Search results for 'Veikko Väänänen' (try it on Scholar)

110 found
Order:
  1. Marty Brice, Bourguignon Mathieu, Jousmäki Veikko, Wens Vincent, Op De Beeck Marc, Van Bogaert Patrick, Goldman Serge, Hari Riitta & De Tiège Xavier (2014). Cortical Kinematic Processing of Executed and Observed Goal-Directed Hand Actions. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  2. Vander Ghinst Marc, Bourguignon Mathieu, Op De Beeck Marc, Wens Vincent, Marty Brice, Hassid Sergio, Choufani Georges, Jousmäki Veikko, Hari Riitta, Van Bogaert Patrick, Goldman Serge & De Tiège Xavier (2014). Auditory Cortex Extraction of Attended Speech Envelope in a Multi-Talker Background. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  3.  34
    J. N. Adams (1982). Veikko Väänänen: Introduction au latin vulgaire. Troisième édition revue et augmentée. Pp. xxi + 273. Paris: Klincksieck, 1981. Paper. [REVIEW] The Classical Review 32 (02):287-.
    Translate
      Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  4.  13
    Robert W. Burch (2006). Review: Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen. Signs of Logic: Peircean Themes on the Philosophy of Language, Games, and Communication. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer, 2006. [REVIEW] Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 42 (4):577-581.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  5.  12
    Betty I. Knott (1967). Veikko Väänänen: Étude sur le texte et la langue des Tablettes Albertini. (Ann. Acad. Scient. Fennicae, ser. B, tom. 141. 2.) Pp. 66. Helsinki: Suomalainen Tiedakatemia, 1965. Paper, 3.20 mk. [REVIEW] The Classical Review 17 (02):227-228.
    Translate
      Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  6.  12
    Michael Winterbottom (1988). Veikko Väänänen: Le Journal-Épître d'Égérie (Itinerarium Egeriae): Étude Linguistique. (Annales Academiae Scientiarum Fennicae, Ser. B, 230.) Pp. 177; Plate of Folio of the Unique MS. Helsinki: Suomalainen Tiedeakatemia, 1987. Paper. [REVIEW] The Classical Review 38 (02):419-420.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  7.  12
    M. Seller (2000). Genes and Morality: New Essays: Edited by Veikko Launis, Juhani Pietarinen and Juha Raikka, Amsterdam, Atlanta, Rodopi, 1999, 199 Pages, US$36. [REVIEW] Journal of Medical Ethics 26 (6):483-483.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  8. Albert Hayward (1998). Arto Haapala, Jerrold Levinson, and Veikko Ran Tala, Eds., The End of Art and Beyond: Essays After Danto Reviewed By. Philosophy in Review 18 (4):258-261.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  9. Stephen Davies (1989). Review of Veikko Rantala, Lewis Rowell, Eero Tarasti : Essays on the philosophy of music. [REVIEW] Theoria 55 (2):137.
    No categories
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  10. David Pfeifer (2016). Peirce: 5 Questions Ed. By Francesco Bellucci, Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, Frederik Stjernfelt. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 51 (4):549-552.
    Over thirty volumes in the “5 Questions” series have appeared. Each publication gives a contemporary picture of the state of studies within a specific area. This volume on Peirce studies is no different. The volume contains answers to the questions by thirty-five Peirce scholars. My only minor criticism of the volume is that I would have liked to have seen some additional authors included—but they may have been unable to participate. The essays indicate that numerous thinkers have been drawn to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  11. G. H. von Wright (1945). Review: Veikko Salonen, On the Principles of Reduction Theory. [REVIEW] Journal of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):130-131.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  12. G. H. Von Wright (1945). Salonen Veikko. Reduktioteorian Periaatteisla . Ajatus, Bd. 13 , Pp. 262–293. Journal of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):130-131.
    Translate
      Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  13.  28
    Veikko Launis (2010). Cosmetic Neurology: Sliding Down the Slippery Slope? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 19 (2):218.
    In an editorial to a recent issue of Neurology, Richard Dees expresses the same criticism in an even more rigorous epistemic tone: Veikko Launis, Ph.D., is Professor of Medical Ethics and Adjunct Professor of Ethics and Social Philosophy at the University of Turku, Finland.FootnotesThis article is part of the Neuroethics of Brainreading research project, directed by myself and funded by the Academy of Finland. I am grateful to Olli Koistinen, Pekka Louhiala, Helena Siipi, and an anonymous referee for helpful (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  14.  3
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2015). Editorial Preface. Synthese 192 (4):877-879.
    This special issue of Synthese on Peirce’s Logic and Philosophy of Language collects papers by Rocco Gangle & Gianluca Caterina, Chuangshen He, Risto Hilpinen, Matthew Moore, Charles S. Peirce, Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen and Frederik Stjernfelt.Charles Sanders Peirce was a scientist, philosopher, mathematician and semiotician, as well as one of the undisputed giants in the founding of modern logic. He advanced virtually endless areas in exact sciences. He worked throughout his long career as a scientist, logician, philosopher, mathematician, and meaning analyst. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  15.  70
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2011). Moving Pictures of Thought II: Graphs, Games, and Pragmaticism's Proof. Semiotica 2011 (186):315-331.
    Peirce believed that his pragmaticism can be conclusively proven. Beginning in 1903, he drafted several attempts, ending by 1908 with a semeiotic proof. Around 1905, he exposes the proof using the theory of Existential Graphs . This paper modernizes the semantics Peirce proposed for EGs in terms of game-theoretic semantics . Peirce's 1905 proof is then reconstructed in three parts, by relating pragmaticism to the GTS conception of meaning, showing that Peirce's proof is an argument for a relational structure of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  16.  20
    Francesco Bellucci & Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, Peirce’s Logic. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Charles Sanders Peirce: Logic Charles Sanders Peirce was an accomplished scientist, philosopher, and mathematician, who considered himself primarily a logician. His contributions to the development of modern logic at the turn of the 20th century were colossal, original and influential. Formal, or deductive, logic was just one of the branches in which he exercized … Continue reading Peirce’s Logic →.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  17.  8
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen & Francesco Bellucci (2015). New Light on Peirce's Conceptions of Retroduction, Deduction, and Scientific Reasoning. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 28 (4):353-373.
    We examine Charles S. Peirce's mature views on the logic of science, especially as contained in his later and still mostly unpublished writings. We focus on two main issues. The first concerns Peirce's late conception of retroduction. Peirce conceived inquiry as performed in three stages, which correspond to three classes of inferences: abduction or retroduction, deduction, and induction. The question of the logical form of retroduction, of its logical justification, and of its methodology stands out as the three major threads (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  18. Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2005). Compositionality, Relevance, and Peirce's Logic of Existential Graphs. Axiomathes 15 (4):513-540.
    Charles S. Peirce’s pragmatist theory of logic teaches us to take the context of utterances as an indispensable logical notion without which there is no meaning. This is not a spat against compositionality per se , since it is possible to posit extra arguments to the meaning function that composes complex meaning. However, that method would be inappropriate for a realistic notion of the meaning of assertions. To accomplish a realistic notion of meaning (as opposed e.g. to algebraic meaning), Sperber (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   5 citations  
  19.  28
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2011). Existential Graphs: What a Diagrammatic Logic of Cognition Might Look Like. History and Philosophy of Logic 32 (3):265-281.
    This paper examines the contemporary philosophical and cognitive relevance of Charles Peirce's diagrammatic logic of existential graphs (EGs), the ?moving pictures of thought?. The first part brings to the fore some hitherto unknown details about the reception of EGs in the early 1900s that took place amidst the emergence of modern conceptions of symbolic logic. In the second part, philosophical aspects of EGs and their contributions to contemporary logical theory are pointed out, including the relationship between iconic logic and images, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   4 citations  
  20.  63
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2010). Peirce's Pragmatic Theory of Proper Names. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 46 (3):341-363.
