Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Bioethics Without Theory?Søren Holm - 2024 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 33 (2):159-166.
    The question that this paper tries to answer is Q: “Can good academic bioethics be done without commitment to moral theory?” It is argued that the answer to Q is an unequivocal “Yes” for most of what we could call “critical bioethics,” that is, the kind of bioethics work that primarily criticizes positions or arguments already in the literature or put forward by policymakers. The answer is also “Yes” for much of empirical bioethics. The second part of the paper then (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Living ethics: a stance and its implications in health ethics.Eric Racine, Sophie Ji, Valérie Badro, Aline Bogossian, Claude Julie Bourque, Marie-Ève Bouthillier, Vanessa Chenel, Clara Dallaire, Hubert Doucet, Caroline Favron-Godbout, Marie-Chantal Fortin, Isabelle Ganache, Anne-Sophie Guernon, Marjorie Montreuil, Catherine Olivier, Ariane Quintal, Abdou Simon Senghor, Michèle Stanton-Jean, Joé T. Martineau, Andréanne Talbot & Nathalie Tremblay - forthcoming - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy:1-18.
    Moral or ethical questions are vital because they affect our daily lives: what is the best choice we can make, the best action to take in a given situation, and ultimately, the best way to live our lives? Health ethics has contributed to moving ethics toward a more experience-based and user-oriented theoretical and methodological stance but remains in our practice an incomplete lever for human development and flourishing. This context led us to envision and develop the stance of a “living (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Feminist and Medical Ethics: Two Different Approaches to Contextual Ethics.Susan Sherwin - 1989 - Hypatia 4 (2):57-72.
    Feminist ethics and medical ethics are critical of contemporary moral theory in several similar respects. There is a shared sense of frustration with the level of abstraction and generality that characterizes traditional philosophic work in ethics and a common commitment to including contextual details and allowing room for the personal aspects of relationships in ethical analysis. This paper explores the ways in which context is appealed to in feminist and medical ethics, the sort of details that should be included in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The Role of Professional Knowledge in Case-Based Reasoning in Practical Ethics.Rosa Lynn Pinkus, Claire Gloeckner & Angela Fortunato - 2015 - Science and Engineering Ethics 21 (3):767-787.
    The use of case-based reasoning in teaching professional ethics has come of age. The fields of medicine, engineering, and business all have incorporated ethics case studies into leading textbooks and journal articles, as well as undergraduate and graduate professional ethics courses. The most recent guidelines from the National Institutes of Health recognize case studies and face-to-face discussion as best practices to be included in training programs for the Responsible Conduct of Research. While there is a general consensus that case studies (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Teaching clinical ethics as a professional skill: bridging the gap between knowledge about ethics and its use in clinical practice.C. Myser, I. H. Kerridge & K. R. Mitchell - 1995 - Journal of Medical Ethics 21 (2):97-103.
    Ethical reasoning and decision-making may be thought of as 'professional skills', and in this sense are as relevant to efficient clinical practice as the biomedical and clinical sciences are to the diagnosis of a patient's problem. Despite this, however, undergraduate medical programmes in ethics tend to focus on the teaching of bioethical theories, concepts and/or prominent ethical issues such as IVF and euthanasia, rather than the use of such ethics knowledge (theories, principles, concepts, rules) to clinical practice. Not surprisingly, many (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Teaching clinical ethics as a professional skill: bridging the gap between knowledge about ethics and its use in clinical practice.Catherine Myser, Ian H. Kerridge & Kenneth R. Mitchell - 1995 - Journal of Medical Ethics 21 (2):97-103.
