Results for 'indirect proof'

995 found
Order:
  1.  23
    Indirect Proof and Inversions of Syllogisms.Roy Dyckhoff - 2019 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 25 (2):196-207.
    By considering the new notion of theinversesof syllogisms such asBarbaraandCelarent, we show how the rule ofIndirect Proof, in the form (no multiple or vacuous discharges) used by Aristotle, may be dispensed with, in a system comprising four basic rules of subalternation or conversion and six basic syllogisms.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  15
    Argumentative aspects of indirect proof.James Gasser - 1992 - Argumentation 6 (1):41-49.
    While direct proof is widely considered the paradigm of the acquisition of knowledge by deductive means, indirect proof has traditionally been criticized as showing merely ‘that’ its conclusion is true and not ‘why’ it is true. This paper accounts for the traditional objection by emphasizing the argumentative role in indirect proof of logical principles such as excluded middle and non-contradiction.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  56
    Frege on Indirect Proof.Ivan Welty - 2011 - History and Philosophy of Logic 32 (3):283-290.
    Frege's account of indirect proof has been thought to be problematic. This thought seems to rest on the supposition that some notion of logical consequence ? which Frege did not have ? is indispensable for a satisfactory account of indirect proof. It is not so. Frege's account is no less workable than the account predominant today. Indeed, Frege's account may be best understood as a restatement of the latter, although from a higher order point of view. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Frege on Axioms, Indirect Proof, and Independence Arguments in Geometry: Did Frege Reject Independence Arguments?Jamie Tappenden - 2000 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 41 (3):271-315.
    It is widely believed that some puzzling and provocative remarks that Frege makes in his late writings indicate he rejected independence arguments in geometry, particularly arguments for the independence of the parallels axiom. I show that this is mistaken: Frege distinguished two approaches to independence arguments and his puzzling remarks apply only to one of them. Not only did Frege not reject independence arguments across the board, but also he had an interesting positive proposal about the logical structure of correct (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  5. Dialectic and Indirect Proof.Clark Butler - 1991 - The Monist 74 (3):422-437.
    Contends that Hegel's reconstruction of valid logic leads to a conception of indirect proof and syllogisms. Clarification of the concept of indirect proof; Reference to previous papers on the subject; Indirect proof as the natural form of deduction.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  17
    Bolzano's criticism of indirect proofs /La critique de Bolzano des preuves indirectes.Johannes Hafner - 1999 - Revue d'Histoire des Sciences 52 (3):385-398.
  7. Thought experiments and indirect proofs in Averroes, Aquinas, and Buridan.Simo Knuuttila & Taneli Kukkonen - 2011 - In Katerina Ierodiakonou & Sophie Roux (eds.), Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts. Brill.
  8. Kant on indirect proofs.Zeljko Loparic - 1991 - O Que Nos Faz Pensar:56-60.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Frege on indirect proof. History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 32.Ivan Welty - 2012 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 18 (2):273-274.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  5
    Ivan Welty. Frege on indirect proof. History and Philosophy of Logic, Vol. 32 , pp. 283–290.Matthias Wille - 2012 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 18 (2):273-274.
  11.  32
    Propositions in Prepositional Logic Provable Only by Indirect Proofs.Jan Ekman - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (1):69-91.
    In this paper it is shown that addition of certain reductions to the standard cut removing reductions of deductions in prepositional logic makes prepositional logic non-normalizable. From this follows that some provable propositions in prepositional logic has no direct proof.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  12.  39
    Remarks on Independence Proofs and Indirect Reference.Günther Eder - 2013 - History and Philosophy of Logic 34 (1):68-78.
    In the last two decades, there has been increasing interest in a re-evaluation of Frege’s stance towards consistency- and independence proofs. Papers by several authors deal with Frege’s views on these topics. In this note, I want to discuss one particular problem, which seems to be a main reason for Frege’s reluctant attitude towards his own proposed method of proving the independence of axioms, namely his view that thoughts, that is, intensional entities are the objects of metatheoretical investigations. This stands (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  11
    Normalization proof for Peano Arithmetic.Annika Siders - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (7-8):921-940.