    Charles Peirce's theory of proper names is intimately connected to a number of central topics in contemporary philosophy of language and logic. Several papers have appeared in the past in which Peirce's theory of names has been attested to be a precursor of the causal-historical theory of reference.2 The causal-historical theory in turn has customarily been pigeonholed as the 'new' theories of reference that have been emerging since the 1950s (Devitt 1981; Donellan 1966; Kripke 1980; Marcus 1950; Putnam 1973). Among (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  21.  7
    Ahti-Veikko J. Pietarinen (2015). The Science to Save Us From Philosophy of Science. Axiomathes 25 (2):149-166.
    Are knowledge and belief pivotal in science, as contemporary epistemology and philosophy of science nearly universally take them to be? I defend the view that scientists are not primarily concerned with knowing and that the methods of arriving at scientific hypotheses, models and scenarios do not commit us having stable beliefs about them. Instead, what drives scientific discovery is ignorance that scientists can cleverly exploit. Not an absence or negation of knowledge, ignorance concerns fundamental uncertainty, and is brought out by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  22.  6
    Francesco Bellucci & Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, Peirce’s Logic. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Charles Sanders Peirce: Logic Charles Sanders Peirce was an accomplished scientist, philosopher, and mathematician, who considered himself primarily a logician. His contributions to the development of modern logic at the turn of the 20th century were colossal, original and influential. Formal, or deductive, logic was just one of the branches in which he exercized … Continue reading Peirce’s Logic →.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  23.  9
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2015). Two Papers on Existential Graphs by Charles Peirce. Synthese 192 (4):881-922.
    The following two articles comprise two sets of Charles Peirce’s manuscripts, “Recent Developments of Existential Graphs and their Consequences for Logic” (MS 498, MS 499, MS 490 & S-36, 1906) and “Assurance through Reasoning” (MS 669 & MS 670, 1911), written for the National Academy of Sciences meetings in 1906 and 1911. The papers are deposited at Houghton Library, Harvard University. Only some parts of MS 470 have been published before, and in somewhat defective form. Although “Assurance” follows “Recent Developments” (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  24.  15
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2004). Grice in the Wake of Peirce. Pragmatics and Cognition 12 (2):295-316.
    I argue that many of the pragmatic notions that are commonly attributed to 1-1. P. Grice, or are reported to be inspired by his work on pragmatics, such as assertion, conventional implicature, cooperation, common ground, common knowledge, presuppositions and conversational strategies, have their origins in C. S. Peirce's theory of signs and his pragmatic logic and philosophy. Both Grice and Peirce rooted their theories in normative rationality, anti-psychologism and the relevance of assertions. With respect to the post-Gricean era of pragmatics, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   4 citations  
  25.  56
    Veikko Rantala (1982). Quantified Modal Logic: Non-Normal Worlds and Propositional Attitudes. Studia Logica 41 (1):41 - 65.
    One way to obtain a comprehensive semantics for various systems of modal logic is to use a general notion of non-normal world. In the present article, a general notion of modal system is considered together with a semantic framework provided by such a general notion of non-normal world. Methodologically, the main purpose of this paper is to provide a logical framework for the study of various modalities, notably prepositional attitudes. Some specific systems are studied together with semantics using non-normal worlds (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   10 citations  
  26.  74
    Bernd Stahl, Richard Heersmink, Philippe Goujon, Catherine Flick, Jeroen van den Hoven, Kutoma Wakunuma, Veikko Ikonen & Michael Rader (2010). Issues, Concepts and Methods Relating to the Identification of the Ethics of Emerging ICTs. Communications of the IIMA 10 (1):33-43.
    Ethical issues of information and communication technologies (ICTs) are important because they can have significant effects on human liberty, happiness, their ability to lead a good life. They are also of functional interest because they can determine whether technologies are used and whether their positive potential can unfold. For these reasons policy makers are interested in finding out what these issues are and how they can be addressed. The best way of creating ICT policy that is sensitive to ethical issues (...)
    Translate
      Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  27.  27
    Bernd Carsten Stahl, Richard Heersmink, Philippe Goujon, Catherine Flick, Jeroen van den Hoven, Kutoma Wakunuma, Veikko Ikonen & Michael Rader (2010). Identifying the Ethics of Emerging Information and Communication Technologies: An Essay on Issues, Concepts and Method. International Journal of Technoethics 1 (4):20-38.
    Ethical issues of information and communication technologies (ICTs) are important because they can have significant effects on human liberty, happiness, and people’s ability to lead a good life. They are also of functional interest because they can determine whether technologies are used and whether their positive potential can unfold. For these reasons, policy makers are interested in finding out what these issues are and how they can be addressed. The best way of creating ICT policy that is sensitive to ethical (...)
    Translate
      Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  28.  7
    Veikko Rantala (1978). The Old and the New Logic of Metascience. Synthese 39 (2):233 - 247.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   11 citations  
  29.  12
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen & Gabriel Sandu (2004). If Logic, Game-Theoretical Semantics, and the Philosophy of Science. In S. Rahman J. Symons (ed.), Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science. Kluwer Academic Publisher 105--138.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  30.  13
    Veikko Launis (2003). Solidarity, Genetic Discrimination, and Insurance. Social Theory and Practice 29 (1):87-111.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   4 citations  
  31.  33
    Veikko Rantala (1975). Urn Models: A New Kind of Non-Standard Model for First-Order Logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic 4 (4):455 - 474.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   10 citations  
  32.  8
    Jaakko Hintikka & Veikko Rantala (1976). A New Approach to Infinitary Languages. Annals of Mathematical Logic 10 (1):95-115.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   10 citations  
  33.  16
    Veikko Rantala (1980). On the Logical Basis of the Structuralist Philosophy of Science. Erkenntnis 15 (3):269 - 286.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   11 citations  
  34.  4
    Amirouche Moktefi & Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2015). On the Diagrammatic Representation of Existential Statements with Venn Diagrams. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 24 (4):361-374.
    It is of common use in modern Venn diagrams to mark a compartment with a cross to express its non-emptiness. Modern scholars seem to derive this convention from Charles S. Peirce, with the assumption that it was unknown to John Venn. This paper demonstrates that Venn actually introduced several methods to represent existentials but felt uneasy with them. The resistance to formalize existentials was not limited to diagrammatic systems, as George Boole and his followers also failed to provide a satisfactory (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  35.  21
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2003). Games as Formal Tools Versus Games as Explanations in Logic and Science. Foundations of Science 8 (4):317-364.
    This paper addresses the theoretical notion of a game as it arisesacross scientific inquiries, exploring its uses as a technical andformal asset in logic and science versus an explanatory mechanism. Whilegames comprise a widely used method in a broad intellectual realm(including, but not limited to, philosophy, logic, mathematics,cognitive science, artificial intelligence, computation, linguistics,physics, economics), each discipline advocates its own methodology and aunified understanding is lacking. In the first part of this paper, anumber of game theories in formal studies are critically (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  36.  12
    David Pearce & Veikko Rantala (1983). New Foundations for Metascience. Synthese 56 (1):1 - 26.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   9 citations  
  37.  8
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2006). Independence-Friendly Logic and Games of Incomplete Information. In Johan van Benthem, Gerhard Heinzman, M. Rebushi & H. Visser (eds.), The Age of Alternative Logics. Springer 243--259.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  38.  24
    Helena Siipi & Veikko Launis (2009). Opposition and Acceptance of GM-Food and GM-Medicine. Open Ethics Journal 3 (3):97-103.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  39.  6
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2004). Semantic Games in Logic and Epistemology. In S. Rahman J. Symons (ed.), Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science. Kluwer Academic Publisher 57--103.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  40.  19
    Veikko Pelto-Piri, Karin Engström & Ingemar Engström (2013). Paternalism, Autonomy and Reciprocity: Ethical Perspectives in Encounters with Patients in Psychiatric in-Patient Care. BMC Medical Ethics 14 (1):49.
