Results for 'best interest standard'

994 found
Order:
  1. The Best-Interests Standard as Threshold, Ideal, and Standard of Reasonableness.L. M. Kopelman - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (3):271-289.
    The best-interests standard is a widely used ethical, legal, and social basis for policy and decision-making involving children and other incompetent persons. It is under attack, however, as self-defeating, individualistic, unknowable, vague, dangerous, and open to abuse. The author defends this standard by identifying its employment, first, as a threshold for intervention and judgment (as in child abuse and neglect rulings), second, as an ideal to establish policies or prima facie duties, and, third, as a standard (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  2.  48
    The Best Interest Standard: Both Guide and Limit to Medical Decision Making on Behalf of Incapacitated Patients.Thaddeus Mason Pope - 2011 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 22 (2):134-138.
    In this issue of JCE, Douglas Diekema argues that the best interest standard (BIS) has been misemployed to serve two materially different functions. On the one hand, clinicians and parents use the BIS to recommend and to make treatment decisions on behalf of children. On the other hand, clinicians and state authorities use the BIS to determine when the government should interfere with parental decision-making authority. Diekema concedes that the BIS is appropriately used to “guide” parents in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  3.  44
    The best interest standard and children: clarifying a concept and responding to its critics.Johan Christiaan Bester - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (2):117-124.
    This work clarifies the role of the best interest standard (BIS) as ethical principle in the medical care of children. It relates the BIS to the ethical framework of medical practice. The BIS is shown to be a general principle in medical ethics, providing grounding to prima facie obligations. The foundational BIS of Kopelman and Buchanan and Brock are reviewed and shown to be in agreement with the BIS here defended. Critics describe the BIS as being too (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  4.  26
    The Best Interest Standard for Health Care Decision Making: Definition and Defense.Thaddeus Mason Pope - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):36-38.
    Bester offers powerful arguments for why the harm principle cannot replace the best interest standard (BIS) as a guide for, and limit on, surrogate healthcare decision making (Bester 2018). Since B...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  78
    The Best Interests Standard for Incompetent or Incapacitated Persons of All Ages.Loretta M. Kopelman - 2007 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 35 (1):187-196.
    When making decisions for adults who lack decision-making capacity and have no discernable preferences, widespread support exists for using the Best Interests Standard. This policy appeals to adults and is compatible with many important recommendations for persons facing end-of-life choices.Common objections to the policy are discussed as well as different meanings of this Standard identified, such as using it to express goals or ideals and to make practical decisions incorporating what reasonable persons would want. For reasons of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  6.  11
    The Best Interest Standard Is the Best We Have: Why the Harm Principle and Constrained Parental Autonomy Cannot Replace the Best Interest Standard in Pediatric Ethics.Johan C. Bester - 2019 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 30 (3):223-231.
    While the best interest standard (BIS) enjoys wide endorsement as the ethical and decision-making standard in pediatrics, it has been criticized as vague and indeterminate. Alternate decision-making standards have been proposed to replace or augment the BIS, notably the harm principle (HP) and constrained parental autonomy (CPA) model. In this edition of The Journal of Clinical Ethics, Lainie Friedman Ross argues that CPA is a better standard than the BIS or the HP as both guide (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  45
    The Best Interest Standard and the Child’s Right to an Open Future.Aliya O. Affdal & Vardit Ravitsky - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):74-76.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  37
    The Best Interest Standard: Same Name but Different Roles in Pediatric Bioethics and Child Rights Frameworks.Lainie Friedman Ross & Alissa Hurwitz Swota - 2017 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 60 (2):186-197.
    The "best interest of the child" standard is central to both pediatric bioethics and the child rights community. In pediatric bioethics in the United States, the best interest of the child standard is cited as the guidance principle for parental decision-making.1 Likewise, in the child rights community, the best interest of the child standard is "of paramount consideration" ). Both approaches also recognize parental rights and responsibilities and support a role for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Clarifying the best interests standard: the elaborative and enumerative strategies in public policy-making.Chong Ming Lim, Michael C. Dunn & Jacqueline J. Chin - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (8):542-549.
