Law and Philosophy

ISSNs: 0167-5249, 1573-0522

14 found

View year:

  1.  10
    Are Parents Fiduciaries?Scott Altman - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (5):411-435.
    Parents resemble trustees, conservators, and other fiduciaries; they exercise broad discretion while making choices for vulnerable people. Like other fiduciaries, parents can be tempted to neglect their duties or pursue self-interest at the expense of those they should protect. This article argues against treating parents as fiduciaries for three reasons. First, the scope of parental fiduciary duties cannot be narrowed enough to make them tolerable. Arguments limiting fiduciary duties to cases where parents exercise delegated powers or act within parenting roles (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Liability for Emissions without Laws or Political Institutions.Göran Duus-Otterström - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (5):461-486.
    Many climate ethicists maintain that climate policy costs should be borne by those who historically emitted the most greenhouse gases. Some theorists have recently argued, however, that actors only became liable for emitting once the emissions breached legitimate legal regulation governing emissions. This paper challenges this view. Focusing on the climate responsibility of states, it argues that even if we assume that legitimate legal regulation is needed to remove excusable ignorance of entitlements to emit or is constitutive of such entitlements, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. Why Busing Voters to the Polling Station is Paying People to Vote.Jørn Sønderholm & Jakob Thrane Mainz - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (5):437-459.
    In this paper, we argue that the widespread practice in the United States of busing voters to the polling station on Election Day is an instance of paying people to vote. We defend a definition of what it means to pay people to vote, and on this definition, busing voters to the polling station is an instance of paying people to vote. Paying people to vote is illegal according to United States federal election law. However, the United States courts have (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  3
    Metalinguistic Negotiation in Legal Speech.Bill Watson - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (5):487-524.
    This paper examines the role of metalinguistic negotiation in lawyers’ and judges’ speech about the law. A speaker engages in metalinguistic negotiation when the speaker uses a term to advocate for what that term should mean or how it should be used relative to context. While I doubt that legal practitioners employ metalinguistic negotiation in the ways that David Plunkett and Tim Sundell have proposed, it is plausible that practitioners do so in another way. Specifically, I contend that lawyers and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  14
    Critical Mercy in Criminal Law.Kristen Bell - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (4):351-378.
    Much contemporary discussion of mercy has focused on what I call ‘beneficent mercy’: compassionately sparing a person from harsh treatment that she deserves. Drawing on Seneca’s discussion of mercy, I articulate a different concept of mercy which I call ‘critical mercy’: treating a person justly when unjust social rules call for harsher treatment. Whereas beneficent mercy is grounded in recognition of imperfection in human individuals, critical mercy is grounded in recognition of imperfection in human institutions. I argue that political communities (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Relational and Distributive Discrimination.Rona Dinur - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (4).
    Recent philosophical accounts of discrimination face challenges in accommodating robust intuitions about the particular way in which it is wrongful—most prominently, the intuition that discriminatory actions intrinsically violate equality irrespective of their contingent consequences. The paper suggests that we understand the normative structure of discrimination in a way that is different from the one implicitly assumed by these accounts. It argues that core discriminatory wrongs—such as segregation in Apartheid South Africa—divide into two types, corresponding to violations of relational and distributive (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  7
    Hart as an Inferentialist: The Methodological Pragmatist Insight in Hart’s Inaugural Lecture.Ziyu Liu - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (4):379-409.
    Jurisprudes today differ in their interpretations of H.L.A. Hart’s analysis of the semantics of internal legal statements. Drawing upon the philosophy of language and metaethics to reconstruct Hart’s view, they disagree as to whether Hart should be interpreted as an expressivist or quasi-expressivist. In this paper I propose a third reconstruction, under which Hart adopted an inferentialist analysis of the semantics of internal legal statements. In executing this reconstruction, I focus on Hart’s inaugural lecture, and utilize the theoretical apparatus of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  29
    The Internal Point of View.Jeffrey Kaplan - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (3):211-236.
    The most discussed theory of law of the twentieth century – HLA Hart’s theory from _The Concept of Law_ – is fundamentally _psychological_. It explains the existence of legal systems in terms of an attitude taken by legal officials: the internal point of view. Though much has been said about this attitude (what statements _express_ it, what it is _not_, how Hart _ought_ to have conceived of it, etc.), we nonetheless lack an adequate account of the attitude itself. This paper (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  2
    Conditional Relevance and Conditional Admissibility.Matthew Kotzen - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (3):237-283.
    In this paper, I aim to explicate the distinction between ‘unconditional relevance’ and ‘conditional relevance’ as those terms and related concepts are applied in the context of admissibility determinations in modern trials. I take the U.S. Federal Rules of Evidence to be my model in analyzing these concepts, though on my view any reasonable approach to legal evidence will have to distinguish between these concepts and make appropriate provisions for their separate treatment. I begin by explaining how the Federal Rules (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  9
    The moral permissibility of banishment.E. E. Sheng - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (3):285-310.
    This essay defends the moral permissibility, as a form of punishment, of banishment, namely the exclusion by a state of a citizen from its territory. I begin by outlining the prima facie case for banishment, consider for whom it may be appropriate, and acknowledge constraints on its permissibility. I then defend banishment against the main objections in the literature to banishment or the related measure of denationalization (stripping citizens of their citizenship): impermissible permanency; excessive severity; ineffectiveness; unfairness to those who (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  4
    The Phenomenology and Ethics of P-Centricity in Mental Capacity Law.Camillia Kong - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (2):145-175.
    Under the Mental Capacity Act 2005 (MCA) in England and Wales, the liberal commitments to subjective freedom guide obligations towards persons who do not lack capacity. For the subject of proceedings who might lack capacity (P), it is less clear as to what obligations orient best interests decision-making on their behalf. The UK Supreme Court has emphasised the centrality of ‘P-centricity’ in best interests decision-making, where there is the legal obligation to consider P’s subjective views and wishes in a holistic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  31
    Now It’s Personal: From Me to Mine to Property Rights.David Shoemaker & Bas van der Vossen - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (2):177-203.
    Philosophical theories of property rights struggle to adequately explain the moral significance of ownership. We propose that the moral significance of property rights is due to the intersection of what we call "the extended self” and conventionally protected rights claims. The latter, drawing on conventionalist accounts of property rights, explains the social nature and flexibility of property. The former, drawing on naturalist theories, explains their personal nature. The upshot is that we find at this intersection the full moral significance of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  16
    Kinship, Justice, and Inheritance: The Case of ‘Rest’ in Ethiopia.Kebadu Mekonnen Gebremariam - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (1):37-55.
    This paper argues that the inheritance of wealth must be grounded on reasons other than the defense of the testator’s right to bequeath or that of an heir’s alleged moral right to receive inheritance. It asserts that the accepted approach in anglophone political philosophy about the justice of inheritance along the framework of ‘justice in transfer’ is misguided. Taking _Rest_ land inheritance in Ethiopia as a case study, it defends a system of corporate ownership of land by the descent group (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  14
    Coercion Without Incapacitation.William R. Tadros - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (1):1-36.
    This essay examines why coerced conduct tends not to have the moral and legal consequences that non-coerced conduct often has. In it, I argue against the “incapacitation approach,” the view that coerced conduct tends not to result in the coercer acquiring a permission or an entitlement because the coercee is typically incapable of exercising her rights to change the coercer’s permissions or entitlements. After demonstrating that coercees retain the ability to exercise those rights, this article develops an alternative account: that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
 Previous issues
  
Next issues