Philosophical Psychology

ISSN: 0951-5089

44 found

View year:

  1.  7
    Critical Psychiatry: A Landmark Exploration in Contemporary Thought. [REVIEW]Adrian Kind - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (3).
    Who would buy a book full of interviews that can be accessed online? Perhaps only some bibliophile readers. Hence, a quick glance at "Conversations in Critical Psychiatry"—consisting of a significant portion of interviews with philosophers, clinicians, and researchers previously published in Psychiatric Times—might lead one to conclude that this volume is of little interest. But such a conclusion would be premature.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  28
    On the importance of infant carrying for social learning and the development of social cognition.Juraj Bánovský - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):847-874.
    Infant carrying provides an important context for cognitive development and social learning in the first year of life. It enables children to perceive the world from a perspective similar to that of their parents. Lateral carrying provides children with new experiences because it gives them access to a broader range of objects. It also gives them better access to socially significant stimuli and aspects of the environment that are relevant to their parents. Thus, it can significantly contribute to learning about (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  28
    A philosophical approach to improving empirical research on posttraumatic growth.Michael Brady & Eranda Jayawickreme - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):796-819.
    Post-traumatic growth (PTG) has been a key topic of research by psychologists over the last 25 years. But the idea that a person can benefit from adversity has been around for much longer, and is a stable in many mainstream cultures, and in theological and recent philosophical thinking. However, there has been, to date, little overlap between psychological research into PTG, and philosophical thinking about similar ideas. This is unfortunate, both because philosophers are not taking up potential sources of empirical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Mental representation, “standing-in-for”, and internal models.Rosa Cao & Jared Warren - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):379-396.
    Talk of ”mental representations” is ubiquitous in the philosophy of mind, psychology, and cognitive science. A slogan common to many different approaches says that representations ”stand in for” the things they represent. This slogan also attaches to most talk of "internal models" in cognitive science. We argue that this slogan is either false or uninformative. We then offer a new slogan that aims to do better. The new slogan ties the role of representations to the cognitive role played by the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  37
    Capturing the Elusive Self.Tony Cheng - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):978-981.
    Psychology and philosophy have maintained a special relationship since very long ago. Nowadays, many psychologists stay away from philosophy and focus on the empirical methods in their studies. The...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  44
    Visual assumption and perceptual social bias. De Yang - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):922-947.
    Siegel recently distinguishes between seven possible ways in which our perceptual access to social information can be biased by flawed practice of either individuals or social structures, two of which, namely attention and cognitive penetration, imply that it is the content of perception, as opposed to that of judgments, that is biased. Both attention and cognitive penetration, however, rely on cognitive states imposing top-down influences on perceptual states. As such, perceptual bias resulting from them is to a large extent merely (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  22
    Posthumous autonomy: Agency and consent in body donation.Tom Farsides & Claire F. Smith - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):599-624.
    Six people were interviewed about the possibility of becoming posthumous body donors. Interview transcripts were analyzed using interpretative phenomenological analysis. Individual-level analysis suggested a common interest in Personhood Concerns and a common commitment to Enlightenment Values. Investigations of these possible themes across participants resulted in identification of two sample-level themes, each with two subthemes: Autonomy, with subthemes of agency and consent, and Rationality, with subthemes of knowledge/epistemology and materialism/ontology. This paper concentrates on the former. Consent for posthumous body donation was (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  8
    Efficient mechanisms.Jorge Ignacio Fuentes - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):555-578.
    A distinguishing feature of neural computation and information processing is that it fits models that describe the most efficient strategies for performing different cognitive tasks. Efficiency determines a distinctive sense of teleology involving optimal performance and resource management through a specific strategy. I articulate this kind of teleology and call it efficient teleological function. I argue that efficient teleological function is compatible with mechanistic explanation and, most likely, neural computational mechanisms are efficiently functional in this sense. They are members of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  22
    Blame-validation: Beyond rationality? Effect of causal link on the relationship between evaluation and causal judgment.Valentin Goulette & Fanny Verkampt - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):436-455.