    One recurring criticism of the best interests standard concerns its vagueness, and thus the inadequate guidance it offers to care providers. The lack of an agreed definition of ‘best interests’, together with the fact that several suggested considerations adopted in legislation or professional guidelines for doctors do not obviously apply across different groups of persons, result in decisions being made in murky waters. In response, bioethicists have attempted to specify the best interests standard, to reduce (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  10.  69
    Revisiting the Best Interest Standard: Uses and Misuses.Douglas S. Diekema - 2011 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 22 (2):128-133.
    The best interest standard is the threshold most frequently employed by physicians and ethics consultants in challenging a parent’s refusal to provide consent for a child’s medical care. In this article, I will argue that the best interest standard has evolved to serve two different functions, and that these functions differ sufficiently that they require separate standards. While the best interest standard is appropriate for choosing among alternative treatment options for children, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  11.  25
    The Best Interest Standard: An Exhaustive Guide for Medical Decision Making in Pediatrics?Eva De Clercq & Katharina Ruhe - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):69-71.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  20
    The Best Interests Standard as a Logic of Empire: Unpacking the Political Dimensions of Parental Refusal.Carey DeMichelis - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):83-85.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. Der best-interest standard in der Pädiatrie–theoretische Konzeption und klinische Anwendung.Andrea Dörries - 2003 - In C. Wiesemann, A. Dörries, G. Wolfslast & A. Simon (eds.), Das Kind Als Patient. Campus.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  40
    The Best-Interest Standard: Surrogate Decision Making and Quality of Life.James F. Drane & John L. Coulehan - 1995 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 6 (1):20-29.
  15.  49
    Using the best interests standard to decide whether to test children for untreatable, late-onset genetic diseases.Loretta M. Kopelman - 2007 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 32 (4):375 – 394.
    A new analysis of the Best Interests Standard is given and applied to the controversy about testing children for untreatable, severe late-onset genetic diseases, such as Huntington's disease or Alzheimer's disease. A professional consensus recommends against such predictive testing, because it is not in children's best interest. Critics disagree. The Best Interests Standard can be a powerful way to resolve such disputes. This paper begins by analyzing its meaning into three necessary and jointly sufficient (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  16. International Consensus Based Review and Recommendations for Minimum Reporting Standards in Research on Transcutaneous Vagus Nerve Stimulation.Adam D. Farmer, Adam Strzelczyk, Alessandra Finisguerra, Alexander V. Gourine, Alireza Gharabaghi, Alkomiet Hasan, Andreas M. Burger, Andrés M. Jaramillo, Ann Mertens, Arshad Majid, Bart Verkuil, Bashar W. Badran, Carlos Ventura-Bort, Charly Gaul, Christian Beste, Christopher M. Warren, Daniel S. Quintana, Dorothea Hämmerer, Elena Freri, Eleni Frangos, Eleonora Tobaldini, Eugenijus Kaniusas, Felix Rosenow, Fioravante Capone, Fivos Panetsos, Gareth L. Ackland, Gaurav Kaithwas, Georgia H. O'Leary, Hannah Genheimer, Heidi I. L. Jacobs, Ilse Van Diest, Jean Schoenen, Jessica Redgrave, Jiliang Fang, Jim Deuchars, Jozsef C. Széles, Julian F. Thayer, Kaushik More, Kristl Vonck, Laura Steenbergen, Lauro C. Vianna, Lisa M. McTeague, Mareike Ludwig, Maria G. Veldhuizen, Marijke De Couck, Marina Casazza, Marius Keute, Marom Bikson, Marta Andreatta, Martina D'Agostini, Mathias Weymar, Matthew Betts, Matthias Prigge, Michael Kaess, Michael Roden, Michelle Thai, Nathaniel M. Schuster & Nico Montano - 2021 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 14.
