Results for 'brain architecture'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  74
    Mind architecture and brain architecture.Camilo J. Cela-Conde & Gisèle Marty - 1997 - Biology and Philosophy 12 (3):327-340.
    The use of the computer metaphor has led to the proposal of mind architecture (Pylyshyn 1984; Newell 1990) as a model of the organization of the mind. The dualist computational model, however, has, since the earliest days of psychological functionalism, required that the concepts mind architecture and brain architecture be remote from each other. The development of both connectionism and neurocomputational science, has sought to dispense with this dualism and provide general models of consciousness – a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. The architect's brain: neuroscience, creativity, and architecture.Harry Francis Mallgrave - 2010 - Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Introduction -- Historical essays -- The humanist brain : Alberti, Vitruvius, and Leonardo -- The enlightened brain : Perrault, Laugier, and Le Roy -- The sensational brain : Burke, Price, and Knight -- The transcendental brain : Kant and Schopenhauer -- The animate brain : Schinkel, Bötticher, and Semper -- The empathetic brain : Vischer, Wölfflin, and Göller -- The gestalt brain : the dynamics of the sensory field -- The neurological brain (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  3. Phenomenological architecture of a mind and Operational Architectonics of the brain: the unified metastable continuum.Andrew A. Fingelkurts, Alexander A. Fingelkurts & Carlos F. H. Neves - 2009 - Journal of New Mathematics and Natural Computing. Special Issue on Neurodynamic Correlates of Higher Cognition and Consciousness: Theoretical and Experimental Approaches - in Honor of Walter J Freeman's 80th Birthday 5 (1):221-244.
    In our contribution we will observe phenomenal architecture of a mind and operational architectonics of the brain and will show their intimate connectedness within a single integrated metastable continuum. The notion of operation of different complexity is the fundamental and central one in bridging the gap between brain and mind: it is precisely by means of this notion that it is possible to identify what at the same time belongs to the phenomenal conscious level and to the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  4. Brain-inspired conscious computing architecture.Włodzisław Duch - 2005 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 26 (1-2):1-21.
    What type of artificial systems will claim to be conscious and will claim to experience qualia? The ability to comment upon physical states of a brain-like dynamical system coupled with its environment seems to be sufficient to make claims. The flow of internal states in such system, guided and limited by associative memory, is similar to the stream of consciousness. Minimal requirements for an artificial system that will claim to be conscious were given in form of specific architecture (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5. Yale University, Department ot Psychology, PO Box 208205, New Haven, CT 06520-8205 Mental Processes and Brain Architecture: Confronting the Complex Adaptive Systems of Human Thought (An Overview). [REVIEW]Jerome L. Singer - 1995 - In Harold J. Morowitz & Jerome L. Singer (eds.), The Mind, the Brain, and Complex Adaptive Systems. Addison-Wesley. pp. 22--3.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Brain-Inspired Conscious Computing Architecture.Wlodzislaw Duch - 2005 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 26 (1-2):1-22.
    What type of artificial systems will claim to be conscious and will claim to experience qualia? The ability to comment upon physical states of a brain-like dynamical system coupled with its environment seems to be sufficient to make claims. The flow of internal states in such systems, guided and limited by associative memory, is similar to the stream of consciousness. A specific architecture of an artificial system, termed articon, is introduced that by its very design has to claim (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  7.  36
    Walking through Architectural Spaces: The Impact of Interior Forms on Human Brain Dynamics.Maryam Banaei, Javad Hatami, Abbas Yazdanfar & Klaus Gramann - 2017 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11:289961.
    Neuroarchitecture uses neuroscientific tools to better understand architectural design and its impact on human perception and subjective experience. The form or shape of the built environment is fundamental to architectural design, but not many studies have shown the impact of different forms on the inhabitants’ emotions. This study investigated the neurophysiological correlates of different interior forms on the perceivers’ affective state and the accompanying brain activity. To understand the impact of naturalistic three-dimensional (3D) architectural forms, it is essential to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  26
    The architecture challenge: Future artificial-intelligence systems will require sophisticated architectures, and knowledge of the brain might guide their construction.Gianluca Baldassarre, Vieri Giuliano Santucci, Emilio Cartoni & Daniele Caligiore - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. A functional architecture of the human brain: emerging insights from the science of emotion.Kristen A. Lindquist & Lisa Feldman Barrett - 2012 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 16 (11):533-540.