    BackgroundPsychiatric staff members have the power to decide the options that frame encounters with patients. Intentional as well as unintentional framing can have a crucial impact on patients’ opportunities to be heard and participate in the process. We identified three dominant ethical perspectives in the normative medical ethics literature concerning how doctors and other staff members should frame interactions in relation to patients; paternalism, autonomy and reciprocity. The aim of this study was to describe and analyse statements describing real work (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  41.  34
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2006). Peirce's Contributions to Possible-Worlds Semantics. Studia Logica 82 (3):345 - 369.
    A century ago, Charles S. Peirce proposed a logical approach to modalities that came close to possible-worlds semantics. This paper investigates his views on modalities through his diagrammatic logic of Existential Graphs (EGs). The contribution of the gamma part of EGs to the study of modalities is examined. Some ramifications of Peirce’s remarks are presented and placed into a contemporary perspective. An appendix is included that provides a transcription with commentary of Peirce’s unpublished manuscript on modality from 1901.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  42.  38
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2003). Logic, Language Games and Ludics. Acta Analytica 18 (30/31):89-123.
    Wittgenstein’s language games can be put into a wider service by virtue of elements they share with some contemporary opinions concerning logic and the semantics of computation. I will give two examples: manifestations of language games and their possible variations in logical studies, and their role in some of the recent developments in computer science. It turns out that the current paradigm of computation that Girard termed Ludics bears a striking resemblance to members of language games. Moreover, the kind of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  43.  19
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2009). Significs and the Origins of Analytic Philosophy. Journal of the History of Ideas 70 (3):467-490.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  44.  7
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2005). Cultivating Habits of Reason: Peirce and the Logica Utens Versus Logica Docens Distinction. History of Philosophy Quarterly 22 (4):357 - 372.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  45.  13
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2013). Christine Ladd-Franklin's and Victoria Welby's Correspondence with Charles Peirce. Semiotica 2013 (196):139-161.
    Journal Name: Semiotica - Journal of the International Association for Semiotic Studies / Revue de l'Association Internationale de Sémiotique Volume: 2013 Issue: 196 Pages: 139-161.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  46. Veikko Rantala (1977). Aspects of Definability.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   6 citations  
  47. Veikko Rantala (1991). The Work of Art, Identity and Interpretation. Semiotica 87 (3-4):271-292.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  48.  6
    David Pearce & Veikko Rantala (1982). Constructing a General Model of Theory Dynamics. Bulletin of the Section of Logic 11 (1/2):56-60.
    Though formal metascience has made rapid advances over the past few decades, it has seldom been seen to contribute much to the rational reconstruction of scientic development; for the most part, logical concepts have found application in the synchronic analysis of scientic theories. It should be important, therefore, to consider to what extent diachronic or dynamic aspects of scientic theorizing may also be captured within the connes of a formal metascientic framework, and what tools are best suited for constructing a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  49.  24
    Veikko Launis (2002). Human Gene Therapy and the Slippery Slope Argument. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 5 (2):169-179.
    The article investigates the validity of two different versions of the slippery slope argument construed in relation to human gene therapy: the empirical and the conceptual argument. The empirical version holds that our accepting somatic cell therapy will eventually cause our accepting eugenic medical goals. The conceptual version holds that we are logically committed to accepting such goals once we have accepted somatic cell therapy. It is argued that neither the empirical nor the conceptual version of the argument can provide (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  50.  7
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen (2014). A Scholastic-Realist Modal-Structuralism. Philosophia Scientiæ 18:127-138.
    How are we to understand the talk about properties of structures the existence of which is conditional upon the assumption of the reality of those structures? Mathematics is not about abstract objects, yet unlike fictionalism, modal-structuralism respects the truth of theorems and proofs. But it is nominalistic with respect to possibilia. The problem is that, for fear of reducing possibilia to actualities, the second-order modal logic that claims to axiomatise modal existence has no real semantics. There is no cross-identification of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
1 — 50 / 110