    Given its non-invasive nature, there is increasing interest in the use of transcutaneous vagus nerve stimulation across basic, translational and clinical research. Contemporaneously, tVNS can be achieved by stimulating either the auricular branch or the cervical bundle of the vagus nerve, referred to as transcutaneous auricular vagus nerve stimulation and transcutaneous cervical VNS, respectively. In order to advance the field in a systematic manner, studies using these technologies need to adequately report sufficient methodological detail to enable comparison of results (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  25
    International Consensus Based Review and Recommendations for Minimum Reporting Standards in Research on Transcutaneous Vagus Nerve Stimulation.Adam D. Farmer, Adam Strzelczyk, Alessandra Finisguerra, Alexander V. Gourine, Alireza Gharabaghi, Alkomiet Hasan, Andreas M. Burger, Andrés M. Jaramillo, Ann Mertens, Arshad Majid, Bart Verkuil, Bashar W. Badran, Carlos Ventura-Bort, Charly Gaul, Christian Beste, Christopher M. Warren, Daniel S. Quintana, Dorothea Hämmerer, Elena Freri, Eleni Frangos, Eleonora Tobaldini, Eugenijus Kaniusas, Felix Rosenow, Fioravante Capone, Fivos Panetsos, Gareth L. Ackland, Gaurav Kaithwas, Georgia H. O'Leary, Hannah Genheimer, Heidi I. L. Jacobs, Ilse Van Diest, Jean Schoenen, Jessica Redgrave, Jiliang Fang, Jim Deuchars, Jozsef C. Széles, Julian F. Thayer, Kaushik More, Kristl Vonck, Laura Steenbergen, Lauro C. Vianna, Lisa M. McTeague, Mareike Ludwig, Maria G. Veldhuizen, Marijke De Couck, Marina Casazza, Marius Keute, Marom Bikson, Marta Andreatta, Martina D'Agostini, Mathias Weymar, Matthew Betts, Matthias Prigge, Michael Kaess, Michael Roden, Michelle Thai, Nathaniel M. Schuster & Nico Montano - 2021 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 14.
    Given its non-invasive nature, there is increasing interest in the use of transcutaneous vagus nerve stimulation across basic, translational and clinical research. Contemporaneously, tVNS can be achieved by stimulating either the auricular branch or the cervical bundle of the vagus nerve, referred to as transcutaneous auricular vagus nerve stimulation and transcutaneous cervical VNS, respectively. In order to advance the field in a systematic manner, studies using these technologies need to adequately report sufficient methodological detail to enable comparison of results (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  11
    Better than Best (Interest Standard) in Pediatric Decision Making.Lainie Friedman Ross - 2019 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 30 (3):183-195.
    Healthcare decision making for children has adopted the best interest of the child standard, a principle originally employed by judges to adjudicate child placement in the case of parental death, divorce, or incompetence. Philosophers and medical ethicists have argued whether the best interest principle is a guidance principle (informing parents on how they should make healthcare decisions for their child), an intervention principle (deciding the limits of parental autonomy in healthcare decision making), or both. Those (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  27
    Why the Best Interest Standard Is Not Self-Defeating, Too Individualistic, Unknowable, Vague or Subjective.Loretta M. Kopelman - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):34-36.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  20.  42
    Using the best-interests standard in treatment decisions for young children.Loretta M. Kopelman - forthcoming - Pediatric Bioethics.
  21.  73
    The Harm Principle Cannot Replace the Best Interest Standard: Problems With Using the Harm Principle for Medical Decision Making for Children.Johan Christiaan Bester - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):9-19.
    For many years the prevailing paradigm for medical decision making for children has been the best interest standard. Recently, some authors have proposed that Mill’s “harm principle” should be used to mediate or to replace the best interest standard. This article critically examines the harm principle movement and identifies serious defects within the project of using Mill’s harm principle for medical decision making for children. While the harm principle proponents successfully highlight some difficulties in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  22.  8
    Nancy Cruzan and the best interest standard.R. M. Veatch - 1990 - Midwest Medical Ethics: A Publication of the Midwest Bioethics Center 6 (4):17.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  15
    Rumors of the Best Interest Standard’s Demise Have Been Greatly Exaggerated, and the Harm Principle Remains Tenuous: Responding to My Commentators.Johan Christiaan Bester - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):W1-W5.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  59
    Using a new analysis of the best interests standard to address cultural disputes: Whose data, which values?Loretta M. Kopelman & Arthur E. Kopelman - 2007 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 28 (5):373-391.
    Clinicians sometimes disagree about how much to honor surrogates’ deeply held cultural values or traditions when they differ from those of the host country. Such a controversy arose when parents requested a cultural accommodation to let their infant die by withdrawing life saving care. While both the parents and clinicians claimed to be using the Best Interests Standard to decide what to do, they were at an impasse. This standard is analyzed into three necessary and jointly sufficient (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  25.  31
    Is ‘best interests’ the right standard in cases like that of Charlie Gard?Robert D. Truog - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (1):16-17.
    Savulescu and colleagues have provided interesting insights into how the UK public view the ‘best interests’ of children like Charlie Gard. But is best interests the right standard for evaluating these types of cases? In the USA, both clinical decisions and legal judgments tend to follow the ‘harm principle’, which holds that parental choices for their children should prevail unless their decisions subject the child to avoidable harm. The case of Charlie Gard, and others like it, show (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  26.  98
    Deciding for a child: a comprehensive analysis of the best interest standard[REVIEW]Erica K. Salter - 2012 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 33 (3):179-198.
    This article critically examines, and ultimately rejects, the best interest standard as the predominant, go-to ethical and legal standard of decision making for children. After an introduction to the presumption of parental authority, it characterizes and distinguishes six versions of the best interest standard according to two key dimensions related to the types of interests emphasized. Then the article brings three main criticisms against the best interest standard: (1) that it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  27.  84
    Rejecting the baby Doe rules and defending a "negative" analysis of the best interests standard.Loretta M. Kopelman - 2005 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 30 (4):331 – 352.
    Two incompatible policies exist for guiding medical decisions for extremely premature, sick, or terminally ill infants, the Best Interests Standard and the newer, 20-year old "Baby Doe" Rules. The background, including why there were two sets of Baby Doe Rules, and their differences with the Best Interests Standard, are illustrated. Two defenses of the Baby Doe Rules are considered and rejected. The first, held by Reagan, Koop, and others, is a "right-to-life" defense. The second, held by (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  28.  24
    Neither the Harm Principle nor the Best Interest Standard Should Be Applied to Pediatric Research.Marcin Waligora, Karolina Strzebonska & Mateusz T. Wasylewski - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):72-74.
    Application of either the harm principle or the best interest standard to medical decision making conflicts with some types of pediatric research that pose elevated risk without the reasonable prob...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  21
    Agreed: The Harm Principle Cannot Replace the Best Interest Standard … but the Best Interest Standard Cannot Replace The Harm Principle Either.D. Micah Hester, Kellie R. Lang, Nanibaa' A. Garrison & Douglas S. Diekema - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):38-40.
    In Bester’s article (2018) challenging the use of the harm principle and advocating sole reliance on the use of a best interest standard (BIS) in pediatric decision-making, we believe that the auth...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  64
    Is best interests a relevant decision making standard for enrolling non-capacitated subjects into clinical research?Jeffrey T. Berger - 2011 - Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (1):45-49.
    The ‘best interests’ decision making standard is used in clinical care to make necessary health decisions for non-capacitated individuals for whom neither explicit nor inferred wishes are known. It has been also widely acknowledged as a basis for enrolling some non-capacitated adults into clinical research such as emergency, critical care, and dementia research. However, the best interests standard requires that choices provide the highest net benefit of available options, and clinical research rarely meets this criterion. In (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31.  49
    Non-beneficial pediatric research and the best interests standard: A legal and ethical reconciliation (8th edition).Paul Litton - 2008 - Yale Journal of Health Law 8.