    A proof of normalization for a classical system of Peano Arithmetic formulated in natural deduction is given. The classical rule of the system is the rule for indirect proof restricted to atomic formulas. This rule does not, due to the restriction, interfere with the standard detour conversions. The convertible detours, numerical inductions and instances of indirect proof concluding falsity are reduced in a way that decreases a vector assigned to the derivation. By interpreting the expressions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  29
    Proof and truth: an anti-realist perspective.Luca Tranchini - 2013 - Pisa: Edizioni ETS. Edited by Luca Tranchini.
    In the first chapter, we discuss Dummett’s idea that the notion of truth arises from the one of the correctness of an assertion. We argue that, in a first-order language, the need of defining truth in terms of the notion of satisfaction, which is yielded by the presence of quantifiers, is structurally analogous to the need of a notion of truth as distinct from the one of correctness of an assertion. In the light of the analogy between predicates in Frege (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  12
    100% Mathematical Proof.Rowan Garnier & John Taylor - 1996 - John Wiley & Son.
    "Proof" has been and remains one of the concepts which characterises mathematics. Covering basic propositional and predicate logic as well as discussing axiom systems and formal proofs, the book seeks to explain what mathematicians understand by proofs and how they are communicated. The authors explore the principle techniques of direct and indirect proof including induction, existence and uniqueness proofs, proof by contradiction, constructive and non-constructive proofs, etc. Many examples from analysis and modern algebra are included. The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Mary Shepherd on the role of proofs in our knowledge of first principles.M. Folescu - 2022 - Noûs 56 (2):473-493.
    This paper examines the role of reason in Shepherd's account of acquiring knowledge of the external world via first principles. Reason is important, but does not have a foundational role. Certain principles enable us to draw the required inferences for acquiring knowledge of the external world. These principles are basic, foundational and, more importantly, self‐evident and thus justified in other ways than by demonstration. Justificatory demonstrations of these principles are neither required, nor possible. By drawing on textual and contextual evidence, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17. What must a proof of incompatibilism prove?Seth Shabo - 2011 - Philosophical Studies 154 (3):361-371.
    Peter van Inwagen has developed two highly influential strategies for establishing incompatibilism about causal determinism and moral responsibility. These have come to be known as ‘the Direct Argument’ and ‘the Indirect Argument,’ respectively. In recent years, the two arguments have attracted closely related criticisms. In each case, it is claimed, the argument does not provide a fully general defense of the incompatibilist’s conclusion. While the critics are right to notice these arguments’ limitations, they have not made it clear what (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18. The Origin of the Indirect Passions in the Treatise: An Analogy Between Books 1 and 2.Haruko Inoue - 2003 - Hume Studies 29 (2):205-221.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume 29, Number 2, November 2003, pp. 205-221 The Origin of the Indirect Passions in the Treatise: An Analogy between Books 1 and 2 HARUKOINOUE 1. The Analogy Between Book 1 and Book 2 If the central design of the Treatise is to demonstrate that "the subjects of the Understanding and Passions make a complete chain of reasoning by themselves" (T 2; SBN xii), as Hume (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  27
    The Origin of the Indirect Passions in the Treatise: An Analogy Between Books 1 and 2.Haruko Inoue - 2003 - Hume Studies 29 (2):205-221.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume 29, Number 2, November 2003, pp. 205-221 The Origin of the Indirect Passions in the Treatise: An Analogy between Books 1 and 2 HARUKOINOUE 1. The Analogy Between Book 1 and Book 2 If the central design of the Treatise is to demonstrate that "the subjects of the Understanding and Passions make a complete chain of reasoning by themselves" (T 2; SBN xii), as Hume (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Formal logic: Classical problems and proofs.Luis M. Augusto - 2019 - London, UK: College Publications.
    Not focusing on the history of classical logic, this book provides discussions and quotes central passages on its origins and development, namely from a philosophical perspective. Not being a book in mathematical logic, it takes formal logic from an essentially mathematical perspective. Biased towards a computational approach, with SAT and VAL as its backbone, this is an introduction to logic that covers essential aspects of the three branches of logic, to wit, philosophical, mathematical, and computational.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  20
    Negation-Free and Contradiction-Free Proof of the Steiner–Lehmus Theorem.Victor Pambuccian - 2018 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 59 (1):75-90.