    Ethical reasoning and decision-making may be thought of as 9professional skills9, and in this sense are as relevant to efficient clinical practice as the biomedical and clinical sciences are to the diagnosis of a patient9s problem. Despite this, however, undergraduate medical programmes in ethics tend to focus on the teaching of bioethical theories, concepts and/or prominent ethical issues such as IVF and euthanasia, rather than the use of such ethics knowledge (theories, principles, concepts, rules) to clinical practice. Not surprisingly, many (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Applied Philosophy and Philosophers' Practice.Michael Mulkay - 1981 - Science, Technology and Human Values 6 (1):7-15.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is ethics consultation an elegant distraction?Jonathan D. Moreno - 1996 - HEC Forum 8 (1):12-21.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Truth and consequences.Polly Mitchell, Alan Cribb & Vikki Entwistle - 2023 - Metaphilosophy 54 (4):523-538.
    In his 1987 paper “Truth or Consequences,” Dan Brock describes a deep conflict between the goals and virtues of philosophical scholarship and public policymaking: whereas the former is concerned with the search for truth, the latter must primarily be concerned with promoting good consequences. When philosophers are engaged in policymaking, he argues, they must shift their primary goal from truth to consequences—but this has both moral and methodological costs. Brock’s argument exemplifies a pessimistic, but not uncommon, view of the possible (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The canadian research strategy for applied ethics: A new opportunity for research in business and professional ethics. [REVIEW]Michael McDonald - 1992 - Journal of Business Ethics 11 (8):569 - 583.
    InTowards a Canadian Research Strategy ForApplied Ethics, I put forward proposals to advance Canadian research in applied ethics. I focus on the assessment made of Canadian teaching, consulting, and research in business and professional ethics and then on the strategy proposed for advancing work in these areas. I argue for research which is [1] oriented to the ethical needs of those in business and the professions, [2] interdisciplinary, and [3] involves the creation of national and international networks. I then offer (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Four Roles of Ethical Theory in Clinical Ethics Consultation.Morten Magelssen, Reidar Pedersen & Reidun Førde - 2016 - American Journal of Bioethics 16 (9):26-33.
    When clinical ethics committee members discuss a complex ethical dilemma, what use do they have for normative ethical theories? Members without training in ethical theory may still contribute to a pointed and nuanced analysis. Nonetheless, the knowledge and use of ethical theories can play four important roles: aiding in the initial awareness and identification of the moral challenges, assisting in the analysis and argumentation, contributing to a sound process and dialogue, and inspiring an attitude of reflexivity. These four roles of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Theory and Practice of Applied Ethics.Barry Hoffmaster - 1991 - Dialogue 30 (3):213-.
    Applied ethics is at a watershed. In all its domains a gulf between the theory of applied ethics and the practice of applied ethics is now being recognized. In medical ethics, for example, it has been observed that “practicing clinicians often feel let down by bioethics.” The disappointment of clinicians is attributed in part to their own unrealistic expectations but is also said to be a function ofthe extent to which bioethics as a discipline doesn't seem to be in possession (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Ethical Culture.Bert Heinrichs - 2018 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 35 (4):371-388.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophers in research ethics committees—what do they think they’re doing? An empirical-ethical analysis.Charlotte Gauckler - 2021 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 24 (4):609-619.
    Research ethics committees in Germany usually don’t have philosophers as members and if so, only contingently, not provided for by statute. This is interesting from a philosophical perspective, assuming that ethics is a discipline of philosophy. It prompts the question what role philosophers play in those committees they can be found in. Eight qualitative semi-structured interviews were conducted to explore the self-perception of philosophers regarding their contribution to research ethics committees. The results show that the participants generally don’t view themselves (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pure and Impure Philosophy in Kant's Metaphilosophy.Ernesto V. Garcia - 2023 - Kantian Journal 42 (3):17-48.
    Kant’s metaphilosophy has three main parts: (1) an essentialist project (“What is philosophy?”); (2) a methodological project (“How do we do philosophy?”); and (3) a taxonomic project (“What are the different parts of philosophy, and how are they related?”). This paper focuses on the third project. In particular, it explores one of the most intriguing yet puzzling aspects of Kant’s philosophy, viz. the relationship between what Kant calls ‘pure’ philosophy vs. ‘applied’, ‘empirical’ or what we can broadly refer to as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Rejection of “Applied Ethics”: Philosophy’s Real Contributions to Bioethics Found Elsewhere.Ryan Marshall Felder & David Magnus - 2022 - American Journal of Bioethics 22 (12):1-2.
