Contents
25 found
Order:
  1. Platonism, Neoplatonism, and the Hermetic Tradition.Francisco Bastitta-Harriet - 2021 - Oxford Bibliographies in Renaissance and Reformation.
    The trends of Platonism which proved to be the most influential throughout the Renaissance were born roughly around the same period as the Greek corpus attributed to the Egyptian sage Hermes Trismegistus. They resulted from the rich intermingling of Greek philosophy with other Near Eastern cultures since the time of Alexander the Great. It is not by chance, then, that their fortunes were bound together until the Early Modern period. Legend has it that Cosimo de’ Medici was highly impressed by (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Roger Bacon's Mathematics: Demonstrative System and Metaphysics in the Communia Mathematica.Flavia Marcacci - 2017 - Franciscan Studies 75:407-421.
    …sit necessaria sciencia mathematice ad bona anime procuranda.Scientific humanism in the 15th and 16th century witnessed the spread of Greek and Arabic mathematics, whose reading was disciplined by philological research, enriched by the practical sense of abacus masters and diffused by the press. This doesn't mean that before this time many of these works were totally unknown. Around the 13th century mathematics scholars were already familiar with the work of Theodosius, Archimedes, Vitruvius, the Banū Mūsā brothers and so on; however, (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Je Tomášovo pojetí matematiky instrumentalistické?Prokop Sousedík & David Svoboda - 2017 - Studia Neoaristotelica 14 (4):19-36.
    Responsione nostra disputationem cum L. Novák prosequimur, qui tractationem nostram, cui titulus “Různá pojetí matematiky u vybraných autorů od antiky po raný novověk”, impugnavit. Impugnatio a L. Novák sub titulo “Tomáš Akvinský instrumentalistou v matematice?” conscripta ansam praebuit nobis ad nonnulla, quae dixeramus, non solum clarius, sed etiam latius ac profundius explananda. Qua in re inprimis ad hoc attendimus, quomodo S. Thomas mathematicam, scientiasque medias necnon philosophiam intellexerit. Adhuc in nostra sententia sistimus, duplicem scil. ac valde diversam interpretationem harum disciplinarum (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Mathematics and Physics of First and Last Instants: Walter Burley and William of Ockham.Edith Dudley Sylla - 2017 - Vivarium 55 (1-3):103-129.
    In his De primo et ultimo instanti, Walter Burley paid careful attention to continuity, assuming that continua included and were limited by indivisibles such as instants, points, ubi, degrees of quality, or mutata esse. In his Tractatus primus, Burley applied the logic of first and last instants to reach novel conclusions about qualities and qualitative change. At the end of his Quaestiones in libros Physicorum Aristotelis, William of Ockham used long passages from Burley’s Tractatus primus, sometimes agreeing with Burley and (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Le opere dei sei giorni: aritmetica ed esegesi secundum physicam in Teodorico di Chartres.Clelia Crialesi - 2016 - Medioevo 41.
    This paper focuses on the exegetical proposal of the Tractatus de sex dierum operibus by Thierry of Chartres and it is tasked with analyzing the twofold interpretative framework adopted by the Cancelor: first, the accordance between the narration of Genesis and the heuristic models of physical and cosmological causality; second, the mathematical theology, which revises the work of creation according to an arithmological approach. The study is divided into two parts which follow the structure of the Tractatus. In the first (...)
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Elliptical Orbits and the Aristotelian Scientific Revolution Comment on Groarke.James Franklin - 2016 - Studia Neoaristotelica 13 (2):169-179.
    The Scientific Revolution was far from the anti-Aristotelian movement traditionally pictured. Its applied mathematics pursued by new means the Aristotelian ideal of science as knowledge by insight into necessary causes. Newton’s derivation of Kepler’s elliptical planetary orbits from the inverse square law of gravity is a central example.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Mathematical Theologies: Nicholas of Cusa and the Legacy of Thierry of Chartres by David Albertson.Denis Robichaud - 2015 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 53 (2):333-334.
  8. Toward a Neoaristotelian Inherence Philosophy of Mathematical Entities.Dale Jacquette - 2014 - Studia Neoaristotelica 11 (2):159-204.
    The fundamental idea of a Neoaristotelian inherence ontology of mathematical entities parallels that of an Aristotelian approach to the ontology of universals. It is proposed that mathematical objects are nominalizations especially of dimensional and related structural properties that inhere as formal species and hence as secondary substances of Aristotelian primary substances in the actual world of existent physical spatiotemporal entities. The approach makes it straightforward to understand the distinction between pure and applied mathematics, and the otherwise enigmatic success of applied (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9. Stredoveká filozofia a predpoklady modernej vedy.Gašpar Fronc - 2012 - In Ivana Miháliková (ed.), Fyzika a etika VI. Komunikácia v globalizačných procesoch a zmeny v kvalite života. Univerzita Konštantína Filozofa. pp. 244 – 261.
    The creators of modern science, such as Galileo Galilei and Isaac Newton, begun their work based on the principles which created generations before them. Nature Research has its origins back to antiquity. The Middle Ages is in general wrongly referred to as "The Dark Ages". Therefore dominates the incorrect opinion that the science had not been developed. In fact, now forgotten medieval scholars in comparison with antiquity had brought a fundamental change in the view of nature. The Christian doctrine of (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Algebraic symbolism in medieval Arabic algebra.Jeffrey A. Oaks - 2012 - Philosophica 87 (4):27-83.
  11. St. Augustine on Time, Time Numbers, and Enduring Objects.Jason W. Carter - 2011 - Vivarium 49 (4):301-323.
    Throughout his works, St. Augustine offers at least nine distinct views on the nature of time, at least three of which have remained almost unnoticed in the secondary literature. I first examine each these nine descriptions of time and attempt to diffuse common misinterpretations, especially of the views which seek to identify Augustinian time as consisting of an un-extended point or a distentio animi . Second, I argue that Augustine's primary understanding of time, like that of later medieval scholastics, is (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12. Medieval Infinities in Mathematics and the Contribution of Gersonides.George Kohler - 2006 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 23 (2):95 - 116.
  13. Un exemple de Question mathématique au Moyen Âge.Sabine Rommevaux - 2006 - Annals of Science 63 (4):425-445.
    Summary The practice of the disputatio in the medieval universities gave rise to a particular literary genre, the questio. This genre is caracterised by the production of arguments in favour of or against the thesis submitted for questio, before the author develops his own answer. This genre is common to philosophy and theology. But to present a mathematical problem in the form of the questio may seem paradoxical since it leads to the production of false proofs. We shall examine three (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Essays on Early Medieval Mathematics: The Latin Tradition. [REVIEW]Jackie Stedall - 2005 - British Journal for the History of Science 38 (3):358-359.
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Ideals and Realities in Ibn al-Haytham's Mathematical Oeuvre.Jan Hogendijk - 2004 - Early Science and Medicine 9 (1):37-43.
    Review essay: Les mathématiques infinitésimales du IXe au XIe siècle. Volume 4: Ibn al-Hatham, méthodes géométriques, transformations ponctuelles, et philosophie des mathématiques (London: Al-Furq¸n Islamic Heritage Foundation, 2002), pp. xiii+1064+vi ¤ 106.71 ISBN 1 87399 260 2.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. Nicholas of Cusa and Aristotle's philosophy of mathematics.M. Vesel - 2000 - Filozofski Vestnik 21 (1):45-71.
    One of the basic elements of Nicholas of Cusa's philosophy of mathematics is his theory of mathematical objects as “entities-of-reason” (entia rationis). He refers to these as being “abstracted from sensible things”. That is why it is possible to assume that Nicholas bases his theory of mathematics on Aristotle's philosophy of mathematics. Aristotle too describes mathematical objects as coming into being through abstraction (ex aphaireseos). The author analyses Cusa's understanding of abstraction in De docta ignorantia and De mente and tries (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. The Establishment of the Mathematical Bookshelf of the Medieval Hebrew Scholar: Translations and Translators.Tony LÉvy - 1997 - Science in Context 10 (3):431-451.
    The ArgumentThe major part of the mathematical “classics” in Hebrew were translated from Arabic between the second third of the thirteenth century and the first third of the fourteenth century, within the northern littoral of the western Mediterranean. This movement occurred after the original works by Abraham bar Hiyya and Abraham ibn Ezra became available to a wide readership. The translations were intended for a restricted audience — the scholarly readership involved in and dealing with the theoretical sciences. In some (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18. Thomists and Thomas Aquinas on the Foundation of Mathematics.Armand Maurer - 1993 - Review of Metaphysics 47 (1):43 - 61.
    SOME MODERN THOMISTS claiming to follow the lead of Thomas Aquinas, hold that the objects of the types of mathematics known in the thirteenth century, such as the arithmetic of whole numbers and Euclidean geometry, are real entities. In scholastic terms they are not beings of reason but real beings. In his once-popular scholastic manual, Elementa Philosophiae Aristotelico-Thomisticae, Joseph Gredt maintains that, according to Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas, the object of mathematics is real quantity, either discrete quantity in arithmetic or (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19. Review of M. Clagett: Achimedes in the Middle Ages: Quasi-Archimedean Geometry in the Thirteenth Century. [REVIEW]Jens Høyrup - 1989 - Annals of Science 46.
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Technology and Instruments Stephen K. Victor Practical geometry in the high middle ages. Artis cuiuslibet consummatio, and the Pratike de geometrie. Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society, 1979. Pp. xii + 638. [REVIEW]Joann Morse - 1983 - British Journal for the History of Science 16 (2):211-212.
  21. Studies in Medieval Physics and MathematicsMarshall Clagett.Edith Sylla - 1981 - Isis 72 (3):512-513.
  22. Aristotle and Aquinas on the Freedom of the Mathematician.Thomas C. Anderson - 1972 - The Thomist 36 (2):231.
  23. A Neglected Thomistic Text on the Foundation of Mathematics.Armand Maurer - 1959 - Mediaeval Studies 21 (1):185-192.
    After a survey of disagreements among Thomists on the nature of mathematical abstraction, the author cites Aquinas's text Scriptum super libros Sententiarum, I, d. 2, a.3 (a late text inserted in an older work). It assimilates the objects of mathematics to those of logic, thus admitting a remote foundation in reality but not the direct one of the concepts of the physical sciences.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. The Medieval Latin Translations from the Arabic of the Elements of Euclid, with Special Emphasis on the Versions of Adelard of Bath.Marshall Clagett - 1953 - Isis 44:16-42.
  25. An Anglo-Norman Algorism of the Fourteenth Century.Louis C. Karpinski & Charles N. Staubach - 1935 - Isis 23 (1):121-152.