    By rephrasing quantifier-free axioms as rules of derivation in sequent calculus, we show that the generalized Steiner–Lehmus theorem admits a direct proof in classical logic. This provides a partial answer to a question raised by Sylvester in 1852. We also present some comments on possible intuitionistic approaches.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  22
    Is There a Metaphysical Proof of God's Existence?Piotr Moskal - 2008 - Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 13 (2):167-174.
    What determines whether the procedures for proving the affirmative statement of God's existence may be called a proof? Certainly, it is necessary that all premises be true and that a reliable inference schemata be applied. One premise appears to be the most critical in the theistic argument. This premise is the principle of sufficient reason. I hold the view that the principle of sufficient reason cannot be found among the premises of any metaphysical explanation of reality, so I suggest (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  6
    Is There a Metaphysical Proof of God's Existence?Piotr Moskal - 2008 - Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 13 (2):167-174.
    What determines whether the procedures for proving the affirmative statement of God's existence may be called a proof? Certainly, it is necessary that all premises be true and that a reliable inference schemata be applied. One premise appears to be the most critical in the theistic argument. This premise is the principle of sufficient reason. I hold the view that the principle of sufficient reason cannot be found among the premises of any metaphysical explanation of reality, so I suggest (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  12
    On the Mediate Proof of Transcendental Idealism.Henny Blomme - 2016 - Studia Kantiana 14 (21):11-26.
    Scholars who consider that the Transcendental Analytic contains the core of what Kant calls ‘transcendental idealism’ are mistaken. Indeed, Kant’s transcendental idealism of space, time and spatiotemporal objects is sufficiently proved in the Transcendental Aesthetic and does not depend on complementary claims made later on in the Critique. This does not mean, however, that we are allowed to subscribe to the so-called separability-thesis, which states that we can endorse Kant's views in the Transcendental Logic without endorsing the results of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  33
    Sheffer’s stroke: A study in proof-theoretic harmony.Stephen Read - 1999 - Danish Yearbook of Philosophy 34 (1):7-23.
    In order to explicate Gentzen’s famous remark that the introduction-rules for logical constants give their meaning, the elimination-rules being simply consequences of the meaning so given, we develop natural deduction rules for Sheffer’s stroke, alternative denial. The first system turns out to lack Double Negation. Strengthening the introduction-rules by allowing the introduction of Sheffer’s stroke into a disjunctive context produces a complete system of classical logic, one which preserves the harmony between the rules which Gentzen wanted: all indirect (...) reduces to direct proof. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  12
    An ethics-based ‘identity-proof’ of god’s existence. An ontology for philotherapy.Aleksandar Fatic - 2021 - Filozofija I Društvo 32 (3):428-438.
    A resurgence of scholarly work on proof of God?s existence is noticeable over the past decade, with considerable emphasis on attempts to provide?analytic proof? based on the meanings and logic of various identity statements which constitute premises of the syllogisms of the?proof?. Most recently perhaps, Emmanuel Rutten?s?modal-epistemic proof? has drawn serious academic attention. Like other?analytic? and strictly logical proofs of God?s existence, Rutten?s proof has been found flawed. In this paper I discuss the possibility of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  22
    An exponential lower bound for a constraint propagation proof system based on ordered binary decision diagrams.Jan Krajíček - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (1):227-237.
    We prove an exponential lower bound on the size of proofs in the proof system operating with ordered binary decision diagrams introduced by Atserias, Kolaitis and Vardi [2]. In fact, the lower bound applies to semantic derivations operating with sets defined by OBDDs. We do not assume any particular format of proofs or ordering of variables, the hard formulas are in CNF. We utilize (somewhat indirectly) feasible interpolation. We define a proof system combining resolution and the OBDD (...) system. (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28.  5
    Reconsidering Kant’s Rejection of Indirect Arguments in Transcendental Philosophy.Marcel Buß - 2021 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 25 (1):115-133.
    Immanuel Kant states that indirect arguments are not suitable for the purposes of transcendental philosophy. If he is correct, this affects contemporary versions of transcendental arguments which are often used as an indirect refutation of scepticism. I discuss two reasons for Kant’s rejection of indirect arguments. Firstly, Kant argues that we are prone to misapply the law of excluded middle in philosophical contexts. Secondly, Kant points out that indirect arguments lack some explanatory power. They can show (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  46
    Sātmaka, Nairātmya, and A-Nairātmya: Dharmakīrti’s Counter-Argument Against the Proof of Ātman. [REVIEW]Kyo Kano - 2011 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 39 (4-5):391-410.
    Ātman (soul) and Nairātmya (no soul) are, for the Brahmanical schools and the Buddhists respectively, equally fundamental tenets which neither side can concede to the other. Among the 16 formulations presented by Uddyotakara, the fifteenth, which is a proof of Ātman and is originally an indirect proof ( avīta/āvīta ), is presented in a prasaṅga -style, and contains double negation ( na nairātmyam ) in the thesis. However, it is perhaps Dharmakīrti who first transformed it into a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  10
    QUOTATION3 By Israel Scheffler FOLLOWING Goodman4 in treating inscriptions framed by quotes as concrete general rather than abstract. [REVIEW]an Inscriptional Approach To Indirect - 1997 - In Catherine Z. Elgin (ed.), Nelson Goodman's Theory of Symbols and its Applications. Garland. pp. 237.
  31.  16
    The Faith/History Problem, and Kierkegaard's "A Priori" 'Proof'.M. J. Ferreira - 1987 - Religious Studies 23 (3):337 - 345.
    What has become known as the ‘faith/history’ problem for historical religions like Christianity centres on the attempt to combine the ontological decisiveness, for faith, of an historical event characterized as an actual Incarnation of God with the epistemological indifference, or irrelevance, of historical information about that event which is decisive for faith. Without the former there is nothing to be related to or personally appropriated; without the latter faith is rendered vulnerable to the vagaries of historical research. Soren Kierkegaard's Climacus (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. On the concept of proof in elementary geometry Pirmin stekeler-weithofer.Proof In Elementary - 1992 - In Michael Detlefsen (ed.), Proof and Knowledge in Mathematics. Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Privacy, Sex.An Indirect - 1999 - Journal of Information Ethics 8:10.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Aristotelian syllogisms: Valid arguments or true universalized conditionals?John Corcoran - 1974 - Mind 83 (330):278-281.
    Corcoran, John. 1974. Aristotelian Syllogisms: Valid arguments or true generalized conditionals?, Mind 83, 278–81. MR0532928 (58 #27178) This tightly-written and self-contained four-page paper must be studied and not just skimmed. It meticulously analyses quotations from Aristotle and Lukasiewicz to establish that Aristotle was using indirect deductions—as required by the natural-deduction interpretation—and not indirect proofs—as required by the axiomatic interpretation. Lukasiewicz was explicit and clear about the subtle fact that Aristotle’s practice could not be construed as correctly performed (...) proof. Lukasiewicz evidence is presented fully; it is irrefutable. But, instead of considering the possibility that Aristotle’s discourses were not intended to express indirect proofs of universalized conditions presupposing axiomatic premises, Lukasiewicz came to the amazing conclusion that Aristotle did not understand indirect proof. This paper builds on the admirable Lukasiewicz scholarship to establish a conclusion diametrically opposed to the one Lukasiewicz asserted. This paper points out that if Aristotle had not been establishing an underlying logic but he was instead axiomatizing a theory of terms, Aristotelians could not claim for Aristotle the title Founder of Logic. People who take Euclid, Peano, and Zermelo to have first axiomatized geometry, arithmetic, and set theory, respectively, do not think that this qualifies them for the titles Founder of Geometry, Founder of Arithmetic, and Founder of Set Theory, respectively. Such people do think that this would qualify the three for the titles Founder of Axiomatic Geometry, Founder of Axiomatic Arithmetic, and Founder of Axiomatic Set Theory, respectively: titles that carry no honors in logic. Being the Founder of Axiomatic Term Theory would likewise carry no honors in the field of logic. CORRECTION: The paper inadvertently implied that Euclid was the first to axiomatize geometry. In order to understand Aristotle’s Analytics as a treatise on demonstration it helps to realize that axiomatized geometry was studied in Plato’s Academy when Aristotle was a student. Euclid was the author of the only ancient axiomatized geometry now available. (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  35.  37
    Tichý's Two-Dimensional Conception of Inference.Ivo Pezlar - 2013 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 20 (2):54-65.
