Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. How Should I Be? A Defense of Platonic Rational Egoism.Jyl Gentzler - 2015 - European Journal of Philosophy 23 (1):39-67.
    There has been a long tradition of interpreting Plato as a rational egoist. Over the past few decades, however, some scholars have challenged this reading. While Rational Egoism appeals to many ordinary folk, in sophisticated philosophical circles it has fallen out of favor as a general and complete account of the nature of reasons for action. I argue that while the theory of practical rationality that is often equated with rational egoism—a view that I call ‘Simple-Minded Rational Egoism'—is neither plausible (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Last Temptation of the Philosopher-Rulers.Cathal Woods - 2009 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 3 (1).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • As Happy As Can Be: How Republic's Philosophers Fare Best by Ruling.Cathal Woods - 2010 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 4 (1).
  • Colloquium 3: The Unjust Philosophers of Republic VII.Roslyn Weiss - 2012 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 27 (1):65-103.
  • Internalization and the Philosophers’ Best Interest in Plato’s Republic.Jada Twedt Strabbing - 2018 - Apeiron 51 (2):147-170.
    I argue that it is in the philosophers’ best interest to rule Kallipolis because that life is the best available to them. Although the life of pure contemplation of the Forms would make them happiest, I make the case that, on Plato’s view, this life is not an option for them because of the essential psychological connections that he posits between the individual and the city. To make this argument, I first draw on Plato’s city/soul analogy to explore why it (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Colloquium 6: Goat-Stags, Philosopher-Kings, and Eudaimonism in the Republic.C. D. C. Reeve - 2007 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 22 (1):185-219.
  • Political Reluctance: On the Noble Lie in Plato's Republic.Olof Pettersson - 2014 - E-Logos 21 (1):1-31.
    As is well known, the rule of the philosophers is what ultimately completes the political project in Plato's Republic. Only if the philosophers accept to rule, may the city see the light of day. Yet, as is equally well known, the philosophers are reluctant to rule. But ruling is what they are designed to do. Their entire education was constructed to prepare them for this task. And therefore, as Plato's repeatedly puts it, they will need to be compelled. How? As (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • « The Allegory Of The Cave: The Necessity Of The Philosopher’s Descent ».Georgia Mouroutsou - 2011 - Plato Journal 11.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Plato on the Rule of Reason.Fred D. Miller - 2005 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 43 (S1):50-83.
  • “Standing apart in the shelter of the city wall”: The contemplative ideal vs. the politically engaged philosopher in Plato's political theory.Catherine McKeen - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 48 (2):197-216.
    Natural philosophers seem to have good reasons to prefer that the kallipolis, the maximally just community of the Republic, is never realized. If such a community is realized, philosophers are under the obligation of a just demand that they govern. However, a life that contains governance as a significant part is not the happiest life a philosopher can live. The happiest life for a philosopher is one consisting entirely or largely in philosophical contemplation. I confront this puzzle by arguing that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Meddling in the work of another.Brennan McDavid - 2022 - Plato Journal 23:95-107.
    The second conjunct of the Republic’s account of justice—that justice is “not meddling in the work of another”—has been neglected in Plato literature. This paper argues that the conjunct does more work than merely reiterating the content of the first conjunct—that justice is “doing one’s own work.” I argue that Socrates develops the concept at work in this conjunct from its introduction with the Principle of Specialization in Book II to its final deployment in the finished conception of justice in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How Should I Be? A Defense of Platonic Rational Egoism.Jyl Gentzler - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (4):39-67.
    There has been a long tradition of interpreting Plato as a rational egoist. Over the past few decades, however, some scholars have challenged this reading. While Rational Egoism appeals to many ordinary folk, in sophisticated philosophical circles it has fallen out of favor as a general and complete account of the nature of reasons for action. I argue that while the theory of practical rationality that is often equated with rational egoism—a view that I call ‘Simple-Minded Rational Egoism'—is neither plausible (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Glaucon's Question Ignored: Republic 519a-521b.James Butler - 2018 - AKROPOLIS: Journal of Hellenic Studies 2:46-66.
    At Republic 519a-521b, Socrates claims that each guardian must return from his/her contemplation to run Kallipolis. Quite reasonably, Glaucon objects that they would be making the guardian's life worse than it could be. This is sometimes referred to as “the happy philosopher problem”. But rather than answering Glaucon, Socrates admonishes him that their focus is instead on the role of the class of guardians and the happiness of the whole city. It turns out this admonition is the last in a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Compulsion to Rule in Plato’s Republic.Christopher Buckels - 2013 - Apeiron 46 (1):63-84.
    Three problems threaten any account of philosophical rule in the Republic. First, Socrates is supposed to show that acting justly is always beneficial, but instead he extols the benefits of having a just soul. He leaves little reason to believe practical justice and psychic justice are connected and thus to believe that philosophers will act justly. In response to this problem, I show that just acts produce just souls. Since philosophers want to have just souls, they will act justly. Second, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Contemplative withdrawal in the Hellenistic age.Eric Brown - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 137 (1):79-89.
    I reject the traditional picture of philosophical withdrawal in the Hellenistic Age by showing how both Epicureans and Stoics oppose, in different ways, the Platonic and Aristotelian assumption that contemplative activity is the greatest good for a human being. Chrysippus the Stoic agrees with Plato and Aristotle that the greatest good for a human being is virtuous activity, but he denies that contemplation exercises virtue. Epicurus more thoroughly rejects the assumption that the greatest good for a human being is virtuous (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Eros and Necessity in the Ascent from the Cave.Rachel Barney - 2008 - Ancient Philosophy 28 (2):357-72.
    A generally ignored feature of Plato’s celebrated image of the cave in Republic VII is that the ascent from the cave is, in its initial stages, said to be brought about by force. What kind of ‘force’ is this, and why is it necessary? This paper considers three possible interpretations, and argues that each may have a role to play.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Beginning the 'Longer Way'.Mitchell Miller - 2007 - In G. R. F. Ferrari (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato's Republic. Cambridge University Press. pp. 310--344.
    At 435c-d and 504b ff., Socrates indicates that there is a "longer and fuller way" that one must take in order to get "the best possible view" of the soul and its virtues. But Plato does not have him take this "longer way." Instead Socrates restricts himself to an indirect indication of its goals by his images of sun, line, and cave and to a programmatic outline of its first phase, the five mathematical studies. Doesn't this pointed restraint function as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A Multiform Desire.Olof Pettersson - 2013 - Dissertation, Uppsala University
    This dissertation is a study of appetite in Plato’s Timaeus, Republic and Phaedrus. In recent research is it often suggested that Plato considers appetite (i) to pertain to the essential needs of the body, (ii) to relate to a distinct set of objects, e.g. food or drink, and (iii) to cause behaviour aiming at sensory pleasure. Exploring how the notion of appetite, directly and indirectly, connects with Plato’s other purposes in these dialogues, this dissertation sets out to evaluate these ideas. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations