Results for 'preference reversal'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  16
    Preference reversal in multiattribute choice.Konstantinos Tsetsos, Marius Usher & Nick Chater - 2010 - Psychological Review 117 (4):1275-1291.
  2.  13
    Preference reversal in quantum decision theory.Vyacheslav I. Yukalov & Didier Sornette - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  29
    Preference reversal in Ellsberg problems.Patrick Maher & Yoshihisa Kashima - 1997 - Philosophical Studies 88 (2):187-207.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. Preference reversals in judgment and choice.Marcus Selart - 1994 - Gothenburg University Press.
    According to normative decision theory there exists a principle of procedure invariance which states that a decision maker's preference order should remain the same, independently of which response mode is used. For example, the decision maker should express the same preference independently of whether he or she has to judge or decide. Nevertheless, previous research in behavioral decision making has suggested that judgments and choices yield different preference orders in both the risky and the riskless domain. In (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  49
    Artefacts in experimental economics: Preference reversals and the becker–degroot–marschak mechanism.Francesco Guala - 2000 - Economics and Philosophy 16 (1):47-75.
    Controversies in economics often fizzle out unresolved. One reason is that, despite their professed empiricism, economists find it hard to agree on the interpretation of the relevant empirical evidence. In this paper I will present an example of a controversial issue first raised and then solved by recourse to laboratory experimentation. A major theme of this paper, then, concerns the methodological advantages of controlled experiments. The second theme is the nature of experimental artefacts and of the methods devised to detect (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  6.  42
    Expression theory and the preference reversal phenomena.William M. Goldstein & Hillel J. Einhorn - 1987 - Psychological Review 94 (2):236-254.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  7. Levi's account of preference reversals.Erik Angner - 2002 - Economics and Philosophy 18 (2):287-302.
    This paper argues that Isaac Levi's account of preference reversals is only a limited success. Levi succeeds in showing that an agent acting in accord with his theory may exhibit reversals. Nevertheless, the specific account that Levi presents in order to accommodate the behavior of experimental subjects appears to be disconfirmed by available evidence.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  32
    Why contextual preference reversals maximize expected value.Andrew Howes, Paul A. Warren, George Farmer, Wael El-Deredy & Richard L. Lewis - 2016 - Psychological Review 123 (4):368-391.
  9.  56
    Models of preference reversals and personal rules: Do they require maximizing a utility function with a specific structure?Horacio Arló-Costa - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (5):650-651.
    One of the reasons for adopting hyperbolic discounting is to explain preference reversals. Another is that this value structure suggests an elegant theory of the will. I examine the capacity of the theory to solve Newcomb's problem. In addition, I compare Ainslie's account with other procedural theories of choice that seem at least equally capable of accommodating reversals of preference.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  34
    Framing, Switching and Preference Reversals.Michael J. Ryan - 2004 - Theory and Decision 57 (3):181-211.
    An explicitly frame related interpretation of a very general more for less result is used to establish a correspondingly general class of frame related switching results. These are used in turn to show how preference reversals of kinds found by Allais and others may not only be essentially non-paradoxical in character, but can be expected to be frequently observed, even under conditions of certainty and of complete information.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  9
    Evaluation Scale or Output Format: The Attentional Mechanism Underpinning Time Preference Reversal.Yan-Bang Zhou, Qiang Li, Qiu-Yue Li & Hong-Zhi Liu - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Time preference reversals refers to systematic inconsistencies between preferences and valuations in intertemporal choice. When faced with a pair of intertemporal options, people preferred the smaller-sooner option but assign a higher price to the larger-later one. Different hypotheses postulate that the differences in evaluation scale or output format between the choice and the bid tasks cause the preference reversal. However, these hypotheses have not been distinguished. In the present study, we conducted a hybrid task, which shares the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  40
    Within-subject preference reversals in description-and experience-based choice.Adrian R. Camilleri & Ben R. Newell - 2009 - In N. A. Taatgen & H. van Rijn (eds.), Proceedings of the 31st Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. pp. 449--454.
  13.  5
    Postscript: Contrasting predictions for preference reversal.Marius Usher, Konstantinos Tsetsos & Nick Chater - 2010 - Psychological Review 117 (4):1291-1293.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. Reasoning about outcome probabilities and values in preference reversals.Marcus Selart, Ole Boe & Tommy Garling - 1999 - Thinking and Reasoning 5 (2):175 – 188.
