Results for 'mathematical objects'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Can Mathematical Objects Be Causally Efficacious?Seungbae Park - 2019 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (3):247–255.
    Callard (2007) argues that it is metaphysically possible that a mathematical object, although abstract, causally affects the brain. I raise the following objections. First, a successful defence of mathematical realism requires not merely the metaphysical possibility but rather the actuality that a mathematical object affects the brain. Second, mathematical realists need to confront a set of three pertinent issues: why a mathematical object does not affect other concrete objects and other mathematical objects, (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  31
    Mathematical Objects arising from Equivalence Relations and their Implementation in Quine's NF.Thomas Forster - 2016 - Philosophia Mathematica 24 (1):nku005.
    Many mathematical objects arise from equivalence classes and invite implementation as those classes. Set-existence principles that would enable this are incompatible with ZFC's unrestricted aussonderung but there are set theories which admit more instances than does ZF. NF provides equivalence classes for stratified relations only. Church's construction provides equivalence classes for “low” sets, and thus, for example, a set of all ordinals. However, that set has an ordinal in turn which is not a member of the set constructed; (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  14
    Mathematical Objects arising from Equivalence Relations and their Implementation in Quine's NF.Thomas Forster - 2016 - Philosophia Mathematica 24 (1):50-59.
    Many mathematical objects arise from equivalence classes and invite implementation as those classes. Set-existence principles that would enable this are incompatible with ZFC's unrestricted _aussonderung_ but there are set theories which admit more instances than does ZF. NF provides equivalence classes for stratified relations only. Church's construction provides equivalence classes for "low" sets, and thus, for example, a set of all ordinals. However, that set has an ordinal in turn which is not a member of the set constructed; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  90
    Handling mathematical objects: representations and context.Jessica Carter - 2013 - Synthese 190 (17):3983-3999.
    This article takes as a starting point the current popular anti realist position, Fictionalism, with the intent to compare it with actual mathematical practice. Fictionalism claims that mathematical statements do purport to be about mathematical objects, and that mathematical statements are not true. Considering these claims in the light of mathematical practice leads to questions about how mathematical objects are handled, and how we prove that certain statements hold. Based on a case (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5. Mathematical Objectivity and Mathematical Objects.Hartry Field - 1998 - In S. Laurence C. MacDonald (ed.), Contemporary Readings in the Foundations of Metaphysics. Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  6. Mathematical Objectivity and Mathematical Objects.Hartry Field - 1998 - In S. Laurence C. MacDonald (ed.), Contemporary Readings in the Foundations of Metaphysics. Blackwell. pp. 387--403.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  7. Alan Turing and the mathematical objection.Gualtiero Piccinini - 2003 - Minds and Machines 13 (1):23-48.
    This paper concerns Alan Turing’s ideas about machines, mathematical methods of proof, and intelligence. By the late 1930s, Kurt Gödel and other logicians, including Turing himself, had shown that no finite set of rules could be used to generate all true mathematical statements. Yet according to Turing, there was no upper bound to the number of mathematical truths provable by intelligent human beings, for they could invent new rules and methods of proof. So, the output of a (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  8.  29
    Mathematical Objectivity and Husserl’s “Community of Monads”.Noam Cohen - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (3):971-991.
    This paper argues that the shared intersubjective accessibility of mathematical objects has its roots in a stratum of experience prior to language or any other form of concrete social interaction. On the basis of Husserl’s phenomenology, I demonstrate that intersubjectivity is an essential stratum of the objects of mathematical experience, i.e., an integral part of the peculiar sense of a mathematical object is its common accessibility to any consciousness whatsoever. For Husserl, any experience of an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  60
    Implementing Mathematical Objects in Set Theory.Thomas Forster - 2007 - Logique Et Analyse 50 (197):79-86.
    In general little thought is given to the general question of how to implement mathematical objects in set theory. It is clear that—at various times in the past—people have gone to considerable lengths to devise implementations with nice properties. There is a litera- ture on the evolution of the Wiener-Kuratowski ordered pair, and a discussion by Quine of the merits of an ordered-pair implemen- tation that makes every set an ordered pair. The implementation of ordinals as Von Neumann (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  66
    Which Mathematical Objects are Referred to by the Enhanced Indispensability Argument?Vladimir Drekalović & Berislav Žarnić - 2018 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 49 (1):121-126.