    Federal efforts beginning in the 1990's have successfully increased pediatric research to improve medical care for all children. Since 1997, the FDA has requested 800 pediatric studies involving 45,000 children. Much of this research is "non-beneficial"; that is, it exposes pediatric subjects to risk even though these children will not benefit from participating in the research. Non-beneficial pediatric research (NBPR) seems, by definition, contrary to the best interests of pediatric subjects, which is why one state supreme court has essentially (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  32.  40
    Predictive Genetic Testing of Children and the Role of the Best Interest Standard: Currents in Contemporary Bioethics.Lainie Friedman Ross - 2013 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 41 (4):899-906.
    The “best interest standard” is the guidance principle for pediatric healthcare in the United States (US) and the United Kingdom (UK). In the UK, the best interest standard may also be used as an intervention principle when parents make good but non-ideal decisions whereas intervention in the US requires a determination of abuse or neglect. I examine whether and how the different uses of the best interest standard influence predictive genetic testing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  29
    Surrogate decision making for unrepresented patients: Proposing a harm reduction interpretation of the best interest standard.Nada Gligorov & Phoebe Friesen - 2020 - Clinical Ethics 15 (2):57-64.
    Unrepresented patients are individuals who lack decision makingcapacity and have no family or friends to make medical decisions for them. This population is growing in number in the United States, particularly within emergency and intensive care settings. While some bioethical discussion has taken place in response to the question of who ought to make decisions for these patients, the issue of how surrogate medical decisions ought to be made for this population remains unexplored. In this paper, we argue that (...) applications of surrogate decision making principles in health care are not well suited to many unrepresented patients with long-term mental health diagnosis. We argue that when applied to this population, the substituted judgment standard, designed to preserve patient preferences and values, may lead to the exclusion of their preferences. We argue further that the application of the best interest standard runs the risk of leading to harmful cases of overtreatment or undertreatment. We offer an alternative interpretation of the best interest principle that is better able to promote the well-being of unrepresented patients, especially for those who lack capacity because of mental disorders. This alternative is based on the practices and principles of harm reduction and includes three components: emphasis on considering the expressed preferences of unrepresented patients, a focus on reducing harm as well as the delivery of clinical benefits, and a recognition of the importance of promoting trust. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  5
    When Better Isn’t Good Enough: Commentary on Ross’s “Better than Best (Interest Standard) in Pediatric Decision Making”.Erica K. Salter - 2019 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 30 (3):213-217.
    In this commentary, the author discusses two strengths and two weaknesses of “Better than Best (Interest Standard) in Pediatric Decision-Making,” in which Lainie Friedman Ross critiques the best interest standard and proposes her own model of constrained parental autonomy (CPA) as a preferable replacement for both an intervention principle and a guidance principle in pediatric decision making. The CPA’s strengths are that it detaches from the language and concept of “best” and that it (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  3
    Offering the “Reasonable Interests Standard” in Response to Ross’s Analysis of the Best Interest Standard.D. Micah Hester - 2019 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 30 (3):196-200.
    Ross’s argument against the best interest standard (BIS) makes a clear case for the problems of the BIS, and she also notes challenges with such notions as the harm principle. In light of these critiques, Ross champions her longstanding pediatric moral norm for decision making, constrained parental autonomy (CPA). This article argues that while Ross’s critique of the traditional accounts of the BIS is correct, her solution still raises some concerns. As such, I offer the “reasonable interests (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  23
    The “Reasonable Subject Standard” as an Alternative to the “Best Interest Standard”.Joseph Millum - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):66-67.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  92
    Children and Bioethics: Uses and Abuses of the Best-Interests Standard.L. M. Kopelman - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (3):213-217.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  38.  18
    Predictive Genetic Testing of Children and the Role of the Best Interest Standard: Currents in Contemporary Bioethics.Lainie Friedman Ross - 2013 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 41 (4):899-906.