    The Culpable Control Model assumes that causal judgments are irrational: a negative evaluative reaction to an agent would lead individuals to overestimate his causal contribution to a harm. However, the extent to which these judgments deviate from criteria of rationality remains unclear. The two present studies aimed at investigating conditions under which this effect occurs. Participants red a vignette in which the evaluative reaction was operationalized through the agent’s motives (blameworthy, laudable). We also varied the causal link between the agent’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  51
    Can memory color effects be explained by cognitive penetration?Woojin Han - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):648-666.
    Orange heart shapes are commonly perceived as slightly reddish, which is an example of the memory color effect (MCE). Given that the MCE is a modulation of visual memories of typical colors of familiar objects, it can be considered to be a top-down effect. Whether cognitive penetration can explain MCEs has been actively debated since Macpherson argued that the belief that hearts are red alters orange perception. This paper aims to provide a credible explanation of the MCE that is consistent (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  41
    Becoming episodic: The Development of Objectivity.Frauke Hildebrandt & Ramiro Glauer - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):456-479.
    We argue that objectivity is acquired by learning to refer to particular situations, that is, by developing episodicity. This contrasts with the widespread idea that genericity is crucial in developing humans’ ability to conceive of an objective world. According to the collective intentionality account, objectivity is acquired by contrasting one’s particular perspective in the “here and now” with a generic group perspective on how things are generally. However, this line of argument rests on confusing two independent notions of genericity: social (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  20
    Must we tolerate hate?James M. Jasper - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):969-973.
    “The British people relish a good hero and a good hate,” proclaimed Alfred Harmsworth, who in 1896 brought cheap, jingoistic journalism to Britain with the Daily Mail, which quickly became the nati...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  13
    (1 other version)Epistemic injustice in psychiatric research and practice.Ian James Kidd, Lucienne Spencer & Havi Carel - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):503-531.
    This paper offers an overview of the philosophical work on epistemic injustices as it relates to psychiatry. After describing the development of epistemic injustice studies, we survey the existing literature on its application to psychiatry. We describe how the concept of epistemic injustice has been taken up into a range of debates in philosophy of psychiatry, including the nature of psychiatric conditions, psychiatric practices and research, and ameliorative projects. The final section of the paper indicates future directions for philosophical research (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  26
    Reconsidering commonsense consent.Hanna Kim - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):397-435.
    In the 2020 Yale Law Journal article, “Commonsense Consent,” Roseanna Sommers argues that deception is compatible with the layperson’s intuitive sense of consent. That is, unlike the canonical understanding of consent defended by legal scholars and philosophers, the notion of consent defended by the folk is not invalidated by deception. In this study, I find that while respondents do appear to attribute consent to victims of deception, they do so in a limited number of contexts – i.e., they attribute de (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  4
    (1 other version)The normative turn in recent literature on psychotherapy.Ulrich Koch & Kelso Cratsley - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):667-694.
    The last few years have seen a marked increase of interest in the ethics of psychotherapy. As the field of mental health has recently taken on a new level of prominence, renewed commitment to the ethical analysis of psychiatric and psychological treatment is clearly required. In this review essay, we survey recent work on psychotherapy ethics, taking a critical yet generally sympathetic view of the new literature. There are important considerations that remain neglected or overlooked entirely, in our view, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  26
    It’s common sense – you don’t need to believe to disagree!Miklós Kürthy, Graham Bex-Priestley & Yonatan Shemmer - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):695-717.
    It is often assumed that disagreement only occurs when there is a clash (e.g., inconsistency) between beliefs. In the philosophical literature, this “narrow” view has sometimes been considered the obvious, intuitively correct view. In this paper, we argue that it should not be. We have conducted two preregistered studies gauging English speakers’ intuitions about whether there is disagreement in a case where the parties have non-clashing beliefs and clashing intentions. Our results suggest that common intuitions tell against the default view. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  36
    Free will: it unlikely exists in light of psychological theories; it “floats” in the complexity paradigm.Felix Lebed - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):948-968.
    This paper explores whether human proactivity can be considered an expression of free will. The discussion involves two paradigms, which are mutually complementary and encompass psychological proactivity and reactivity. Both paradigms raise the question of linear and non-linear determinism, which inevitably leads to the issue of free will. The analysis attempts to find a compromise between linear and non-linear determinism through the approach of human dialectical complexity (Lebed & Bar-Eli, 2013). This refers to the relationships of two types of complex (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  91
    Gunning for affective realism: Emotion, perception and police shooting errors.Raamy Majeed - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):532-554.
    Affective realism, roughly the hypothesis that you “perceive what you feel”, has recently been put forward as a novel, empirically-backed explanation of police shooting errors. The affective states involved in policing in high-pressure situations result in police officers literally seeing guns even when none are present. The aim of this paper is to (i) unpack the implications of this explanation for assessing police culpability and (ii) determine whether we should take these implications at face value. I argue that while affective (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  33
    Towards a new standard model of concepts?Christian Michel - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):974-977.
    Guy Dove’s book is about the puzzle of how our minds can represent and process abstract concepts. Abstract concepts have posed a problem for the influential view of the embodied mind and grounded c...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  32
    Sacrificing objects instead of persons: Order effects without emotional engagement.Emilian Mihailov, Ivar R. Hannikainen & Alex Wiegmann - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):579-598.
    In this paper we develop test cases to adjudicate between dual-process and the causal mapping explanations of order effects. Using dilemmas with minimized emotional force, we explore new conditions for order effects to occur. Overall, the results support causal model theory. We produced novel evidence that order effects extend not only to cases with low emotional engagement, but also to specialized judgments about whether an action violates a rule. However, when objects are sacrificed instead of persons the order effect either (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  24
    Watching the watchmen: Vigilance-based models of honesty fail to explain it.Camilo Ordóñez-Pinilla & William Jiménez-Leal - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):767-795.
    Promoting honesty is considered a key endeavor in the betterment of our societies. However, our understanding of this phenomenon, and of its evil twin, dishonesty, is still lacking. In this text, we analyze the main tenets assumed by empirical models of vigilance and sanctions. We approach our analysis in three sections. Initially, we investigate the concept of honesty as assumed by commonly used methodologies in studying honesty. This then leads us to identify the previously overlooked but essential element of epistemic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  26
    Implications of the TASI taxonomy for understanding inconsistent effects pertaining to free will beliefs.Tom St Quinton & David Trafimow - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):480-502.
    Whether people possess free will has been a long-lasting philosophical debate. Recent attention in social psychology has been given to the behavioral consequences of believing in free will. Research has demonstrated that manipulating free will beliefs has implications for many social behaviors. For example, free will belief manipulations have been associated with cheating, aggressiveness, and prejudice. Despite this work, some of these findings have failed to replicate. Testing theoretical predictions, such as whether believing in free will influences behavior, depends on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  13
    Guess who? Identity attribution as Bayesian inference.Francesco Rigoli - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):875-896.
    An influential argument is that mental processes can be explained at three different levels of analysis: the functional, algorithmic, and implementation level. Identity attribution (the process whereby an identity is attributed to another individual or to the self) has been rarely explored at the functional level. To address this, here I propose a theory of identity attribution grounded on Bayesian inference, being the latter a well-established functional perspective in cognitive science. The theory posits that an identity is inferred based on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  29
    A Kaleidoscope of play: a new approach to play analysis in childhood.Laura Sparaci & Shaun Gallagher - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):718-747.
    Play is a frequent and relevant activity during childhood, and developmental psychologists agree that it offers a unique window on development. Play, however, remains a fuzzy concept, and difficulties persist in its definition, often leading to obstacles in building and comparing experimental studies. This may be due to widespread tendencies to define play by referring to non-observable inner states, to consider playing something that occurs in the head rather than in-the-world and to overreliance on developmental stages. Enactive approaches to child (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Curiosity and zetetic style in ADHD.Asbjørn Steglich-Petersen & Somogy Varga - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):897-921.
    While research on Attention Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder (ADHD) has traditionally focused on cognitive and behavioral deficits, there is increasing interest in exploring possible resources associated with the disorder. In this paper, we argue that the attention-patterns associated with ADHD can be understood as expressing an alternative style of inquiry, or “zetetic” style, characterized mainly by a lower barrier for becoming curious and engaging in inquiry, and a weaker disposition to regulate curiosity in response to the cognitive and practical costs associated (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  6
    With great(er) power comes great(er) responsibility: an intercultural investigation of the effect of social roles on moral responsibility attribution.Pascale Https://Orcidorg Willemsen, Albert Https://Orcidorg Newen, Karolina Https://Orcidorg914X Prochownik & Kai Https://Orcidorg Kaspar - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):820-846.
    This paper investigates the relevance of social roles and hierarchies for the attribution of blame and causation in five culturally different countries, namely China, Germany, Poland, the United Arabic Emirates, and the United States of America. We demonstrate that in all these countries, hierarchical differences between the social roles occupied by two agents and associated differences in duties to care for others affect how these two agents are morally and causally judged when they make a decision together. Agents higher in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  30
    Virtue for affective engines.Chris Zarpentine - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (2):748-766.
    Practical reasoning is reasoning about what to do. Practical wisdom is the traditional ideal of practical reasoning associated with virtue ethics. Practical wisdom requires the knowledge and skills necessary to act rightly across a wide range of situations. Critics allege that this notion does not cohere well with what contemporary cognitive science tells us about the production of human behavior. After briefly discussing these criticisms, I sketch an alternative account of these cognitive processes that I call affective engine theory. I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  5
    Contextualising mental health: interdisciplinary contributions to a new model for tackling social differences and inequalities in mental healthcare.Roxana Baiasu & Guilherme Messas - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):246-266.
    Many classical approaches in the area of phenomenological pscyhopathology focus on structures of lived experience of mental illness and overlook the role social context plays in the formation of lived experiences. The paper addresses this issue and contributes to recent research which has pointed out that there is a need for an approach to mental health which investigates the role of context in shaping lived experiences. We propose a conception of contextuality (or situatedness) which we develop in terms of two (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  24
    “Minimal self” locked into a model: exploring the prospect of formalizing intentionality in schizophrenia.Marianne D. Broeker & Matthew R. Broome - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):331-352.
    Computational psychiatry is a quickly evolving discipline that aims to understand psychopathology in terms of computational, hence algorithmic processes. While cognitive phenomena, especially beliefs or ways of “reasoning”, can more easily be formalized, meaning re-described in mathematical terms and then entered computational models, there is speculation as to whether phenomenology might be formalizable too. In other words, there are speculations in terms of what aspects of the human experience, rather than specific cognitive processes alone, can enter computational models. Here, we (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  29
    Silence, depression, and bodily doubt: toward a phenomenology of silence in psychopathology.Dan Degerman - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):126-149.
    Despite the relevance of silence in several psychopathologies, first-person perspectives on silence have been largely neglected in the phenomenological scholarship on those conditions. This paper proposes a phenomenological framework for addressing this neglect and demonstrates its usefulness through a case study of empty silence, an experience which can be found in many first-person accounts of depression. The paper begins by surveying research on silence in depression in mental health research and phenomenological psychopathology. Drawing on the thought of Merleau-Ponty, it then (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  41
    The death of the self in posttraumatic experience.Jake Dorothy & Emily Hughes - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):168-188.
    Survivors of trauma commonly report feeling as though a part of themselves has died. This article provides a theoretical interpretation of this phenomenon, drawing on Waldenfels' notion of the split self. We argue that trauma gives rise to an explicit tension between the lived and corporeal body which is so profoundly distressing that it can be experienced by survivors as the death of part of oneself. We explore the ways in which this is manifest in the posttraumatic phenomena of dissociation; (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  25
    Self-disorders in schizophrenia as disorders of transparency: an exploratory account.Jasper Feyaerts, Barnaby Nelson & Louis Sass - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):49-76.
    Understanding alterations of selfhood (termed self-disorders or self-disturbances) that are considered typical of the schizophrenia-spectrum is a central focus of phenomenological research. The currently most influential way of phenomenologically conceiving self-disorders in schizophrenia is as disorders of the so-called most basic or “minimal self”. In this paper, we first highlight some challenges for the minimal self-view of self-disorders, focusing on (1) problems arising from the supposedly “essential” or “universal” nature of minimal self with respect to phenomenal awareness and (2) the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  19
    Situating evaluativism in psychiatry: on the axiological dimension of phenomenological psychopathology and Fulford’s value-based practice.Alessandro Guardascione - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):267-303.
    Evaluativists hold that psychiatric disorders have a factual and evaluative dimension and recognize that psychiatric patients have an active role in shaping their symptoms, influencing the development of their disorders, and the outcome of psychiatric therapy. This is reflected in person-centered approaches that explicitly consider the role of values in psychiatric conceptualization, classification, and decision-making. In this respect, in light of the recent partnership between Fulford’s value-based practice (VBP), and Stanghellini’s phenomenological-hermeneutic-dynamical (P.H.D) psychotherapy method, this paper presents a comparative analysis (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  13
    Autistic trans camouflaging: an early phenomenological exploration.Ruby Hake - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):150-167.
    Autistic people often camouflage, i.e. they adopt certain behaviors in order to fit in in neurotypical environments. Autobiographical accounts suggest that autistic trans people experience camouflaging in a unique, more complex and often heightened way than cis autistic people, and this has not been studied. They have autistic traits to mask, as well as gendered traits, in a hostile neuronormative and cisnormative world. This intersection of experience is worthy of exploration, not least because this group of people are typically misunderstood (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  62
    Allegedly impossible experiences.Sofia Jeppsson - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):77-99.
    In this paper, I will argue for two interrelated theses. First, if we take phenomenological psychopathology seriously, and want to understand what it is like to undergo various psychopathological experiences, we cannot treat madpeople’s testimony as mere data for sane clinicians, philosophers, and other scholars to analyze and interpret. Madpeople must be involved with analysis an interpretation too. Second, sane clinicians and scholars must open their minds to the possibility that there may be experiences that other people have, which they (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  20
    Thinking in schizophrenia and the social phenomenology of thought insertion.Pablo López-Silva - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):17-48.
    Patients suffering from delusions of thought insertion (TI) report that external agents of different nature have placed thoughts into their minds. The symptom involves distressing feelings of intromission and exposition, loss of mental privacy, diminished ego boundaries, and a – often neglected – peculiar “physicality”. A dominant approach within cognitive sciences characterizes TI as involving alterations in the experience of being the author of certain thoughts. For the advocates of this so-called Standard Approach to TI, the absence of a sense (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  20
    Open-mindedness and phenomenological psychopathology: an intellectual virtue account of phenomenology and three educational recommendations.Andrew Jonathan Maile - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):304-330.
    In his account of phenomenological psychopathology, Karl Jaspers advocates for the central role of subjective experience, something which he maintains cannot be accessed through intellectual effort, but through “empathic understanding” alone. In contradistinction to Jaspers’ account, I propose that phenomenology, as a process of inquiry and investigation, is fundamentally epistemological. Accordingly, I offer an intellectual virtue characterization of phenomenological psychopathology, using open-mindedness to illustrate the close conceptual links between the phenomenological endeavor and the intellectual virtues. By introducing the intellectual virtue (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  32
    Psychotherapy of the oppressed: the education of Paulo Freire in dialogue with phenomenology.Valter L. Piedade & Guilherme Messas - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):189-208.
    The current paradigm of mental health has fallen short in its promises to deliver better care and quality of life for those who lives with mental illness. Recent works have expressed the need for more comprehensive frameworks of research, in which phenomenology emerges as a fundamental tool for a new wave interdisciplinary studies with the humanities. In line with this project, this article hopes to explore the relation between education and phenomenologically oriented psychotherapy, through the work of Brazilian educator Paulo (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  6
    Clinical narrative and the painful side of conscious experience.Jesús Ramírez-Bermúdez, Ximena González-Grandón & Rosa Aurora Chávez - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):353-377.
    This article explores a literary tradition situated at the intersection of scientific reports, memoirs, and creative writing, termed “clinical narrative.” This genre offers a profound approach to the painful aspects of conscious experience, particularly the phenomenological states associated with mental illness and brain disease, seen as unsettling landscapes of phenomenal experience. Through case studies providing multifaceted viewpoints – first-person, second-person, and third-person perspectives – we argue that clinical narratives are valuable resources for a transepistemic study of consciousness. By examining clinical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  42
    Socialized into depression – toward a social phenomenological psychopathology.Domonkos Sik - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):100-125.
    The article aims at expanding the horizon of phenomenological psychopathology of depression from a social theoretical perspective. Based on Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenological ontology, in the first section, depression is reinterpreted as a disruption of chiasm: it is not merely the illness of the body, the disorder of the mind, or a specific form of social suffering, but the interrelated distortion of time consciousness, agency, and interaffectivity. The phenomenological clarification of these components provides opportunity for connecting sociological and psychopathological insight. In the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  18
    The future of phenomenological psychopathology.Lucienne Spencer, Matthew R. Broome & Giovanni Stanghellini - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):1-16.
    The ways in which we attempt to make sense of psychiatric illness have been slow to progress. Over the last several decades, clinicians and researchers have inherited one-size-fits-all diagnostic f...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  21
    Existential injustice in phenomenological psychopathology.Daniel Vespermann & Sanna Karoliina Tirkkonen - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology 38 (1):209-245.
    In this article, we investigate how distressing background feelings can be subject to social injustice. We define background feelings as enduring feeling states that condition our perceptions of everyday situations, interpersonal dynamics, and the broader social milieu. While phenomenological psychopathology has long addressed such affective phenomena, including anxiety, guilt, and feelings of not belonging, the intersection with social injustice remains largely unexplored within the framework. To address this gap, we introduce the concept of existential injustice into phenomenological psychopathology. Existential injustice (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  2
    Engrams and causal specificity.Jonathan Najenson - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology:1-27.
    The identification of memory engrams remains a methodological obstacle in neuroscience if they are to play the explanatory role ascribed to them by engram theory. I tackle the problem of specificity, namely the extent to which engrams can be identified, tracked, and distinguished from other engram and non-engram vehicles. I propose that adopting causal specificity from the interventionist framework of causation allows us to describe how engrams are specific to the memories and behaviors they generate. Drawing on recent work using (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  14
    What's my motivation? Reputational motives, virtue signaling, and self-directed mindshaping.Leda Berio - 2025 - Philosophical Psychology.
    In engaging in public moral discourse and publicly visible moral behavior, our motivations can be mixed: while on the one hand we might want to genuinely commit to norms we find morally virtuous, we can also be strongly motivated by enhancing our reputation. At times, we might even be accused of “virtue signaling”, that is, of engaging in moral discourse for self-aggrandizing and reputational gains. We might consider these reputational motives as a barrier to moral progress. In this paper, I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
 Previous issues
  
Next issues