    This discussion note points to some verbal imprecisions in the formulation of the Enhanced Indispensability Argument. The examination of the plausibility of alternative interpretations reveals that the argument’s minor premise should be understood as a particular, not a universal, statement. Interpretations of the major premise and the conclusion oscillate between de re and de dicto readings. The attempt to find an appropriate interpretation for the EIA leads to undesirable results. If assumed to be valid and sound, the argument warrants the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11. Objectivity in Mathematics, Without Mathematical Objects†.Markus Pantsar - 2021 - Philosophia Mathematica 29 (3):318-352.
    I identify two reasons for believing in the objectivity of mathematical knowledge: apparent objectivity and applications in science. Focusing on arithmetic, I analyze platonism and cognitive nativism in terms of explaining these two reasons. After establishing that both theories run into difficulties, I present an alternative epistemological account that combines the theoretical frameworks of enculturation and cumulative cultural evolution. I show that this account can explain why arithmetical knowledge appears to be objective and has scientific applications. Finally, I will (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  12.  30
    Mathematical Objects and Mathematical Knowledge.Michael D. Resnik - 1995 - Dartmouth Publishing Company.
    The International research Library of Philosophy collects in book form a wide range of important and influential essays in philosophy, drawn predominantly from English-language journals. Each volume in the library deals with a field of enquiry which has received significant attention in philosophy in the last 25 years and is edited by a philosopher noted in that field.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. Mathematical Objects and Mathematical Knowledge.Michael D. Resnik - 1998 - Erkenntnis 48 (1):125-127.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14. Indefiniteness of mathematical objects.Ken Akiba - 2000 - Philosophia Mathematica 8 (1):26--46.
    The view that mathematical objects are indefinite in nature is presented and defended, hi the first section, Field's argument for fictionalism, given in response to Benacerraf's problem of identification, is closely examined, and it is contended that platonists can solve the problem equally well if they take the view that mathematical objects are indefinite. In the second section, two general arguments against the intelligibility of objectual indefiniteness are shown erroneous, hi the final section, the view is (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15. The Ontogenesis of Mathematical Objects.Barry Smith - 1975 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 6 (2):91-101.
    Mathematical objects are divided into (1) those which are autonomous, i.e., not dependent for their existence upon mathematicians’ conscious acts, and (2) intentional objects, which are so dependent. Platonist philosophy of mathematics argues that all objects belong to group (1), Brouwer’s intuitionism argues that all belong to group (2). Here we attempt to develop a dualist ontology of mathematics (implicit in the work of, e.g., Hilbert), exploiting the theories of Meinong, Husserl and Ingarden on the relations (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16. 3 Mathematical Objects and Identity.Patricia Blanchette - 2007 - In Michael O'Rourke Corey Washington (ed.), Situating Semantics: Essays on the Philosophy of John Perry. pp. 73.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  13
    Mathematical Objects.Joseph Ullian, Bernard Baumrin & Joseph S. Ullian - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (4):593-595.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Mathematical Objects and Mathematical Knowledge.Fabrice Pataut - unknown
  19.  40
    Mathematical Objects and Mathematical Knowledge.Roman Murawski - 1996 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 52 (1):257-259.
  20.  48
    Mathematical objects and mathematical knowledge.Jan Woleński - 1998 - Erkenntnis 48 (1):129-131.
  21. The structuralist view of mathematical objects.Charles Parsons - 1990 - Synthese 84 (3):303 - 346.
  22.  13
    The insubstantiality of mathematical objects as positions in structures.Bahram Assadian - 2022 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 20.
    The realist versions of mathematical structuralism are often characterized by what I call ‘the insubstantiality thesis’, according to which mathematical objects, being positions in structures, have no non-structural properties: they are purely structural objects. The thesis has been criticized for being inconsistent or descriptively inadequate. In this paper, by implementing the resources of a real-definitional account of essence in the context of Fregean abstraction principles, I offer a version of structuralism – essentialist structuralism – which validates (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. Does the existence of mathematical objects make a difference?A. Baker - 2003 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (2):246 – 264.
    In this paper I examine a strategy which aims to bypass the technicalities of the indispensability debate and to offer a direct route to nominalism. The starting-point for this alternative nominalist strategy is the claim that--according to the platonist picture--the existence of mathematical objects makes no difference to the concrete, physical world. My principal goal is to show that the 'Makes No Difference' (MND) Argument does not succeed in undermining platonism. The basic reason why not is that the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  24.  50
    Comparing the structures of mathematical objects.Isaac Wilhelm - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):6357-6369.
    A popular method for comparing the structures of mathematical objects, which I call the ‘subset approach’, says that X has more structure than Y just in case X’s automorphisms form a proper subset of Y’s automorphisms. This approach is attractive, in part, because it seems to yield the right results in some comparisons of spacetime structure. But as I show, it yields the wrong results in a number of other cases. The problem is that the subset approach compares (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25. Our knowledge of mathematical objects.Kit Fine - 2005 - In Tamar Szabó Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 89-109.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  26.  37
    Referring to Mathematical Objects via Definite Descriptions.Stefan Buijsman - 2017 - Philosophia Mathematica 25 (1):128-138.
    Linsky and Zalta try to explain how we can refer to mathematical objects by saying that this happens through definite descriptions which may appeal to mathematical theories. I present two issues for their account. First, there is a problem of finding appropriate pre-conditions to reference, which are currently difficult to satisfy. Second, there is a problem of ensuring the stability of the resulting reference. Slight changes in the properties ascribed to a mathematical object can result in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27. The conceptual contingency of mathematical objects.Hartry Field - 1993 - Mind 102 (406):285-299.
  28. Our Knowledge of Mathematical Objects.Kit Fine - 2006 - Oxford Studies in Epistemology 1.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  29. Our Knowledge of Mathematical Objects.Kit Fine - 2005 - In Tamar Szabo Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology Volume 1. Oxford University Press UK.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  30. The nature of mathematical objects.Øystein Linnebo - 2008 - In Bonnie Gold & Roger Simons (eds.), Proof and Other Dilemmas: Mathematics and Philosophy. Mathematical Association of America. pp. 205--219.
    On the face of it, platonism seems very far removed from the scientific world view that dominates our age. Nevertheless many philosophers and mathematicians believe that modern mathematics requires some form of platonism. The defense of mathematical platonism that is both most direct and has been most influential in the analytic tradition in philosophy derives from the German logician-philosopher Gottlob Frege (1848-1925).2 I will therefore refer to it as Frege’s argument. This argument is part of the background of any (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31. The Reality of Mathematical Objects.Gideon Rosen - 2011 - In John Polkinghorne (ed.), Meaning in Mathematics. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  32.  46
    How are Mathematical Objects Constituted? A Structuralist Answer.Wolfgang Spohn - unknown
    The paper proposes to amend structuralism in mathematics by saying what places in a structure and thus mathematical objects are. They are the objects of the canonical system realizing a categorical structure, where that canonical system is a minimal system in a specific essentialistic sense. It would thus be a basic ontological axiom that such a canonical system always exists. This way of conceiving mathematical objects is underscored by a defense of an essentialistic version of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  15
    Nominalism and Mathematical Objectivity.Guanglong Luo - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (3):833-851.
    We observe that Putnam’s model-theoretic argument against determinacy of the concept of second-order quantification or that of the set is harmless to the nominalist. It serves as a good motivation for the nominalist philosophy of mathematics. But in the end it can lead to a serious challenge to the nominalist account of mathematical objectivity if some minimal assumptions about the relation between mathematical objectivity and logical objectivity are made. We consider three strategies the nominalist might take to meet (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Aristotle on Mathematical Objects.Edward Hussey - 1991 - Apeiron 24 (4):105 - 133.
  35. A Gödelian Thesis Regarding Mathematical Objects: Do They Exist? And Can We Perceive Them?Charles S. Chihara - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (2):211-227.
  36.  17
    Truth as a Mathematical Object DOI:10.5007/1808-1711.2010v14n1p31.Jean-Yves Béziau - 2010 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 14 (1):31-46.
    In this paper we discuss in which sense truth is considered as a mathematical object in propositional logic. After clarifying how this concept is used in classical logic, through the notions of truth-table, truth-function and bivaluation, we examine some generalizations of it in non-classical logics: many-valued matrix semantics with three and four values, non-truth-functional bivalent semantics, Kripke possible world semantics. • DOI:10.5007/1808-1711.2010v14n1p31.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  55
    Avicenna on the Nature of Mathematical Objects.Mohammad Saleh Zarepour - 2016 - Dialogue 55 (3):511-536.
    Some authors have proposed that Avicenna considers mathematical objects, i.e., geometric shapes and numbers, to be mental existents completely separated from matter. In this paper, I will show that this description, though not completely wrong, is misleading. Avicenna endorses, I will argue, some sort of literalism, potentialism, and finitism.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38. Fictionalism and Mathematical Objectivity.Iulian D. Toader - 2012 - In Metaphysics and Science. University of Bucharest Press. pp. 137-158.
    This paper, written in Romanian, compares fictionalism, nominalism, and neo-Meinongianism as responses to the problem of objectivity in mathematics, and then motivates a fictionalist view of objectivity as invariance.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  48
    Chrysippus on Mathematical Objects.David G. Robertson - 2004 - Ancient Philosophy 24 (1):169-191.
  40.  37
    Infons as mathematical objects.Keith J. Devlin - 1992 - Minds and Machines 2 (2):185-201.
    I argue that the role played by infons in the kind of mathematical theory of information being developed by several workers affiliated to CSLI is analogous to that of the various number systems in mathematics. In particular, I present a mathematical construction of infons in terms of representations and informational equivalences between them. The main theme of the paper arose from an electronic mail exchange with Pat Hayes of Xeroxparc. The exposition derives from a talk I gave at (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  4
    Mathematical Objects and Mathematical Knowledge. [REVIEW]Roman Murawski - 1996 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 52 (1):257-259.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Reference to Mathematical Objects.J. R. G. Williams - 2002
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  77
    Truth as a Mathematical Object.Jean-Yves Béziau - 2010 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 14 (1):31-46.
    Neste artigo, discutimos em que sentido a verdade é considerada como um objeto matemático na lógica proposicional. Depois de esclarecer como este conceito é usado na lógica clássica, através das noções de tabela de verdade, de função de verdade, de bivaloração, examinamos algumas generalizações desse conceito nas lógicas não clássicas: semânticas matriciais multi-valoradas com três ou quatro valores, semântica bivalente não veritativa, semânticas dos mundos possiveis de Kripke. DOI:10.5007/1808-1711.2010v14n1p31.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44. On Positing Mathematical Objects.Michael D. ReSNik - 1996 - In Matthias Schirn (ed.), Frege: importance and legacy. New York: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 13--45.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Aristotle's mathematical objects as th" intermediates".B. Vezjak - 2000 - Filozofski Vestnik 21 (1):27-44.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  4
    Plato and the Mathematical Objects.Dionysios A. Anapolitanos - 2019 - Politeia 1 (2):57-66.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  93
    Gödel and 'the objective existence' of mathematical objects.Pierre Cassou-Noguès - 2005 - History and Philosophy of Logic 26 (3):211-228.
    This paper is a discussion of Gödel's arguments for a Platonistic conception of mathematical objects. I review the arguments that Gödel offers in different papers, and compare them to unpublished material (from Gödel's Nachlass). My claim is that Gödel's later arguments simply intend to establish that mathematical knowledge cannot be accounted for by a reflexive analysis of our mental acts. In other words, there is at the basis of mathematics some data whose constitution cannot be explained by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  38
    Michael D. Resnik (ed.), Mathematical Objects and Mathematical Knowledge.Jan Woleński - 1998 - Erkenntnis 48 (1):129-131.
  49.  16
    Access to Mathematical Objects.Keith Hossack - 1991 - Critica 23 (68):157 - 181.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. “In Nature as in Geometry”: Du Châtelet and the Post-Newtonian Debate on the Physical Significance of Mathematical Objects.Aaron Wells - 2023 - In Wolfgang Lefèvre (ed.), Between Leibniz, Newton, and Kant: Philosophy and Science in the Eighteenth Century. Springer Verlag. pp. 69-98.
    Du Châtelet holds that mathematical representations play an explanatory role in natural science. Moreover, she writes that things proceed in nature as they do in geometry. How should we square these assertions with Du Châtelet’s idealism about mathematical objects, on which they are ‘fictions’ dependent on acts of abstraction? The question is especially pressing because some of her important interlocutors (Wolff, Maupertuis, and Voltaire) denied that mathematics informs us about the properties of material things. After situating Du (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000