    The genetic testing and screening of children has been fraught with controversy since Robert Guthrie developed the bacterial inhibition assay to test for phenylketonuria and advocated for rapid uptake of universal newborn screening in the early 1960s. Today with fast and affordable mass screening of the whole genome on the horizon, the debate about when and in what scenarios children should undergo genetic testing and screening has gained renewed attention. United States professional guidelines — both the American College of Medical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  16
    DCDD and Children: A Defense of the “Best Interests” Standard.Pablo De Lora - 2015 - American Journal of Bioethics 15 (8):21-22.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  19
    The Harm Principle and the Best Interests Standard: Are Aspirational or Minimal Standards the Key?Giles Birchley - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):32-34.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  28
    The Harms of a Duty: Misapplication of the Best Interest Standard.Naomi Laventhal & Melissa Constantine - 2012 - American Journal of Bioethics 12 (4):17-19.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 12, Issue 4, Page 17-19, April 2012.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  18
    Antemortem Donor Bilateral Nephrectomy: A Violation of the Patient's Best Interests Standard.Thomas M. Wertin, Mohamed Y. Rady & Joseph L. Verheijde - 2012 - American Journal of Bioethics 12 (6):17-20.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 12, Issue 6, Page 17-20, June 2012.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  31
    Best Interests in the MCA 2005—What can Healthcare Law Learn from Family Law?Shazia Choudhry - 2008 - Health Care Analysis 16 (3):240-251.
    The ‘best interests’ standard is a highly seductive standard in English law. Not only does it appear to be fairly uncontroversial but it also presents as the most sensible, objective and ‘fair’ method of dealing with decision making on behalf of those who are perceived to be the most vulnerable within society. This article aims to provide a critical appraisal of how the standard has been applied within family law, to outline how the standard is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  21
    Best Interests, the Power of the Medical Profession, and the Power of the Judiciary.Muireann Quigley - 2008 - Health Care Analysis 16 (3):233-239.
    This paper is a response to a paper by John Coggon ‘Best Interests, Public Interest, and the Power of the Medical Profession'. It argues that certain legal judgements in relation to best interests seek to change and curtail the role of the medical profession in this arena while simultaneously extending the jurisdiction of the courts. It also argues that we must guard against replacing one professional standard, that of the medical profession, with another, that of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  43
    Best Interest of the Child: Surrogate Decision Making and the Economics of Externalities. [REVIEW]Joseph P. DeMarco, Douglas P. Powell & Douglas O. Stewart - 2011 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 8 (3):289-298.
    The case of Twin B involves the decision to send a newborn to a less intensive Level 2 special care nursery (SCN) than to the Level 3 neonatal intensive care unit (NICU) that is considered optimal by the physician. The physician’s acceptance of the transfer is against the child’s best interest and is due to parental convenience. In analyzing the case, we reject the best interest standard. Our rejection is partly supported by the views of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46.  95
    Value Theory and the Best Interests Standard1.David Degrazia - 1995 - Bioethics 9 (1):50-61.
    The idea of a patient's best interests raises issues in prudential value theory–the study of what makes up an individual's ultimate (nonmoral) good or well‐being. While this connection may strike a philosopher as obvious, the literature on the best interests standard reveals almost no engagement of recent work in value theory. There seems to be a growing sentiment among bioethicists that their work is independent of philosophical theorizing. Is this sentiment wrong in the present case? Does value (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  47.  41
    Standards for Family Decisions: Replacing Best Interests with Harm Prevention.Rebecca Dresser - 2003 - American Journal of Bioethics 3 (2):54-55.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  48.  27
    Neonatal Decision-Making: Beyond the Standard of Best Interests.Robert D. Truog & Sadath A. Sayeed - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (2):44 - 45.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49.  23
    Evaluating the Harm Principle and the Best Interest of the Child: A Case Resolved Using Standard Microeconomics Principles.Douglas O. Stewart & Joseph P. De Marco - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):76-78.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  10
    Respect for Patient Through Clinical Ethics and Standard of Best Interest.Lezley Anderson - 2017 - American Journal of Bioethics 17 (7):69-71.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 994