    Research on preference reversals has demonstrated a disproportionate influence of outcome probability on choices between monetary gambles. The aim was to investigate the hypothesis that this is a prominence effect originally demonstrated for riskless choice. Another aim was to test the structure compatibility hypothesis as an explanation of the effect. The hypothesis implies that probability should be the prominent attribute when compared with value attributes both in a choice and a preference rating procedure. In Experiment 1, two groups (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  15. The Locality and Globality of Instrumental Rationality: The normative significance of preference reversals.Brian Kim - 2014 - Synthese 191 (18):4353-4376.
    When we ask a decision maker to express her preferences, it is typically assumed that we are eliciting a pre-existing set of preferences. However, empirical research has suggested that our preferences are often constructed on the fly for the decision problem at hand. This paper explores the ramifications of this empirical research for our understanding of instrumental rationality. First, I argue that these results pose serious challenges for the traditional decision-theoretic view of instrumental rationality, which demands global coherence amongst all (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  11
    Life and Death Decisions and COVID‐19: Investigating and Modeling the Effect of Framing, Experience, and Context on Preference Reversals in the Asian Disease Problem.Shashank Uttrani, Neha Sharma & Varun Dutt - 2022 - Topics in Cognitive Science 14 (4):800-824.
    Prior research in judgment and decision making (JDM) has investigated the effect of problem framing on human preferences. Furthermore, research in JDM documented the absence of such reversal of preferences when making decisions from experience. However, little is known about the effect of context on preferences under the combined influence of problem framing and problem format. Also, little is known about how cognitive models would account for human choices in different problem frames and types (general/specific) in the experience format. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  62
    Non-hyperbolic discounting and dynamic preference reversal.Shou Chen, Richard Fu, Lei Wedge & Ziran Zou - 2019 - Theory and Decision 86 (2):283-302.
    In this paper, we present a time-varying and non-stationary but non-hyperbolic discount function that explains dynamic preference reversal. The new discount function emerges from an analysis of intertemporal consumption and savings choices with mortality risk and an altruistic factor. Our analysis shows that the process of updating survival information may also account for dynamic preference reversal.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  18
    The fragile nature of contextual preference reversals: Reply to Tsetsos, Chater, and Usher (2015).Jennifer S. Trueblood, Scott D. Brown & Andrew Heathcote - 2015 - Psychological Review 122 (4):848-853.
  19.  24
    A Dynamic, Stochastic, Computational Model of Preference Reversal Phenomena.Joseph G. Johnson & Jerome R. Busemeyer - 2005 - Psychological Review 112 (4):841-861.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  20.  13
    Examining the mechanisms underlying contextual preference reversal: Comment on Trueblood, Brown, and Heathcote (2014).Konstantinos Tsetsos, Nick Chater & Marius Usher - 2015 - Psychological Review 122 (4):838-847.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21.  25
    The neurodynamics of choice, value-based decisions, and preference reversal.Marius Usher, Anat Elhalal & James L. McClelland - 2008 - In Nick Chater & Mike Oaksford (eds.), The Probabilistic Mind: Prospects for Bayesian Cognitive Science. Oxford University Press. pp. 277--300.
  22. The neurodynamics of choice, value-based decisions and preference reversal.Marius Usher, Anat Elhalal & McClelland & L. James - 2008 - In Nick Chater & Mike Oaksford (eds.), The Probabilistic Mind: Prospects for Bayesian Cognitive Science. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  7
    Preference-based English reverse auctions.Marie-Jo Bellosta, Sylvie Kornman & Daniel Vanderpooten - 2011 - Artificial Intelligence 175 (7-8):1449-1467.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Preference for unpredictability reversed when nonreward is aversive-a review of data and theory.Hb Daly - 1987 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 25 (5):351-351.
  25.  15
    Right-response preference in probability learning and reversal.Marilyn E. Miller - 1966 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 71 (5):776.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  31
    Prediction of preference, transposition, and transposition-reversal from the generalization gradient.Werner K. Honig - 1962 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 64 (3):239.
  27.  19
    The effect of reversal shifts and scrambled shock on preference for signaled shock established with unscrambled shock.Brian M. Kruger, Patrick E. Campbell & Mark S. Crabtree - 1981 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 17 (2):113-116.
  28. Must Theorising about Adaptive Preferences Deny Women's Agency?Serene J. Khader - 2012 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 29 (4):302-317.
