Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Social action-functions.Raimo Tuomela - 1984 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 14 (2):133-147.
  • Mapping complexity/Human knowledge as a complex adaptive system.John Thomas & Anna Zaytseva - 2016 - Complexity 21 (S2):207-234.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Historical laws in modern biology.Paul Thompson - 1983 - Acta Biotheoretica 32 (3):167-177.
    Several important analyses of the structure of evolutionary explanation have explicitly or implicitly required that historical laws be among the explanans statements. The required historical laws take the form of a generalization which relates some property or event to a developmental sequence of properties or events. The thesis of this paper is that historical laws of this kind are precluded by modern biological theory and, hence, analysis of evolutionary explanation within modern biology that require such laws are defective.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Conceptual and Logical Aspects of the ‘New’ Evolutionary Epistemology.Paul Thompson - 1988 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (sup1):235-253.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • » The Nature of Natural Laws «.Chris Swoyer - 1982 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (3):1982.
    That laws of nature play a vital role in explanation, prediction, and inductive inference is far clearer than the nature of the laws themselves. My hope here is to shed some light on the nature of natural laws by developing and defending the view that they involve genuine relations between properties. Such a position is suggested by Plato, and more recent versions have been sketched by several writers.~ But I am not happy with any of these accounts, not so much (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  • An objectivist argument for thirdism.The Oscar Seminar - 2008 - Analysis 68 (2):149–155.
  • An objectivist argument for thirdism.Oscar Seminar - 2008 - Analysis 68 (2):149-155.
  • Monsters Among Us.Timothy Schroeder - 2001 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 31 (sup1):167-184.
    There are monsters that scare children and monsters that scare grownups, and then there are monsters that scare philosophers of mind. This paper is concerned with this third sort of monster, whose primary representative is the zombie—a living being, physically just like a person but lacking consciousness. Though zombies act like normal people and appear to have normal brains, everything is blank inside. Unfortunately, the term ‘zombie’ covers a narrower class of deficits than is convenient, failing to cover apparently normal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Woodger on genetics a critical evaluation.Michael Ruse - 1975 - Acta Biotheoretica 24 (1-2):1-13.
    A critical analysis of Woodger's work on formal logic in biology, especially genetics, reveals that the claim for the value of such methods in genetics is misplaced.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The nature of scientific models : Formal V material analogy.Michael Ruse - 1973 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 3 (1):63-80.
  • A Theory of Non-universal Laws.Alexander Reutlinger - 2011 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 25 (2):97 - 117.
    Laws in the special sciences are usually regarded to be non-universal. A theory of laws in the special sciences faces two challenges. (I) According to Lange's dilemma, laws in the special sciences are either false or trivially true. (II) They have to meet the ?requirement of relevance?, which is a way to require the non-accidentality of special science laws. I argue that both challenges can be met if one distinguishes four dimensions of (non-) universality. The upshot is that I argue (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Humean problem of induction and Carroll’s Paradox.Manuel Pérez Otero - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 141 (3):357-376.
    Hume argued that inductive inferences do not have rational justification. My aim is to reject Hume's argument. The discussion is partly motivated by an analogy with Carroll's Paradox, which concerns deductive inferences. A first radically externalist reply to Hume is that justified inductive inferences do not require the subject to know that nature is uniform, though the uniformity of nature is necessary condition for having the justification. But then the subject does not have reasons for believing what she believes. I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Sociology as a science.David V. McQueen - 1981 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (2):263-284.
    Presented here is an overview from the standpoints of sociology, history of science, philosophy of science and “pure science” of the lingering question of whether sociology is a form of scientific pursuit. The conclusion is drawn that sociology barely meets any of the rigid criteria traditionally associated with the natural sciences. Sociology is viewed as having a position of theory and argument which is labeled “inconoclastic scepticism.”.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evers & Walker and forms of knowledge.Jim Mackenzie - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 19 (2):199–209.
    Jim Mackenzie; Evers & Walker and Forms of Knowledge, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 19, Issue 2, 30 May 2006, Pages 199–209, https://doi.org/10.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Are there molar psychological laws?Richard F. Kitchener - 1976 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 6 (2):143-154.
  • Methode oder Dogma?Andreas Kamlah - 1981 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (1):138-162.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Methode oder dogma?Andreas Kamlah - 1981 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (1):138-162.
    Summary Some leading ideas of the constructivist protophysics are discussed on the basis of P. Janich's Protophysik der Zeit. After having reviewed the contents of the second edition Janich's claim that analytical philosophy of science is purely affirmative and not critical towards science in its historical appearence is refuted. In the next section the principles of constructivist methodology of physics are criticised, and the claim is refuted that prescriptions for measurement cannot without circularity be shown to be invalid by experimental (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rezension: Melcher Imke, Franz Alexander und die moderne Psychotherapie.Andrea Huppke - 2016 - Psyche 70 (11):1099-1101.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rezension: Heimann Paula, Gegenübertragung und andere Schriften zur Psychoanalyse. Vorträge und Aufsätze aus den Jahren 1942–1980.Maren Holmes - 2016 - Psyche 70 (11):1096-1098.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Defending Scientific Realism Without Relying on Inference to the Best Explanation.Michel Ghins - 2017 - Axiomathes 27 (6):635-651.
    Explanationist strategies for defending epistemological scientific realism make heavy use of a particular version of inference to the best explanation known as the no-miracle argument. I consider ESR to be a genuinely philosophical—non-naturalistic—thesis which contends that there are strong arguments to believe in some non-observational claims made by scientific theories that are partially observationally correct. In this paper, I examine the grounds of the strength of these arguments from what I call a contemplative perspective which focuses on the end products, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Embedding Quantum Mechanics into a Broader Noncontextual Theory.Claudio Garola & Marco Persano - 2014 - Foundations of Science 19 (3):217-239.
    Scholars concerned with the foundations of quantum mechanics (QM) usually think that contextuality (hence nonobjectivity of physical properties, which implies numerous problems and paradoxes) is an unavoidable feature of QM which directly follows from the mathematical apparatus of QM. Based on some previous papers on this issue, we criticize this view and supply a new informal presentation of the extended semantic realism (ESR) model which embodies the formalism of QM into a broader mathematical formalism and reinterprets quantum probabilities as conditional (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Epistemic Circularity: Malignant and Benign.Michael Bergmann - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (3):709-727.
    * Editor’s Note: This paper won the Young Epistemologist Prize for the Rutgers Epistemology conference held in 2003.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Bions Erbe.Dominic Angeloch - 2016 - Psyche 70 (11):1089-1095.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Foreign policy as a goal directed activity.Paul A. Anderson - 1984 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 14 (2):159-181.
  • The Meaning of 'Theory'.Gabriel Abend - 2008 - Sociological Theory 26 (2):173-199.
    'Theory' is one of the most important words in the lexicon of contemporary sociology. Yet, their ubiquity notwithstanding, it is quite unclear what sociologists mean by the words 'theory,' 'theoretical,' and 'theorize.' I argue that confusions about the meaning of 'theory' have brought about undesirable consequences, including conceptual muddles and even downright miscommunication. In this paper I tackle two questions: what does 'theory' mean in the sociological language?; and what ought 'theory' to mean in the sociological language? I proceed in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The effect of talk and writing on learning science: An exploratory study.Léonard P. Rivard & Stanley B. Straw - 2000 - Science Education 84 (5):566-593.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations