Related

Contents
1126 found
Order:
1 — 50 / 1126
Material to categorize
  1. Hume's Philosophy of Belief: Is Religious Belief Natural Belief? Emine Gocer - 2024 - Journal of the Faculty of Divinity of Cukurova University 24 (1):29-44.
    Among the politics of belief that we encounter in Early Modern Philosophy, Hume's concept of natural belief is known as a problematic area to understand. Although Hume develops a concept of belief based on sensation and sensation, the fact that it is controversial to consider it as an empiricist method when considered together with his scepticism is related to the fact that he sees the method he develops as a natural tendency and habit rather than an inferential method. Whether Hume's (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. A Virtuous Way of Doing Philosophy: The Moderation of Curiosity and Hume’s Philosophical Method in A Treatise of Human Nature.Manuel Vásquez Villavicencio - 2024 - Hume Studies 49 (2):231-256.
    In _A Treatise of Human Nature_, Hume proposes a new philosophical method. This method results from integrating an empirically founded skepticism with an innovative study of the epistemic role of emotions. This combination of skepticism, empiricism, and moral psychology aims to establish a virtuous way of doing philosophy based on the regulation of our epistemic emotions. In this paper, I present the operating principles of this virtuous way of doing philosophy. The paper has three parts. I firstly claim that four (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Hume’s Causal Reconstruction of the Perceptual Relativity Argument in Treatise 1.4.4.Annemarie Butler - 2009 - Dialogue 48 (1):77-101.
    ABSTRACT: In Treatise 1.4.4, on behalf of modern philosophers, Hume described a causal argument that shows that our impressions of secondary qualities do not resemble qualities of objects themselves. However, in their respective arguments, Hume’s philosophical predecessors did not argue causally, but appealed to contrary qualities. I argue that Hume’s presentation was not simply a “gratuitous” stylistic difference, but an important correction of his predecessors in light of his own philosophical discoveries. -/- RÉSUMÉ : Dans le Traité 1.4.4, Hume a (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4. (1 other version)Hume's Theory of Knowledge. A Critical Examination.Constance Maund - 1937 - Philosophy 12 (48):488-489.
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5. (1 other version)Hume's Scepticism.Robert E. Butts - 1959 - Journal of the History of Ideas 20 (3):413.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Philosophy and the Good Life: Hume's Defence of Probable Reasoning.David Owen - 1996 - Dialogue 35 (3):485-504.
    At the beginning of his section “Of Miracles,” Hume mentions an argument of Dr. Tillotson. The doctrine of “the real presence” seems contradicted by our senses. We see a piece of bread, but are asked to believe it consists in the substance of the body of Christ.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. David Hume: His Theory of Knowledge and Morality.Hume: Theory of Knowledge.G. P. Henderson - 1952 - Philosophical Quarterly 2 (8):270-271.
  8. Hume’s Moral Epistemology.Stewart R. Sutherland - 1978 - Philosophical Quarterly 28 (110):77-78.
  9. (1 other version)Hume's Theory of Knowledge: A Critical Examination.M. B. Singer - 1937 - International Journal of Ethics 48 (1):128-130.
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10. (1 other version)On the Nature and Significance of Hume's Scepticism.Constance Maund - 1952 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 6 (20):168-183.
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11. (1 other version)Some Misunderstandings of Hume.T. E. Jessop - 1952 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 6 (20):155-167.
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12. Hume's "gematigd" scepticisme: futiel of fataal?Patricia De Martelaere - 1981 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 43:427-464.
    The aim of this paper is to make clear in what sense Hume's actually very radical scepticism can nevertheless be called moderate, and not only leaves intact the praxis in daily life but is even compatible with a — modest and experimental — form of science. The first part stresses the theoretical profoundness of Hume's scepticism, and more specifically the arguments concerning the validity of reason and those concerning some typically 'metaphysical' objects. The former culminate in the impossibility of determining (...)
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. (1 other version)Hume on Knowledge, by Harold Noonan. [REVIEW]P. J. E. Kail - 2001 - Mind 110 (440):1102-1105.
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  14. (1 other version)Hume’s Skepticism in the Treatise of Human Nature.Robert J. Fogelin - 1985 - Mind 95 (379):392-396.
  15. (3 other versions)Hume.Terence Penelhum - 1978 - Mind 87 (346):287-289.
  16. (1 other version)Hume: Theory of Knowledge.D. C. Yalden-Thomson - 1954 - Philosophy of Science 21 (3):270-270.
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Sellars on Hume and Kant on Representing Complexes.David Landy - 2009 - European Journal of Philosophy 17 (2):224-246.
    No Abstract In his graduate-seminar lectures on Kant—published as Kant and Pre-Kantian Themes (Sellars, 2002)—Wilfrid Sellars argues that because Hume cannot distinguish between a vivacious idea and an idea of something vivacious he cannot account for the human ability to represent temporally complex states of affairs. The first section of this paper aims to show that this argument is not properly aimed at the historical Hume who can, on a proper reading, distinguish these kinds of representations. This is not, however, (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  18. Is Hume really a reductivist?Michael Welbourne - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33 (2):407-423.
    Coady misrepresents Hume as a reductivist about testimony. Hume occasionally writes carelessly as if what goes for beliefs based on induction will also go for beliefs obtained from testimony. But, in fact, he has no theory of testimony at all, though in his more considered remarks he rightly thinks, as does Reid, that the natural response to a bit of testimony is simply to accept the information which it contains. The sense in which we owe the beliefs we get from (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  19. Imagination and Experimentalism in Hume’s Philosophy.Andrew Ward - 2012 - Southwest Philosophy Review 28 (1):165-175.
  20. The Rules for Dispositional Judgment in Hume’s Treatise.Walter Brand - 1992 - Southwest Philosophy Review 8 (2):1-11.
  21. Inference, Reason and Reasoning in Book One of Hume’s Treatise.David Owen - 1994 - Southwest Philosophy Review 10 (1):17-27.
  22. Imagination and Experimentalism in Hume’s Philosophy.J. Mock - 2012 - Southwest Philosophy Review 28 (1):165-175.
  23. Hume's First Principle, His Missing Shade, and His Distinctions of Reason.Karánn Durland - 1996 - Hume Studies 22 (1):105-121.
  24. Custom and Reason in Hume. [REVIEW]Paul Guyer - 2009 - Hume Studies 35 (1-2):236-239.
    Henry Allison offers a new understanding of Hume's theory of knowledge, as contained in the first book of his Treatise. Allison provides a comprehensive and detailed critical analysis of Hume's views on the subject, and an extensive comparison with Kant on a range of issues including space and time, causation, existence, and the self.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Philosophical Relations, Natural Relations, and Philosophic Decisionism in Belief in the External World: Comments on P. J. E. Kail, Projection and Realism in Hume’s Philosophy. [REVIEW]Eric Schliesser - 2010 - Hume Studies 36 (1):67-76.
    My critical comments on Part I of P. J. E. Kail's Projection and Realism in Hume's Philosophy are divided into two parts. First, I challenge the exegetical details of Kail's take on Hume's important distinction between natural and philosophical relations. I show that Kail misreads Hume in a subtle fashion. If I am right, then much of the machinery that Kail puts into place for his main argument does different work in Hume than Kail thinks. Second, I offer a brief (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Hume's Epistemic Naturalism in the Treatise.Tim Black - 2011 - Hume Studies 37 (2):211-242.
    We can understand epistemic naturalism as the view that there are cases in which we are justified in holding a belief and cases in which we are not so justified, and that we can distinguish cases of one sort from cases of the other with reference to non-normative facts about the mechanisms that produce them. By my lights, Hume is an epistemic naturalist of this sort, and I propose in this paper a novel and detailed account of his epistemic naturalism. (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. The Vulgar Conception of Objects in "Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses".Stefanie Rocknak - 2007 - Hume Studies 33 (1):67-90.
    In this paper, we see that contrary to most readings of T 1.4.2 in the Treatise ("Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses"), Hume does not think that objects are sense impressions. This means that Hume's position on objects (whatever that may be) is not to be conflated with the vulgar perspective. Moreover, the vulgar perspective undergoes a marked transition in T 1.4.2, evolving from what we may call vulgar perspective I into vulgar perspective II. This paper presents the first (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28. Belief and Introspective Knowledge in Treatise 1.3.7.Jennifer Smalligan Marušić - 2011 - Hume Studies 37 (1):99-122.
    Hume argues that the difference between belief and mere conception consists in a difference in the manner of conception. His argument assumes that the difference between belief and mere conception must be a function of either the content conceived or of the manner of conception; however, it is unclear what justifies this assumption. I argue that the assumption depends on Hume’s confidence that we can know immediately that we believe when we believe, and that we can only have such knowledge (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Walking the Tightrope of Reason. [REVIEW]Ira Singer - 2005 - Hume Studies 31 (1):169-172.
    This lively little book — 170 small-format pages, excluding front and end matter — has its origin in the author’s 1995 Romanell-Phi Beta Kappa lectures at Dartmouth College. Consistent with this origin, it speaks primarily to a general audience rather than to philosophical specialists. Nevertheless, even specialist readers will find Walking the Tightrope of Reason valuable. It revisits figures and issues that have long and productively occupied Fogelin, and here we see his thoughts about these figures and issues clearly and (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Projection and Realism in Hume's Philosophy (review). [REVIEW]Stephen Buckle - 2008 - Hume Studies 34 (1):163-165.
  31. Hume's Probability Argument of I,iv,1.Richard DeWitt - 1985 - Hume Studies 11 (2):125-140.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:125, HUME'S PROBABILITY ARGUMENT OF?,??,? In the Treatise,?,??,?, Hume presents an follows:' argument which, in the barest of outlines, goes as 1 (Pl) Every proposition has a probability less than one. (P2) If reason were the basis of our beliefs, then we would have no beliefs. (follows from (Pl)) (P3) We in fact do have beliefs. Hence, (P4) Reason is not the basis of our beliefs. The argument has (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32. Stability and Justification in Hume’s Treatise. [REVIEW]David Owen - 2004 - International Philosophical Quarterly 44 (2):271-273.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. The distinction between coherence and constancy in Hume's Treatise I.iv.2.Tim Black - 2007 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 15 (1):1-25.
    In the Treatise, Book I, Part iv, Section 2, Hume seeks to explain what causes us to believe that objects continue to exist even when they are not perceived. He argues that we won't be able to prov...
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34. Hume’s Naturalism about Cognitive Norms.Janet Broughton - 2003 - Philosophical Topics 31 (1-2):1-19.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35. A Via Media Between Scepticism and Dogmatism?Gerald McCarthy - 2009 - Newman Studies Journal 6 (2):57-81.
    Beginning with an overview of the knowledge claims proposed by John Locke and David Hume, this essay first explores the respective responses of Newman and W. G. Ward and then updates the discussion by bringing Newman into dialogue with the thoughtof Alasdair MacIntyre.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36. The Consequences of Hume’s Epistemology.Aristotelis Santas - 1995 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 10 (1):1-8.
  37. (1 other version)Hume's Alleged Pyrrhonism.Dorothy Coleman - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (4):461-468.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. Norman Kemp Smith on “Natural Belief”.Thomas K. Hearn - 1969 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 7 (1):3-7.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. The Concept of Truth in Hume's Treatise.Lilly-Marlene Russow - 1981 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 19 (2):217-228.
  40. Hume's Scepticism Regarding ‘Probable Reasoning’ in the Treatise.Owen Raynor - 1964 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 2 (3):103-106.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Was Hume a Subjectivist?Fred Wilson - 1988 - Philosophy Research Archives 14:247-282.
    In a crucial passage in the Treatise, Hume argues that all our sense impressions are dependent for their existence upon the state of our sense organs. Hume points out that this is not the same as an ontological dependence upon minds; and moreover the argument is clearly causal. Hume uses it to establish the system of the philosophers as opposed to the system of the vulgar. This paper argues that Hume’s case parallels that which, in this century, the critical realists (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Hume on Deduction.Charles Echelbarger - 1987 - Philosophy Research Archives 13:351-365.
    In this paper, the author discusses the feasibility of constructing a Humean model of the psychological realities of categorical propositions and syllogistic deduction by employing only Hume’s kinds of “ideas” and kinds of mental operations on ideas which Hume explicitly or implicitly postulated in his theory of discursive thinking.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Epistemological Skepticism(s) and Rational Self-Control.Brian Ribeiro - 2002 - The Monist 85 (3):468-477.
    In this paper I aim to do two things. First, I attempt to illustrate an interesting pattern of argument one can find in Hume's work. Next, I employ this Humean pattern of argument to show that IF there is a cogent and intuitive argument for any form of epistemological skepticism, which despite its cogency and intuitiveness has a unbelievable conclusion, THEN we lack a very important form of doxastic self-control, which I call rational self-control, over the beliefs problematized by that (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. (5 other versions)Truth, Probability and Paradox. [REVIEW]Maria Wolf - 1976 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 25:353-353.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. (1 other version)Hume: Theory of Knowledge. [REVIEW]Venant Cauchey - 1954 - New Scholasticism 28 (3):370-370.
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Hume’s Reason. [REVIEW]Charles Eschelbarger - 2004 - International Studies in Philosophy 36 (1):235-236.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Hume and the Contemporary “Common Sense” Critique of Hume.Lorne Falkenstein - 2016 - In Paul Russell (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of David Hume. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This paper examines the principal objections that Hume’s Scots contemporaries, George Campbell, James Beattie, and Thomas Reid raised against his views of testimony, belief, and the “theory of ideas.” In opposition to Kant’s claim that “Reid, Oswald, and Beattie” had “appealed to common sense as an oracle when insight and research [failed them]” and had “[taken] for granted what [Hume] meant to call into doubt while emphatically, and often with great indignation, demonstrating what he had never thought to question” it (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. (1 other version)The Tendency of Hume's Skepticism.Robert J. Fogelin - 1992 - In Philosophical interpretations. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This essay provides a survey of the central role of various radically skeptical arguments in David Hume's philosophy. The discussion relies upon a distinction between theoretical skepticism and prescriptive skepticism. A theoretical skepticism calls into question the grounds or the warrant for some important class of beliefs, e.g., our inductive beliefs about the future and our beliefs about the external world. A prescriptive skepticism recommends the suspension of belief for some class of beliefs. This essay is an attempt to show (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Contexts for Hume's Epistemological Projects.Louis E. Loeb - 2002 - In Stability and Justification in Hume's Treatise. New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Hume assigns a pivotal role to stability in understanding normativity in a variety of theoretical contexts, including the passions, justice, and moral judgment; in epistemology, he seeks to sustain his pretheoretical epistemic intuitions in terms of a stability‐based theory of justification. A distinctive feature of Hume's naturalism is that he tends to ground epistemic obligation in the desire to relieve the discomfort or felt uneasiness in unsettled states. Since he rejects the Pyrrhonian claim that ataraxia or quietude results from an (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. (2 other versions)Integrating Hume's Accounts of Belief and Justification.Louis E. Loeb - 2002 - In Stability and Justification in Hume's Treatise. New York, US: Oup Usa.
    In Treatise I.iii.5–10, Hume's claim that association by the relation of cause and effect produces belief is often intertwined – though without his remarking on this fact – with the claim that belief based on causal inference is justified. To explain this, I offer the hypothesis that, in Hume's view, stability plays a double role: whether belief is justified depends upon considerations of stability, and fixity, a species of stability is also essential to belief itself. Hume identifies belief with steadiness, (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1126