    Critics argue that adaptive preference theorists misrepresent oppressed people's reasons for perpetuating their oppression. According to critics, AP theorists assume that people who adapt their preferences to unjust conditions lack the psychic capacities that would allow them to develop their own normative perspectives and/or form appropriate values. The misrepresentation is morally problematic, because it promotes unjustified paternalism and perpetuates colonial stereotypes of third‐world women. I argue that we can imagine a conception of AP that is consistent with acknowledging agency (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  29.  77
    The reversal test, status quo bias, and opposition to human cognitive enhancement.Steve Clarke - 2016 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 46 (3):369-386.
    Bostrom and Ord’s reversal test has been appealed to by many philosophers to substantiate the charge that preferences for status quo options are motivated by status quo bias. I argue that their characterization of the reversal test needs to be modified, and that their description of the burden of proof it imposes needs to be clarified. I then argue that there is a way to meet that burden of proof which Bostrom and Ord fail to recognize. I also (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30. Causation and Time Reversal.Matt Farr - 2020 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 71 (1):177-204.
    What would it be for a process to happen backwards in time? Would such a process involve different causal relations? It is common to understand the time-reversal invariance of a physical theory in causal terms, such that whatever can happen forwards in time can also happen backwards in time. This has led many to hold that time-reversal symmetry is incompatible with the asymmetry of cause and effect. This article critiques the causal reading of time reversal. First, I (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  31. In Defense of Reverse Inference.Edouard Machery - 2014 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 65 (2):251-267.
    Reverse inference is the most commonly used inferential strategy for bringing images of brain activation to bear on psychological hypotheses, but its inductive validity has recently been questioned. In this article, I show that, when it is analyzed in likelihoodist terms, reverse inference does not suffer from the problems highlighted in the recent literature, and I defend the appropriateness of treating reverse inference in these terms. 1 Introduction2 Reverse Inference3 Reverse Inference Defended3.1 Typical reverse inferences are fallacious3.2 No quick and (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  32. The construction of preference.Sarah Lichtenstein & Paul Slovic (eds.) - 2006 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    One of the main themes that has emerged from behavioral decision research during the past three decades is the view that people's preferences are often constructed in the process of elicitation. This idea is derived from studies demonstrating that normatively equivalent methods of elicitation (e.g., choice and pricing) give rise to systematically different responses. These preference reversals violate the principle of procedure invariance that is fundamental to all theories of rational choice. If different elicitation procedures produce different orderings of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  33.  2
    The role of category valence in prototype preference.Moritz Ingendahl, Nadja Propheter & Tobias Vogel - forthcoming - Cognition and Emotion.
    People prefer prototypical stimuli over atypical stimuli. The dominant explanation for this prototype preference effect is that prototypical stimuli are processed more fluently. However, a more recent account proposes that prototypes are more strongly associated with their category’s valence, leading to a reversed prototype preference effect for negative categories. One critical but untested assumption of this category-valence account is that no prototype preference should emerge for entirely neutral categories. We tested this prediction by conditioning categories of dot (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Climate Change, Individual Preferences, and Procrastination.Fausto Corvino - 2021 - In Sarah Kenehan & Corey Katz (eds.), Climate Justice and Feasibility: Normative Theorizing, Feasibility Constraints, and Climate Action. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 193-211.
    When discussing the general inertia in climate change mitigation, it is common to approach the analysis either in terms of epistemic obstacles (climate change is too scientifically complex to be fully understood by all in its dramatic nature and/or to find space in the media) and/or moral obstacles (the causal link between polluting actions and social damage is too loose, both geographically and temporally, to allow individuals to understand the consequences of their emissions). In this chapter I maintain that both (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Reversibility and Dogmatism as Philosophical Styles.Norbert Miklas - 2009 - Filozofia 64 (4):351-355.
    The paper offers an analysis of reversibility, a stylistic strategy philosophers employ when solving theoretical dilemmas. Reversibility means oscillating of a philosopher between two contradictory truths or dogmas. First, the adherent of reversibility faces two contradictory truths or dogmas. What follows is a rejection or an acceptance of both poles. In contrast to the style of the authors using the principle of reversibility, the paper describes a specific stylistic strategy preferred by dogmatic philosophers, one marked by moderate modality and certainty (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  71
    No going back? Reversibility and why it matters for deep brain stimulation.Jonathan Pugh - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (4):225-230.
    Deep brain stimulation (DBS) is frequently described as a ‘reversible’ medical treatment, and the reversibility of DBS is often cited as an important reason for preferring it to brain lesioning procedures as a last resort treatment modality for patients suffering from treatment-refractory conditions. Despite its widespread acceptance, the claim that DBS is reversible has recently come under attack. Critics have pointed out that data are beginning to suggest that there can be non-stimulation-dependent effects of DBS. Furthermore, we lack long-term data (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  37.  23
    A reversed pre.William B. Pavlik, Peter L. Carlton & Robert Lehr - 1967 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 75 (2):274.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  17
    Adaptive preferences: a remaining obstacle for basic income.Pedro Jesús Pérez Zafrilla - 2019 - Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 44:29-48.
    Resumen La renta básica proporciona a la ciudadanía una autonomía económica que se traduce en una libertad real para conducir sus vidas. Sin embargo, en este artículo defiendo que la renta básica no sería efectiva en situaciones de pobreza donde se generan preferencias adaptativas en las personas. Para mostrarlo analizaré las bases psicológicas del comportamiento de personas con preferencias adaptativas. A continuación, abordaré qué estrategias son las indicadas para revertir la situación de preferencias adaptativas. Implementar estas políticas permitirá que la (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. A radical reversal in cortical information flow as the mechanism for human cognitive abilities: The frontal feedback model.R. A. Noack - 1995 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 16 (3):281-304.
    The paper argues that the rich cognitive abilities of humans are the result of a unique functional system in the human brain which is absent in the nonhuman brain. This "frontal feedback system" is suggested to have evolved in the transition from the great apes to humans and is a product of a reversal in the preferred direction of information flow in the human cortex due to the phylogenetic enlargement of the human frontal lobe. The frontal feedback system forms (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  70
    Saudi mothers' preferences about breaking bad news concerning newborns: a structured verbal questionnaire.Sameer Y. Al-Abdi, Eman A. Al-Ali, Matar H. Daheer, Yaseen M. Al-Saleh, Khalid H. Al-Qurashi & Maryam A. Al-Aamri - 2011 - BMC Medical Ethics 12 (1):1-8.
    Breaking bad news (BBN) to parents whose newborn has a major disease is an ethical dilemma. In Saudi Arabia, BBN about newborns is performed according to the parental preferences that have been reported from non-Arabic/non-Islamic countries. Saudi mothers' preferences about BBN have not yet been studied. Therefore, we aimed to elicit the preferences of Saudi mothers about BBN concerning newborns. We selected a convenience sample of 402 Saudi mothers, aged 18-50 years, who had no previous experience with BBN. We selected (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41. Aspects of compatibility and the construction of preference.Marcus Selart - 1997 - In Rob Ranyard, Ray Crozier & Ola Svenson (eds.), Decision making: Cognitive models and explanations. Routledge. pp. 58-72.
    This chapter focuses on the psychological mechanisms behind the construction of preference, especially the actual processes used by humans when they make decisions in their everyday lives or in business situations. The chapter uses cognitive psychological techniques to break down these processes and set them in their social context. When attributes are compatible with the response scale, they are assigned greater weight because they are most easily mapped onto the response. For instance, when subjects are asked to set a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  42.  23
    Continuity properties of preference relations.Marian A. Baroni & Douglas S. Bridges - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (5):454-459.
    Various types of continuity for preference relations on a metric space are examined constructively. In particular, necessary and sufficient conditions are given for an order-dense, strongly extensional preference relation on a complete metric space to be continuous. It is also shown, in the spirit of constructive reverse mathematics, that the continuity of sequentially continuous, order-dense preference relations on complete, separable metric spaces is connected to Ishihara's principleBD-ℕ, and therefore is not provable within Bishop-style constructive mathematics alone.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  12
    Is the Social Unrest like COVID-19 or Is COVID-19 like the Social Unrest? A Case Study of Source-target Reversibility.Dennis Tay - 2021 - Metaphor and Symbol 36 (2):99-115.
    Hong Kong is undergoing two overlapping crises: social unrest over anti-government protests, and COVID-19. The media has linked these events in both objective and subjective ways. While some liken the social unrest to COVID-19, others do the opposite. This is an intriguing real-world instance of source-target reversibility with interchangeable source and target resulting in two apt variants. This paper reports a survey study of the links between crisis perceptions and the aptness of metaphor variants. Participants (N = 93) rated 30 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44. What if I were in his shoes? On Hare's argument for preference utilitarianism.Wlodek Rabinowicz & Bertil Strömberg - 1996 - Theoria 62 (1-2):95-123.
    This paper discusses the argument for preference utilitarianism proposed by Richard Hare in Moral Thinking(Hare, 1981). G. F. Schueler (1984) and Ingmar Persson (1989) identified a serious gap in Hare’s reasoning, which might be called the No-Conflict Problem. The paper first tries to fill the gap. Then, however, starting with an idea of Zeno Vendler, the question is raised whether the gap is there to begin with. Unfortunately, this Vendlerian move does not save Hare from criticism. Paradoxically, it instead (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  45.  9
    An Agent‐First Preference in a Patient‐First Language During Sentence Comprehension.Sebastian Sauppe, Åshild Næss, Giovanni Roversi, Martin Meyer, Ina Bornkessel-Schlesewsky & Balthasar Bickel - 2023 - Cognitive Science 47 (9):e13340.
    The language comprehension system preferentially assumes that agents come first during incremental processing. While this might reflect a biologically fixed bias, shared with other domains and other species, the evidence is limited to languages that place agents first, and so the bias could also be learned from usage frequency. Here, we probe the bias with electroencephalography (EEG) in Äiwoo, a language that by default places patients first, but where sentence-initial nouns are still locally ambiguous between patient or agent roles. Comprehenders (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  92
    The Logic of Electoral Preference: Response to Saraydar and Hudelson.Geoffrey Brennan - 1987 - Economics and Philosophy 3 (1):131-138.
    How may we best understand the motivational structure that stands behind individuals' acts of voting? In “The Impartial Spectator Goes to Washington” we suggested that expressive concerns swamp narrowly consequential motivations, in contradistinction to normal market transactions in which the priority is reversed. A striking consequence of this fact is that individuals will be led to vote for outcomes that they would reject were they in a position to act decisively. In this regard we found the moral psychology Adam Smith (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  26
    Local is not fair: indigenous peasant farmer preference for export markets.Rachel Soper - 2016 - Agriculture and Human Values 33 (3):537-548.
    The food sovereignty movement calls for a reversal of the neoliberal globalization of food, toward an alternative development model that supports peasant production for local consumption. The movement holds an ambiguous stance on peasant production for export markets, and clearly prioritizes localized trade. Food sovereignty discourse often simplifies and romanticizes the peasantry—overlooking agrarian class categories and ignoring the interests of export-oriented peasants. Drawing on 8 months of participant observation in the Andean countryside and 85 interviews with indigenous peasant farmers, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  48.  24
    Evaluative Processing of Food Images: A Conditional Role for Viewing in Preference Formation.Alexandra Wolf, Kajornvut Ounjai, Muneyoshi Takahashi, Shunsuke Kobayashi, Tetsuya Matsuda & Johan Lauwereyns - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9:363543.
    Previous research suggested a role of gaze in preference formation, not merely as an expression of preference, but also as a causal influence. According to the gaze cascade hypothesis, the longer subjects look at an item, the more likely they are to develop a preference for it. However, to date the connection between viewing and liking has been investigated predominately with self-paced viewing conditions in which the subjects were required to select certain items from simultaneously presented stimuli (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  8
    The deconstruction of Baudrillard: the "unexpected reversibility" of discourse.Aleksandar S. Santrac̆ - 2005 - Lewiston, N.Y.: Edwin Mellen Press.
    Jean Baudrillard is one of the outstanding representatives both of French poststructuralism and postmodernism. Because of radical criticism it was not possible for him to establish a logically coherent theoretical system; the philosophical aspects of his work are specifically merged, therefore, into a critical asystematic fragmentarism, which is the subject of this work. From the critique of the political economy of the sign, through critiques of rationalism, reality, progress, truth, history to the theory of simulation, Baudrillard's specific para-concepts (fatal strategy, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  10
    Being In Front_ Is Good—But Where Is _In Front? Preferences for Spatial Referencing Affect Evaluation.Andrea Bender, Sarah Teige-Mocigemba, Annelie Rothe-Wulf, Miriam Seel & Sieghard Beller - 2020 - Cognitive Science 44 (6):e12840.
    Speakers of English frequently associate location in space with valence, as in moving up and down the “social ladder.” If such an association also holds for the sagittal axis, an object “in front of” another object would be evaluated more positively than the one “behind.” Yet how people conceptualize relative locations depends on which frame of reference (FoR) they adopt—and hence on cross‐linguistically diverging preferences. What is conceptualized as “in front” in one variant of the relative FoR (e.g., translation) is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000