    In this paper we revisit Pavel Tichý’s novel distinction between one-dimensional and two-dimensional conception of inference, which he presented in his book Foundations of Frege’s Logic (1988), and later in On Inference (1999), which was prepared from his manuscript by his co-author Jindra Tichý. We shall focus our inquiry not only on the motivation behind the introduction of this non-classical concept of inference, but also on further inspection of selected Tichý’s arguments, which we see as the most compelling or simply (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  38
    Question-begging and infinite regress.Henry W. Johnstone - 1994 - Argumentation 8 (3):291-293.
    InMetaphysics Γ, Ch. 4, Aristotle speaks of both infinite regress and question-begging, but does not explicitly relate them. We get the impression that he thinks that to use one of these arguments to avoid the other is to jump from the frying-pan into the fire. This relationship is illustrated in terms of the ignorant belief that everything can be proved, and of attempts to prove the Law of Noncontradiction.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Wittgenstein Sobre as Provas Indutivas.André Porto - 2009 - Dois Pontos 6 (2).
    This paper offers a reconstruction of Wittgenstein's discussion on inductive proofs. A "algebraic version" of these indirect proofs is offered and contrasted with the usual ones in which an infinite sequence of modus pones is projected.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  17
    The Fiery Test of Critique: A Reading of Kant's Dialectic.Ian Proops - 2021 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    Kant conceived of 'critique' as a kind of winnowing exercise, with the aim of separating the wheat of good metaphysics from the chaff of bad. He used a less familiar metaphor to make this point, namely, that of 'the fiery test of critique'-not a medieval ordeal of trial by fire, but rather a metallurgical assay, or cupellation, a procedure in which ore samples are tested for their precious-metal content. When seen in this light, critique has a positive, investigatory side: it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  39. REVIEW OF 1988. Saccheri, G. Euclides Vindicatus (1733), edited and translated by G. B. Halsted, 2nd ed. (1986), in Mathematical Reviews MR0862448. 88j:01013.John Corcoran - 1988 - MATHEMATICAL REVIEWS 88 (J):88j:01013.
    Girolamo Saccheri (1667--1733) was an Italian Jesuit priest, scholastic philosopher, and mathematician. He earned a permanent place in the history of mathematics by discovering and rigorously deducing an elaborate chain of consequences of an axiom-set for what is now known as hyperbolic (or Lobachevskian) plane geometry. Reviewer's remarks: (1) On two pages of this book Saccheri refers to his previous and equally original book Logica demonstrativa (Turin, 1697) to which 14 of the 16 pages of the editor's "Introduction" are devoted. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  6
    Das Problem der apagogischen Beweise in Bolzanos Beyträgen_ und seiner _Wissenschaftslehre.Stefania Centrone - 2012 - History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (2):127-157.
    This paper analyzes and evaluates Bolzano's remarks on the apagogic method of proof with reference to his juvenile booklet ‘Contributions to a better founded presentation of mathematics’ of 1810 and to his ‘Theory of science’ (1837). I shall try to defend the following contentions: (1) Bolzanos’ vain attempt to transform all indirect proofs into direct proofs becomes comprehensible as soon as one recognizes the following facts: (1.1) his attitude towards indirect proofs with an affirmative conclusion differs from (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  3
    Logic and philosophy.Howard Kahane - 1969 - Belmont, Calif.,: Wadsworth Pub. Co..
    A comprehensive introduction to formal logic, Logic and Philosophy: A Modern Introduction is a rigorous yet accessible text, appropriate for students encountering the subject for the first time. Abundant, carefully crafted exercise sets accompanied by a clear, engaging exposition build to an exploration of sentential logic, first-order predicate logic, the theory of descriptions, identity, relations, set theory, modal logic, and Aristotelian logic. And as its title suggests, Logic and Philosophy is devoted not only to logic but also to the philosophical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  42. Normal derivability in classical natural deduction.Jan Von Plato & Annika Siders - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):205-211.
    A normalization procedure is given for classical natural deduction with the standard rule of indirect proof applied to arbitrary formulas. For normal derivability and the subformula property, it is sufficient to permute down instances of indirect proof whenever they have been used for concluding a major premiss of an elimination rule. The result applies even to natural deduction for classical modal logic.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  43.  61
    Constructing Cantorian counterexamples.George Boolos - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (3):237-239.
    Cantor's diagonal argument provides an indirect proof that there is no one-one function from the power set of a set A into A. This paper provides a somewhat more constructive proof of Cantor's theorem, showing how, given a function f from the power set of A into A, one can explicitly define a counterexample to the thesis that f is one-one.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  44.  29
    Das Problem der apagogischen Beweise in Bolzanos Beyträgen und seiner Wissenschaftslehre.Stefania Centrone - 2012 - History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (2):127 - 157.
    This paper analyzes and evaluates Bolzano's remarks on the apagogic method of proof with reference to his juvenile booklet "Contributions to a better founded presentation of mathematics" of 1810 and to his ?Theory of science? (1837). I shall try to defend the following contentions: (1) Bolzanos vain attempt to transform all indirect proofs into direct proofs becomes comprehensible as soon as one recognizes the following facts: (1.1) his attitude towards indirect proofs with an affirmative conclusion differs from (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  23
    What Use Is Empirical Confirmation?David Miller - 1996 - Economics and Philosophy 12 (2):197.
    1. Despite the plain fact that there is nothing in this world that can be proved without reliance on some assumption or another, there is an inalienable difference between an argument that begins by assuming what it is designed to establish and one that begins by assuming the contradictory of what it is designed to establish. Arguments of the first kind are uncontroversially acknowledged to be circular, or question-begging; though valid they achieve nothing. Those of the second kind conform to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46. Duns Scotus on Natural Theology.James F. Ross - manuscript
    Scotus’ natural theology has distinctive claims: (i) that we can reason demonstratively to the necessary existence and nature of God from what is actually so; but not from imagined situations, or from conceivability-to-us; rather, only from the possibility logically required for what we know actually to be so; (ii) that there is a univocal transcendental notion of being; (iii) that there are disjunctive transcendental notions that apply exclusively to everything, like ‘contingent/necessary,’ and such that the inferior cannot have a case (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47.  60
    Kant's Refutation of Realism.Henry E. Allison - 1976 - Dialectica 30 (2‐3):223-253.
    SummaryThis paper attempts to develop an interpretation of Kant's transcendental idealism which is based upon his critique of transcendental realism . It is argued that given Kant's transcendental distinction, all non‐ or pre‐critical philosophies, even Berkeleian phenomenalism are transcendentally realistic. This paradoxical result is used as the basis for an analysis of Kant's resolution of the mathematical antinomies, wherein this resolution is seen both as an “indirect proof” of transcendental idealism and as a refutation of transcendental realism. Finally, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48. Transcendental illusion and antinomy in Kant and Deleuze.Henry Somers-Hall - 2009 - In Edward Willatt & Matt Lee (eds.), Thinking Between Deleuze and Kant: A Strange Encounter. Continuum.
    In this paper, I want to look at the way in which Deleuze's reading of Kant's transcendental dialectic influences some of the key thèmes of Différence and Répétition. As we shall see, in the transcendental dialectic, Kant takes the step of claiming that reason, in its natural functioning, is prone to misadventures. Whereas for Descartes, for instance, error takes place between two faculties, such as when reason (wrongly) infers that a stick in water is bent on the basis of sensé (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  75
    What Is Kant's Second Antinomy About.Oscar Schmiege - 2006 - Kant Studien 97 (3):272-300.
    The central questions in this study are: What does Kant consider the essence of the dispute between Rationalists and Realist Empiricists which he titles the “Second Conflict of the Transcendental Ideas?” Why does he believe it supports such wider aims of the Critical Philosophy as: showing the impossibility of a Transcendental Realist explanation of the spatiotemporal world, which amounts to an indirect proof of Transcendental Idealism ; being the only means for detecting the transcendental illusion which leads to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  8
    David Hume’s Treatment of Mind.Aaron Preston - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 35:198-204.
    This paper critically examines Hume’s argument against the knowledge/existence of substantival mind. This denial is rooted in his epistemology which includes a theory of how complex ideas which lack corresponding impressions are manufactured by the imagination, in conjunction with the memory, on the basis of three relations among impressions: resemblance, continuity and constant conjunction. The crux of my critique consists in pointing out that these relations are such that only an enduring, unified agent could interact with them in the way (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 995