126-152.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  24.  11
    Robert P. Richardson (1929). The Theory of Universals and the Individualization of Attributes. The Monist 39 (4):535-560.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  25.  10
    Robert C. Richardson & Richard M. Burian (1992). A Defense of Propensity Interpretations of Fitness. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992:349 - 362.
    We offer a systematic examination of propensity interpretations of fitness, which emphasizes the role that fitness plays in evolutionary theory and takes seriously the probabilistic character of evolutionary change. We distinguish questions of the probabilistic character of fitness from the particular interpretations of probability which could be incorporated. The roles of selection and drift in evolutionary models support the view that fitness must be understood within a probabilistic framework, and the specific character of organism/environment interactions supports the conclusion that fitness (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   7 citations  
  26. Robert D. Richardson (2008). William James: In the Maelstrom of American Modernism. The Pluralist 3 (1):128-130.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  27.  54
    Robert C. Richardson & G. Muilenberg (1982). Sellars and Sense Impressions. Erkenntnis 17 (March):171-212.
  28.  40
    Robert C. Richardson (1982). How Not to Reduce a Functional Psychology. Philosophy of Science 49 (1):125-37.
  29.  33
    Robert C. Richardson (2003). Adaptationism, Adaptation, and Optimality. Biology and Philosophy 18 (5):695-713.
  30. Menachem Fisch & Robert C. Richardson (1994). William Whewell Philosopher of Sciences. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 16 (1):155.
  31.  56
    Robert Richardson & Lawrence A. Shapiro (2009). Evolution Without Adaptation? Metascience 18 (2):319-323.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  32.  8
    Edward H. Landis & Robert P. Richardson (1915). Numbers, Variables and Mr. Russell's Philosophy. The Monist 25 (3):321-364.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  33.  18
    Robert C. Richardson (1981). Internal Representation: Prologue to a Theory of Intentionality. Philosophical Topics 12 (1):171-212.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  34.  7
    Robert Richardson (1998). Heidegger, Dilthey, and the Crisis of Historicism. Review of Metaphysics 51 (4):906-910.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  35.  23
    Robert C. Richardson (2000). Michael Levin, Why Race Matters: Race Differences and What They Mean:Why Race Matters: Race Differences and What They Mean. Ethics 110 (4):847-848.
  36.  27
    Robert C. Richardson (1982). Turing Tests for Intelligence: Ned Block's Defense of Psychologism. [REVIEW] Philosophical Studies 41 (May):421-6.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  37.  11
    Robert C. Richardson (1986). Models and Scientific Explanations. Philosophica 37.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  38.  19
    Robert C. Richardson (2000). The Organism in Development. Philosophy of Science 67 (3):321.
    Developmental biology has resurfaced in recent years, often without a clearly central role for the organism. The organism is pulled in divergent directions: on the one hand, there is an important body of work that emphasizes the role of the gene in development, as executing and controlling embryological change; on the other hand, there are more theoretical approaches under which the organism disappears as little more than an instance for testing biological generalizations. I press here for the ineliminability of the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  39.  20
    Robert N. Brandon, Janis Antonovics, Richard Burian, Scott Carson, Greg Cooper, Paul Sheldon Davies, Christopher Horvath, Brent D. Mishler, Robert C. Richardson, Kelly Smith & Peter Thrall (1994). Sober on Brandon on Screening-Off and the Levels of Selection. Philosophy of Science 61 (3):475-486.
    Sober (1992) has recently evaluated Brandon's (1982, 1990; see also 1985, 1988) use of Salmon's (1971) concept of screening-off in the philosophy of biology. He critiques three particular issues, each of which will be considered in this discussion.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  40.  2
    Robert K. Richardson (1917). Resist Not Evil. Ethics 27 (2):225.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  41.  26
    Robert C. Richardson (2003). Engineering Design and Adaptation. Philosophy of Science 70 (5):1277-1288.
    Reverse engineering is a matter of inferring adaptive function from structure. The utility of reverse engineering for evolutionary biology has been a matter of controversy. I offer a simple taxonomy of the uses of engineering design in assessing adaptation, with a variety of illustrations. The plausibility of applications of engineering design reflects the specific way the models are elaborated and derived.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  42.  7
    Robert K. Richardson (1917). Resist Not Evil. International Journal of Ethics 27 (2):225-238.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  43.  15
    Robert Richardson (1983). Brentano on Intentional Inexistence and the Distinction Between Mental and Physical Phenomena. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 65 (3):250-282.
  44.  11
    Robert C. Richardson (1996). Book Review:Adaptation and Environment Robert N. Brandon. [REVIEW] Philosophy of Science 63 (1):122-.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  45.  22
    William E. Morris & Robert C. Richardson (1995). How Not to Demarcate Cognitive Science and Folk Psychology: A Response to Pickering and Chater. [REVIEW] Minds and Machines 5 (3):339-355.
    Pickering and Chater (P&C) maintain that folk psychology and cognitive science should neither compete nor cooperate. Each is an independent enterprise, with a distinct subject matter and characteristic modes of explanation. P&C''s case depends upon their characterizations of cognitive science and folk psychology. We question the basis for their characterizations, challenge both the coherence and the individual adequacy of their contrasts between the two, and show that they waver in their views about the scope of each. We conclude that P&C (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  46.  6
    Richard M. Burian & Robert C. Richardson (1990). Form and Order in Evolutionary Biology: Stuart Kauffman's Transformation of Theoretical Biology. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990:267 - 287.
    The formal framework of Kauffman (1991) depicts the constraints of self-organization on the evolution of complex systems and the relation of self-organization to selection. We discuss his treatment of 'generic constraints' as sources of order (section 2) and the relation between adaptation and organization (section 3). We then raise a number of issues, including the role of adaptation in explaining order (section 4) and the limitations of formal approaches in explaining the distinctively biological (section 5). The principal question we pose (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  47.  15
    Robert C. Richardson (1981). Disappearance and the Identity Theory. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 (September):473-85.
    We have no schema for comprehending how a radical revision of our conceptual scheme such as that embraced by "eliminative materialism" could possibly be rationally justified. This general point is illustrated and pressed through an examination of richard rorty's classic defense of the "disappearance form of the identity theory." it is argued that 1) though more standard critiques of rorty fail, 2) rorty fails to make out the case for the view that incorrigibility" is the "mark of the mental" to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  48.  21
    Robert C. Richardson (2007). Review of William C. Wimsatt, Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to Reality. [REVIEW] Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2007 (12).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  49. Robert D. Richardson (1998). Emerson: The Mind on Fire. Journal of Speculative Philosophy 12 (1):77-81.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  50. Richard M. Burian & Robert C. Richardson (1996). Form and Order in Evolutionary Biology. In Margaret A. Boden (ed.), The Philosophy of Artificial Life. Oxford University Press 146--72.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 86