  10.  39
    When Neuroscience ‘Touches’ Architecture: From Hapticity to a Supramodal Functioning of the Human Brain.Paolo Papale, Leonardo Chiesi, Alessandra C. Rampinini, Pietro Pietrini & Emiliano Ricciardi - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7:186785.
    In the last decades, the rapid growth of functional brain imaging methodologies allowed cognitive neuroscience to address open questions in philosophy and the social sciences. At the same time, novel insights from cognitive neuroscience research have begun to influence various disciplines, leading to a turn to cognition and emotion in the fields of planning and architectural design. Since 2003, the Academy of Neuroscience for Architecture has been supporting ‘neuro-architecture’ as a way to connect neuroscience and the study (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  22
    The Endogenously Active Brain: The Need for an Alternative Cognitive Architecture.William Bechtel - 2013 - Philosophia Scientiae 17:3-30.
    La plupart des projets d’architectures cognitives dans les sciences cognitives et des explications des processus cérébraux dans les neurosciences interprètent l’esprit/cerveau comme réactif : le processus est déclenché par un stimulus et se termine par une réponse. Mais il y a de plus en plus de données laissant penser que le cerveau est endogéniquement actif : des oscillations de l’activité électrochimique à de multiples fréquences ont lieu dans le cerveau même en l’absence de stimuli et ceux-ci servent plutôt à moduler (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  12.  23
    The Endogenously Active Brain: The Need for an Alternative Cognitive Architecture.William Bechtel - 2013 - Philosophia Scientiae 17 (2):3-30.
    La plupart des projets d’architectures cognitives dans les sciences cognitives et des explications des processus cérébraux dans les neurosciences interprètent l’esprit/cerveau comme réactif : le processus est déclenché par un stimulus et se termine par une réponse. Mais il y a de plus en plus de données laissant penser que le cerveau est endogéniquement actif : des oscillations de l’activité électrochimique à de multiples fréquences ont lieu dans le cerveau même en l’absence de stimuli et ceux-ci servent plutôt à moduler (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  36
    A System Architecture Approach to the Brain: From Neurons to Consciousness.L. Andrew Coward - 2005 - Nova Biomedical Books.
    This book is the integrated presentation of a large body of work on understanding the operation of biological brains as systems.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  17
    An astonishingly intricate architecture: Visual Music of the Brain and Mind.Terry Trickett - 2018 - Technoetic Arts 16 (1):5-22.
    The overarching guiding principle of Alan Turing’s work was directed towards modelling the human mind as a machine. It is extraordinary that Turing introduced, in his early papers, ideas that are only now beginning to be investigated. Throughout his life, he considered conjectures to be of great importance because they suggest useful lines of research. In my own conjecture, I am asking the question: what is the brain’s geometry? Can it ever be unravelled, or does its complexity defy any (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  32
    Consciousness in a multilevel architecture: Evidence from the right side of the brain.Boris M. Velichkovsky, Olga A. Krotkova, Artemy A. Kotov, Vyacheslav A. Orlov, Vitaly M. Verkhlyutov, Vadim L. Ushakov & Maxim G. Sharaev - 2018 - Consciousness and Cognition 64:227-239.
  16.  11
    The Functional Architecture of the Brain Underlies Strategic Deception in Impression Management.Qiang Luo, Yina Ma, Meghana A. Bhatt, P. Read Montague & Jianfeng Feng - 2017 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11.
  17.  65
    Toward a Model of Functional Brain Processes I: Central Nervous System Functional Micro-architecture.Mark H. Bickhard - 2015 - Axiomathes 25 (3):217-238.
    Standard semantic information processing models—information in; information processed; information out —lend themselves to standard models of the functioning of the brain in terms, e.g., of threshold-switch neurons connected via classical synapses. That is, in terms of sophisticated descendants of McCulloch and Pitts models. I argue that both the cognition and the brain sides of this framework are incorrect: cognition and thought are not constituted as forms of semantic information processing, and the brain does not function in terms (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18.  51
    Toward a Model of Functional Brain Processes II: Central Nervous System Functional Macro-architecture.Mark H. Bickhard - 2015 - Axiomathes 25 (4):377-407.
    The first paper in this pair (Bickhard in Axiomathes, 2015) developed a model of the nature of representation and cognition, and argued for a model of the micro-functioning of the brain on the basis of that model. In this sequel paper, starting with part III, this model is extended to address macro-functioning in the CNS. In part IV, I offer a discussion of an approach to brain functioning that has some similarities with, as well as differences from, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  19. Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis.Jerry A. Fodor & Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1988 - Cognition 28 (1-2):3-71.
    This paper explores the difference between Connectionist proposals for cognitive a r c h i t e c t u r e a n d t h e s o r t s o f m o d e l s t hat have traditionally been assum e d i n c o g n i t i v e s c i e n c e . W e c l a i m t h a t t h (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1119 citations  
  20.  29
    Domains, Brains and Evolution.Michael Wheeler & Anthony Atkinson - 2001 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 49:239-266.
    According to Darwinian thinking, organisms are (for the most part) designed by natural selection, and so are (for the most part) integrated collections of adaptations, where an adaptation is a phenotypic trait that is a specialized response to a particular selection pressure. For animals that make their living in the Arctic, one adaptive problem is how to maintain body temperature above a certain minimum level necessary for survival. Polar bears' thick coats are a response to that selection pressure (surviving in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  19
    What happens to accounts of mind-brain relations if we forgo an architecture of rules and representations?William P. Bechtel - 1986 - Philosophy of Science Association 1986:159 - 171.
    The notion that the mind is a physical symbol system (Newell) with a determinate functional architecture (Pylyshyn) provides a compelling conception of the relation of cognitive inquiry to neuroscience inquiry: cognitive inquiry explores the activity within the symbol system while neuroscience explains how the symbol system is realized in the brain. However, the view the the mind is a physical symbol system is being challenged today by researchers in artificial intelligence who propose that the mind is a connectionist (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. What Happens to Accounts of Mind-Brain Relations If We Forego an Architecture of Rules and Representations?William Bechtel - 1986 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986:159-171.
    The notion that the mind is a physical symbol system with a determinate functional architecture provides a compelling conception of the relation of cognitive inquiry to neuroscience inquiry: cognitive inquiry explores the activity within the symbol system while neuroscience explains how the symbol system is realized in the brain. However, the view the the mind is a physical symbol system is being challenged today by researchers in artificial intelligence who propose that the mind is a connectionist system and (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  2
    What Happens to Accounts of Mind-Brain Relations If We Forego An Architecture of Rules and Representations?.William Bechtel - 1986 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 (1):157-171.
    While some philosophers have assumed that there are only two options for characterizing the ontological status of mental models in cognitive information processing psychology--treating them as nearly autonomous from theories of brain activity (Putnam 1975 and Fodor 1974) or eliminating them in favor of neuroscience accounts (Churchland 1979)-- cognitive scientists have often tacitly assumed a third option. This involves treating the mental models as systems of rules and representations that are instantiated in the nervous system much in the way (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. The Architecture of Mind as a Network of Networks of Natural Computational Processes.Gordana Dodig-Crnkovic - 2015 - Philosophies 1 (1):111--125.
    In discussions regarding models of cognition, the very mention of “computationalism” often incites reactions against the insufficiency of the Turing machine model, its abstractness, determinism, the lack of naturalist foundations, triviality and the absence of clarity. None of those objections, however, concerns models based on natural computation or computing nature, where the model of computation is broader than symbol manipulation or conventional models of computation. Computing nature consists of physical structures that form layered computational architecture, with computation processes ranging (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  41
    Mapping the structural and functional architecture of the brain.Stavroula Kousta - 2013 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 17 (12):595.
  26. The architecture of representation.Rick Grush - 1997 - Philosophical Psychology 10 (1):5-23.
    b>: In this article I outline, apply, and defend a theory of natural representation. The main consequences of this theory are: i) representational status is a matter of how physical entities are used, and specifically is not a matter of causation, nomic relations with the intentional object, or information; ii) there are genuine (brain-)internal representations; iii) such representations are really representations, and not just farcical pseudo-representations, such as attractors, principal components, state-space partitions, or what-have-you;and iv) the theory allows us (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  27.  17
    Cognitive Architecture: From Bio-politics to Noo-politics ; Architecture & Mind in the Age of Communication and Information.Deborah Hauptmann & Warren Neidich (eds.) - 2010 - 010 Publishers.
    "Cognitive Architecture" asks how evolving modalities--from bio-politics to "noo-politics"--can be mapped upon the city under contemporary conditions of urbanization and globalization. Noo-politics, most broadly understood as the power exerted over the life of the mind, reconfigures perception, memory and attention, and also implicates potential ways and means by which neurobiological architecture is undergoing reconfiguration. This volume, motivated by theories such as 'cognitive capitalism' and concepts such as 'neural plasticity, ' shows how architecture and urban processes and products (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  81
    The Leabra architecture: Specialization without modularity.Alexander A. Petrov, David J. Jilk, Randall C. O'Reilly & Michael L. Anderson - 2010 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (4):286-287.
    The posterior cortex, hippocampus, and prefrontal cortex in the Leabra architecture are specialized in terms of various neural parameters, and thus are predilections for learning and processing, but domain-general in terms of cognitive functions such as face recognition. Also, these areas are not encapsulated and violate Fodorian criteria for modularity. Anderson's terminology obscures these important points, but we applaud his overall message.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  97
    A cognitive architecture that combines internal simulation with a global workspace.Murray Shanahan - 2006 - Consciousness and Cognition 15 (2):433-449.
    This paper proposes a brain-inspired cognitive architecture that incorporates approximations to the concepts of consciousness, imagination, and emotion. To emulate the empirically established cognitive efficacy of conscious as opposed to non-conscious information processing in the mammalian brain, the architecture adopts a model of information flow from global workspace theory. Cognitive functions such as anticipation and planning are realised through internal simulation of interaction with the environment. Action selection, in both actual and internally simulated interaction with the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  30.  17
    Encapsulating architecture and encapsulating processes.Patrick Juola - 2002 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (6):759-759.
    Thomas & Karmiloff- Smith raise the excellent and, in retrospect, obvious point that in a dynamic learning environment where feedback is possible, we should expect networks to adapt to damage by altering details of their behavior. We should therefore not expect that developmental disorders should result in “normal” modules. The implications of this point go much further, since interprocess dependency in the brain does not rely only on learned neural connections. This argues strongly against behavioral and process-related definitions, as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  13
    Compositionality in a Parallel Architecture for Language Processing.Giosuè Baggio - 2021 - Cognitive Science 45 (5):e12949.
    Compositionality has been a central concept in linguistics and philosophy for decades, and it is increasingly prominent in many other areas of cognitive science. Its status, however, remains contentious. Here, I reassess the nature and scope of the principle of compositionality (Partee, 1995) from the perspective of psycholinguistics and cognitive neuroscience. First, I review classic arguments for compositionality and conclude that they fail to establish compositionality as a property of human language. Next, I state a new competence argument, acknowledging the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  32.  31
    Cognitive architectures need compliancy, not universality.Richard M. Young - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (5):628-628.
    The criterion of computational universality for an architecture should be replaced by the notion of compliancy, where a model built within an architecture is compliant to the extent that the model allows the architecture to determine the processing. The test should be that the architecture does easily – that is, enables a compliant model to do – what people do easily.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33. Cognition without classical architecture.James W. Garson - 1994 - Synthese 100 (2):291-306.
    Fodor and Pylyshyn (1988) argue that any successful model of cognition must use classical architecture; it must depend upon rule-based processing sensitive to constituent structure. This claim is central to their defense of classical AI against the recent enthusiasm for connectionism. Connectionist nets, they contend, may serve as theories of the implementation of cognition, but never as proper theories of psychology. Connectionist models are doomed to describing the brain at the wrong level, leaving the classical view to account (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  13
    Altered Brain Functional Connectivity Density in Fast-Ball Sports Athletes With Early Stage of Motor Training.Chengbo Yang, Ning Luo, Minfeng Liang, Sihong Zhou, Qian Yu, Jiabao Zhang, Mu Zhang, Jingpu Guo, Hu Wang, Jiali Yu, Qian Cui, Huafu Chen & Qing Gao - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11:530122.
    The human brain shows neuroplastic adaptations induced by motor skill training. However, the description of the plastic architecture of the whole-brain network in resting-state is still limited. In the present study, we aimed to detect how motor training affected the density distribution of whole-brain resting-state functional connectivity (FC) brain in fast-ball student-athletes using resting-state functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) data of student-athletes (SA), and non-athlete healthy controls (NC). The voxel-wise data-driven graph theory approach, namely global (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  15
    Inferring a Cognitive Architecture from Multitask Neuroimaging Data: A Data‐Driven Test of the Common Model of Cognition Using Granger Causality.Holly Sue Hake, Catherine Sibert & Andrea Stocco - 2022 - Topics in Cognitive Science 14 (4):845-859.
    Cognitive architectures (i.e., theorized blueprints on the structure of the mind) can be used to make predictions about the effect of multiregion brain activity on the systems level. Recent work has connected one high-level cognitive architecture, known as the “Common Model of Cognition,” to task-based functional MRI data with great success. That approach, however, was limited in that it was intrinsically top-down, and could thus only be compared with alternate architectures that the experimenter could contrive. In this paper, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  37
    “Parallel architecture” as a variety of stratificationalism.David G. Lockwood - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (6):686-687.
    The model of parallel architecture for language presented by Jackendoff is a kind of stratificational model in the spirit of Sydney Lamb. It differs from the more usual stratificationalism most importantly in its clear commitment to nativism, though the variety of nativism is greatly modified from what is more usual among Chomskyans. The revised model presents a potential for fruitful discussion with proponents of stratificationalism, and the potential for enrichment via a relational implementation.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  22
    Cognitive architectures have limited explanatory power.Prasad Tadepalli - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (5):622-623.
    Cognitive architectures, like programming languages, make commitments only at the implementation level and have limited explanatory power. Their universality implies that it is hard, if not impossible, to justify them in detail from finite quantities of data. It is more fruitful to focus on particular tasks such as language understanding and propose testable theories at the computational and algorithmic levels.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  74
    Domains, brains and evolution.Michael Wheeler & Anthony Atkinson - 2001 - In D. Walsh (ed.), Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement. Cambridge University Press. pp. 239-266.
    According to Darwinian thinking, organisms are designed by natural selection, and so are integrated collections of adaptations, where an adaptation is a phenotypic trait that is a specialized response to a particular selection pressure. For animals that make their living in the Arctic, one adaptive problem is how to maintain body temperature above a certain minimum level necessary for survival. Polar bears' thick coats are a response to that selection pressure . A thick coat makes a positive difference to a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39.  75
    Neural blackboard architectures of combinatorial structures in cognition.van der Velde Frank & de Kamps Marc - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (1):37-70.
    Human cognition is unique in the way in which it relies on combinatorial (or compositional) structures. Language provides ample evidence for the existence of combinatorial structures, but they can also be found in visual cognition. To understand the neural basis of human cognition, it is therefore essential to understand how combinatorial structures can be instantiated in neural terms. In his recent book on the foundations of language, Jackendoff described four fundamental problems for a neural instantiation of combinatorial structures: the massiveness (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  40.  18
    Brain evolution: A matter of constraints and permissions?Emmanuel Gilissen & Robert M. T. Simmons - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (2):284-286.
    The article of Finlay et al. is an excellent example of identifying constraints in the development of the brain, and their implications on brain architecture in evolution. Here we further illustrate the importance of constraints by presenting a few examples of how a small number of biophysical mechanisms or even a single life history parameter can have an enormous impact on brain evolution.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. The Brain Is Both Neurocomputer and Quantum Computer.Stuart R. Hameroff - 2007 - Cognitive Science 31 (6):1035-1045.
    _Figure 1. Dendrites and cell bodies of schematic neurons connected by dendritic-dendritic gap junctions form a laterally connected input_ _layer (“dendritic web”) within a neurocomputational architecture. Dendritic web dynamics are temporally coupled to gamma synchrony_ _EEG, and correspond with integration phases of “integrate and fire” cycles. Axonal firings provide input to, and output from, integration_ _phases (only one input, and three output axons are shown). Cell bodies/soma contain nuclei shown as black circles; microtubule networks_ _pervade the cytoplasm. According to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  42.  26
    The architecture is not exactly parallel: Some modules are more equal than others.Boris B. Velichkovsky, Andrej A. Kibrik & Boris M. Velichkovsky - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (6):692-693.
    Despite its computational elegancy, Jackendoff's proposal to reconcile competing approaches by postulating a parallel architecture for phonological, syntactic, and semantic modules is disappointing. We argue that it is a pragmatic version of the leading module which Jackendoff would probably prefer, but which he does not explicitly acknowledge. This internal conflict leads to several shortcomings and even distortions of information presented in the book.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Architectures of Intelligent Systems.David Kirsh - 1992 - Exploring Brain Functions:293-321.
    Theories of intelligence can be of use to neuroscientists if they: 1. Provide illuminating suggestions about the functional architecture of neural systems; 2. Suggest specific models of processing that neural circuits might implement. The objective of our session was to stand back and consider the prospects for this interdisciplinary exchange.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  12
    Cognitive architectures combine formal and heuristic approaches.Cleotilde Gonzalez & Christian Lebiere - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (3):285 - 286.
    Quantum probability (QP) theory provides an alternative account of empirical phenomena in decision making that classical probability (CP) theory cannot explain. Cognitive architectures combine probabilistic mechanisms with symbolic knowledge-based representations (e.g., heuristics) to address effects that motivate QP. They provide simple and natural explanations of these phenomena based on general cognitive processes such as memory retrieval, similarity-based partial matching, and associative learning.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. A dual-networks architecture of top-down control.Nico U. F. Dosenbach, Damien A. Fair, Alexander L. Cohen, Bradley L. Schlaggar & Steven E. Petersen - 2008 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12 (3):99-105.
  46. Beyond Functional Architecture in Cognitive Neuropsychology: A Reply to Coltheart (2010).David C. Plaut & Karalyn Patterson - 2010 - Topics in Cognitive Science 2 (1):12-14.
    We (Patterson & Plaut, 2009) argued that cognitive neuropsychology has had a limited impact on cognitive science due to a nearly exclusive reliance on (a) single‐case studies, (b) dissociations in cognitive performance, and (c) shallow, box‐and‐arrow theorizing, and we advocated adopting a case‐series methodology, considering associations as well as dissociations, and employing explicit computational modeling in studying “how the brain does its cognitive business.” In reply, Coltheart (2010) claims that our concern is misplaced because cognitive neuropsychology is concerned only (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  48
    The b-I-c-a of biologically inspired cognitive architectures.Andrea Stocco, Christian Lebiere & Alexei V. Samsonovich - 2010 - International Journal of Machine Consciousness 2 (2):171-192.
    Recent years have seen a gradual convergence of seemingly distant research fields over a single goal: understanding and replicating biological intelligence in artifacts. This work presents a general overview on the origin, the state-of-the-art, scientific challenges and the future of Biologically Inspired Cognitive Architecture (BICA) research. Our perspective decomposes the field into the four principal semantic components associated with the BICA challenge that together call for an integration of efforts of researchers across disciplines. Areas and directions of study where (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  14
    Foundations of Language: Brain, Meaning, Grammar, Evolution.Ray Jackendoff - 2002 - Oxford University Press UK.
    Already hailed as a masterpiece, Foundations of Language offers a brilliant overhaul of the last thirty-five years of research in generative linguistics and related fields. "Few books really deserve the cliché 'this should be read by every researcher in the field'," writes Steven Pinker, author of The Language Instinct, "but Ray Jackendoff's Foundations of Language does." Foundations of Language offers a radically new understanding of how language, the brain, and perception intermesh. The book renews the promise of early generative (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   218 citations  
  49.  31
    Commentary on “Consciousness in a multilevel architecture: Evidence from the right side of the brain” by B.M. Velichkovsky et al. [REVIEW]Elkhonon Goldberg - 2019 - Consciousness and Cognition 73:102753.
  50.  32
    Language, Architecture & Integration.Aaron Sloman - unknown
    • These ... have now been joined by ... dynamical systems theory which is being used to interpret brain dynamics on the one hand and language and cognition on the other.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000