Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The d-Logic of the Rational Numbers: A Fruitful Construction.Joel Lucero-Bryan - 2011 - Studia Logica 97 (2):265-295.
    We present a geometric construction that yields completeness results for modal logics including K4, KD4, GL and GL n with respect to certain subspaces of the rational numbers. These completeness results are extended to the bimodal case with the universal modality.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Taming the ‘Elsewhere’: On Expressivity of Topological Languages.David Fernández-Duque - 2024 - Review of Symbolic Logic 17 (1):144-153.
    In topological modal logic, it is well known that the Cantor derivative is more expressive than the topological closure, and the ‘elsewhere’, or ‘difference’, operator is more expressive than the ‘somewhere’ operator. In 2014, Kudinov and Shehtman asked whether the combination of closure and elsewhere becomes strictly more expressive when adding the Cantor derivative. In this paper we give an affirmative answer: in fact, the Cantor derivative alone can define properties of topological spaces not expressible with closure and elsewhere. To (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Foreword.Daniele Mundici - 1998 - Studia Logica 61 (1):1-1.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Finite Model Property in Weakly Transitive Tense Logics.Minghui Ma & Qian Chen - 2023 - Studia Logica 111 (2):217-250.
    The finite model property (FMP) in weakly transitive tense logics is explored. Let \(\mathbb {S}=[\textsf{wK}_t\textsf{4}, \textsf{K}_t\textsf{4}]\) be the interval of tense logics between \(\textsf{wK}_t\textsf{4}\) and \(\textsf{K}_t\textsf{4}\). We introduce the modal formula \(\textrm{t}_0^n\) for each \(n\ge 1\). Within the class of all weakly transitive frames, \(\textrm{t}_0^n\) defines the class of all frames in which every cluster has at most _n_ irreflexive points. For each \(n\ge 1\), we define the interval \(\mathbb {S}_n=[\textsf{wK}_t\textsf{4T}_0^{n+1}, \textsf{wK}_t\textsf{4T}_0^{n}]\) which is a subset of \(\mathbb {S}\). There are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The introduction of topology into analytic philosophy: two movements and a coda.Samuel C. Fletcher & Nathan Lackey - 2022 - Synthese 200 (3):1-34.
    Both early analytic philosophy and the branch of mathematics now known as topology were gestated and born in the early part of the 20th century. It is not well recognized that there was early interaction between the communities practicing and developing these fields. We trace the history of how topological ideas entered into analytic philosophy through two migrations, an earlier one conceiving of topology geometrically and a later one conceiving of topology algebraically. This allows us to reassess the influence and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • More on d-Logics of Subspaces of the Rational Numbers.Guram Bezhanishvili & Joel Lucero-Bryan - 2012 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 53 (3):319-345.
    We prove that each countable rooted K4 -frame is a d-morphic image of a subspace of the space $\mathbb{Q}$ of rational numbers. From this we derive that each modal logic over K4 axiomatizable by variable-free formulas is the d-logic of a subspace of $\mathbb{Q}$ . It follows that subspaces of $\mathbb{Q}$ give rise to continuum many d-logics over K4 , continuum many of which are neither finitely axiomatizable nor decidable. In addition, we exhibit several families of modal logics finitely axiomatizable (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Foreword.Lev Beklemishev, Guram Bezhanishvili, Daniele Mundici & Yde Venema - 2012 - Studia Logica 100 (1-2):1-7.