    This month’s Target Article by Blumenthal-Barby et al. (2022) offers a defense of the importance of philosophy to bioethics. The authors cite the crucial role of philosophers in the development and...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Research Ethics Committees: The Business of Society and Medicine.Nathan Emmerich - 2009 - Research Ethics 5 (4):154-156.
    Whilst Colin Parker and I are in broad disagreement we would nevertheless agree that RECs have both political and ethical functions, albeit to differing degrees, and that a proper account of ethical expertise needs to be given. The uses RECs make of ethical experts and expertise and the way in which this might be recognised remains, from my perspective, open for debate. My only conclusion is that it should be recognised.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Ethics Committee: The Expert Member, the Lay Member and the Absentee Ethicist.Nathan Emmerich - 2009 - Research Ethics 5 (1):9-13.
    This paper considers the roles and definitions of expert and lay members of ethics committees, focussing on those given by the National Research Ethics Service which is mandated to review all research conducted in National Health Service settings in the United Kingdom. It questions the absence of a specified position for the ‘professional ethicist’ and suggests that such individuals will often be lay members of ethics committees, their participation being a reflection of their academic interest and expertise. The absence of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • For an Ethnomethodology of Healthcare Ethics.Nathan Emmerich - 2013 - Health Care Analysis 21 (4):372-389.
    This paper considers the utility of Ethnomethodology (EM) for the study of healthcare ethics as part of the empirical turn in Bioethics. I give a brief introduction to EM through its respecification of sociology, the specific view on the social world this generates and EM's posture of ‘indifference’. I then take a number of EM concepts and articulate each in the context of an EM study of healthcare ethics in professional practice. Having given an overview of the relationship and perspective (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Anti-theory in action? Planning for pandemics, triage and ICU or: how not to bite a bullet. [REVIEW]Nathan Emmerich - 2011 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 14 (1):91-100.
    Anti-theory is a multi-faceted critique of moral theory which, it appears, is undergoing something of reassessment. In a recent paper Hämäläinen discusses the relevance of an anti-theoretical perspective for the activity of applied ethics. This paper explores her view of anti-theory. In particular I examine its relevance for understanding the formal guidance on pandemic flu planning issues by the Department of Health in the UK and some subsequent discussions around triage and reverse triage decisions which may be considered by both (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Significant Limit on Applied History, Philosophy, and Sociology of Science and Technology.Paul T. Durbin - 1981 - Science, Technology and Human Values 6 (1):18-19.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defence of clinical bioethics.J. D. Arras & T. H. Murray - 1982 - Journal of Medical Ethics 8 (3):122-127.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What kind of doing is clinical ethics?George J. Agich - 2004 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 26 (1):7-24.
    This paper discusses the importance of Richard M. Zaners work on clinical ethics for answering the question: what kind of doing is ethics consultation? The paper argues first, that four common approaches to clinical ethics – applied ethics, casuistry, principlism, and conflict resolution – cannot adequately address the nature of the activity that makes up clinical ethics; second, that understanding the practical character of clinical ethics is critically important for the field; and third, that the practice of clinical ethics is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Theory and bioethics.John Arras - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Ineffable and the Incalculable: G. E. Moore on Ethical Expertise.Ben Eggleston - 2005 - In Lisa Rasmussen (ed.), Ethics Expertise: History, Contemporary Perspectives, and Applications. Springer. pp. 89–102.
    According to G. E. Moore, moral expertise requires abilities of several kinds: the ability to factor judgments of right and wrong into (a) judgments of good and bad and (b) judgments of cause and effect, (2) the ability to use intuition to make the requisite judgments of good and bad, and (3) the ability to use empirical investigation to make the requisite judgments of cause and effect. Moore’s conception of moral expertise is thus extremely demanding, but he supplements it with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation