Switch to: References

Citations of:

Elements of Intuitionism

Oxford University Press. Edited by Roberto Minio (1977)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Compactness notions for an apartness space.Douglas S. Bridges - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (5-6):517-534.
    Two new notions of compactness, each classically equivalent to the standard classical one of sequential compactness, for apartness spaces are examined within Bishop-style constructive mathematics.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Constructive Hilbert Program and the Limits of Martin-Löf Type Theory.Michael Rathjen - 2005 - Synthese 147 (1):81-120.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Never say never.Timothy Williamson - 1994 - Topoi 13 (2):135-145.
    I. An argument is presented for the conclusion that the hypothesis that no one will ever decide a given proposition is intuitionistically inconsistent. II. A distinction between sentences and statements blocks a similar argument for the stronger conclusion that the hypothesis that I have not yet decided a given proposition is intuitionistically inconsistent, but does not block the original argument. III. A distinction between empirical and mathematical negation might block the original argument, and empirical negation might be modelled on Nelson''s (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Knowledge of proofs.Peter Pagin - 1994 - Topoi 13 (2):93-100.
    If proofs are nothing more than truth makers, then there is no force in the standard argument against classical logic (there is no guarantee that there is either a proof forA or a proof fornot A). The standard intuitionistic conception of a mathematical proof is stronger: there are epistemic constraints on proofs. But the idea that proofs must be recognizable as such by us, with our actual capacities, is incompatible with the standard intuitionistic explanations of the meanings of the logical (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On Naturalizing the Epistemology of Mathematics.Jeffrey W. Roland - 2009 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (1):63-97.
    In this paper, I consider an argument for the claim that any satisfactory epistemology of mathematics will violate core tenets of naturalism, i.e. that mathematics cannot be naturalized. I find little reason for optimism that the argument can be effectively answered.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Holism and meaning.James O. Young - 1992 - Erkenntnis 37 (3):309 - 325.
  • Bivalence and subjunctive conditionals.Timothy Williamson - 1988 - Synthese 75 (3):405 - 421.
    Writers such as Stalnaker and Dummett have argued that specific features of subjunctive conditional statements undermine the principle of bivalence. This, paper is concerned with rebutting such claims. 1. It is shown how subjective conditionals pose a prima facie threat to bivalence, and how this threat can be dissolved by a distinction between the results of negating a subjective conditional and of negating its consequent. To make this distinction is to side with Lewis against Stalnaker in a dispute about possible (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Nāgārjuna’s Catuṣkoṭi.Jan Westerhoff - 2006 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 34 (4):367-395.
    The catuṣkoṭi or tetralemma is an argumentative figure familiar to any reader of Buddhist philosophical literature. Roughly speaking it consists of the enumeration of four alternatives: that some propositions holds, that it fails to hold, that it both holds and fails to hold, that it neither holds nor fails to hold. The tetralemma also constitutes one of the more puzzling features of Buddhist philosophy as the use to which it is put in arguments is not immediately obvious and certainly not (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Intuitionistic mathematics and wittgenstein.Wenceslao J. Gonzalez - 1991 - History and Philosophy of Logic 12 (2):167-183.
    The relation between Wittgenstein's philosophy of mathematics and mathematical Intuitionism has raised a considerable debate. My attempt is to analyse if there is a commitment in Wittgenstein to themes characteristic of the intuitionist movement in Mathematics and if that commitment is one important strain that runs through his Remarks on the foundations of mathematics. The intuitionistic themes to analyse in his philosophy of mathematics are: firstly, his attacks on the unrestricted use of the Law of Excluded Middle; secondly, his distrust (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A propositional logic with explicit fixed points.Albert Visser - 1981 - Studia Logica 40 (2):155 - 175.
    This paper studies a propositional logic which is obtained by interpreting implication as formal provability. It is also the logic of finite irreflexive Kripke Models.A Kripke Model completeness theorem is given and several completeness theorems for interpretations into Provability Logic and Peano Arithmetic.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Anti-Realist Truth and Truth-Recognition.Gabriele Usberti - 2012 - Topoi 31 (1):37-45.
    I will be concerned with the following question: are there compelling arguments for postulating a distinction between the truth of a statement and the recognition of its truth, when truth is conceived along the lines of a suitable generalization of the intuitionistic idea that it should be characterized as the existence of a proof? I will argue that the distinction is not necessary within the conceptual framework of intuitionism by replying to two arguments to the contrary, one based on the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Towards a Semantics Based on the Notion of Justification.Gabriele Usberti - 2006 - Synthese 148 (3):675-699.
    Suppose we want to take seriously the neoverificationist idea that an intuitionistic theory of meaning can be generalized in such a way as to be applicable not only to mathematical but also to empirical sentences. The paper explores some consequences of this attitude and takes some steps towards the realization of this program. The general idea is to develop a meaning theory, and consequently a formal semantics, based on the idea that knowing the meaning of a sentence is tantamount to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Parts, classes and Parts of Classes : an anti-realist reading of Lewisian mereology.Neil Tennant - 2013 - Synthese 190 (4):709-742.
    This study is in two parts. In the first part, various important principles of classical extensional mereology are derived on the basis of a nice axiomatization involving ‘part of’ and fusion. All results are proved here with full Fregean rigor. They are chosen because they are needed for the second part. In the second part, this natural-deduction framework is used in order to regiment David Lewis’s justification of his Division Thesis, which features prominently in his combination of mereology with class (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Truth and proof: The platonism of mathematics.W. W. Tait - 1986 - Synthese 69 (3):341 - 370.
  • Validity and quantification in intuitionism.H. C. M. Swart & C. J. Posy - 1981 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (1):117 - 126.
    We distinguish three different readings of the intuitionistic notions of validity, soundness, and completeness with respect to the quantification occurring in the notion of validity, and we establish certain relations between the different readings. For each of the meta-logicalnotions considered we suggest that the "most natural" reading (which is not the same for all cases) is precisely the one which is required by the recent intuitionistic completeness theorems for IPC.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Semantic Values for Natural Deduction Derivations.Göran Sundholm - 2006 - Synthese 148 (3):623-638.
    Drawing upon Martin-Löf’s semantic framework for his constructive type theory, semantic values are assigned also to natural-deduction derivations, while observing the crucial distinction between consequence among propositions and inference among judgements. Derivations in Gentzen’s format with derivable formulae dependent upon open assumptions, stand, it is suggested, for proof-objects, whereas derivations in Gentzen’s sequential format are proof-acts.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The significance of a non-reductionist ontology for the discipline of mathematics: A historical and systematic analysis. [REVIEW]D. F. M. Strauss - 2010 - Axiomathes 20 (1):19-52.
    A Christian approach to scholarship, directed by the central biblical motive of creation, fall and redemption and guided by the theoretical idea that God subjected all of creation to His Law-Word, delimiting and determining the cohering diversity we experience within reality, in principle safe-guards those in the grip of this ultimate commitment and theoretical orientation from absolutizing or deifying anything within creation. In this article my over-all approach is focused on the one-sided legacy of mathematics, starting with Pythagorean arithmeticism (“everything (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Plantinga and anti-realism.Shelley I. Stillwfii - 1989 - Synthese 78 (1):87-115.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What Harmony Could and Could Not Be.Florian Steinberger - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (4):617 - 639.
    The notion of harmony has played a pivotal role in a number of debates in the philosophy of logic. Yet there is little agreement as to how the requirement of harmony should be spelled out in detail or even what purpose it is to serve. Most, if not all, conceptions of harmony can already be found in Michael Dummett's seminal discussion of the matter in The Logical Basis of Metaphysics. Hence, if we wish to gain a better understanding of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The completeness of intuitionistic logic with respect to a validity concept based on an inversion principle.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 1983 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 12 (3):359 - 377.
  • Expression for expressivists.Mark Schroeder - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (1):86–116.
    Expressivism’s central idea is that normative sentences bear the same relation to non-cognitive attitudes that ordinary descriptive sentences bear to beliefs: the expression relation. Allan Gibbard teIls us that “that words express judgments will be accepted by almost everyone” - the distinctive contribution of expressivism, his claim goes, is only a view about what kind of judgments words express. But not every account of the expression relation is equally suitable for the expressivist’s purposes. In fact, what I argue in this (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • On A Neglected Path to Intuitionism.Ian Rumfitt - 2012 - Topoi 31 (1):101-109.
    According to Quine, in any disagreement over basic logical laws the contesting parties must mean different things by the connectives or quantifiers implicated in those laws; when a deviant logician ‘tries to deny the doctrine he only changes the subject’. The standard semantics for intuitionism offers some confirmation for this thesis, for it represents an intuitionist as attaching quite different senses to the connectives than does a classical logician. All the same, I think Quine was wrong, even about the dispute (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Intuitionism, Meaning Theory and Cognition.Richard Tieszen - 2000 - History and Philosophy of Logic 21 (3):179-194.
    Michael Dummett has interpreted and expounded upon intuitionism under the influence of Wittgensteinian views on language, meaning and cognition. I argue against the application of some of these views to intuitionism and point to shortcomings in Dummett's approach. The alternative I propose makes use of recent, post-Wittgensteinian views in the philosophy of mind, meaning and language. These views are associated with the claim that human cognition exhibits intentionality and with related ideas in philosophical psychology. Intuitionism holds that mathematical constructions are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Direct deductive computation on discourse representation structures.Uwe Reyle & Dov M. Gabbay - 1994 - Linguistics and Philosophy 17 (4):343 - 390.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Truth Values and Proof Theory.Greg Restall - 2009 - Studia Logica 92 (2):241-264.
    I present an account of truth values for classical logic, intuitionistic logic, and the modal logic S5, in which truth values are not a fundamental category from which the logic is defined, but rather, an idealisation of more fundamental logical features in the proof theory for each system. The result is not a new set of semantic structures, but a new understanding of how the existing semantic structures may be understood in terms of a more fundamental notion of logical consequence.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Constructive logic, truth and warranted assertability.Greg Restall - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 51 (205):474-483.
    Shapiro and Taschek have argued that simply using intuitionistic logic and its Heyting semantics, one can show that there are no gaps in warranted assertability. That is, given that a discourse is faithfully modeled using Heyting's semantics for the logical constants, then if a statement _S is not warrantedly assertable, its negation (superscript box) _S is. Tennant has argued for this conclusion on similar grounds. I show that these arguments fail, albeit in illuminating ways. An appeal to constructive logic does (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Finite Hilbert‐Style Axiomatization of the Implication‐Less Fragment of the Intuitionistic Propositional Calculus.Jordi Rebagliato & Ventura Verdú - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (1):61-68.
    In this paper we obtain a finite Hilbert-style axiomatization of the implicationless fragment of the intuitionistic propositional calculus. As a consequence we obtain finite axiomatizations of all structural closure operators on the algebra of {–}-formulas containing this fragment.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Supervaluational anti-realism and logic.Stig Alstrup Rasmussen - 1990 - Synthese 84 (1):97 - 138.
  • Intuitionistic truth.Wlodzimierz Rabinowicz - 1985 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 14 (2):191 - 228.
  • Truth as an Epistemic Notion.Dag Prawitz - 2012 - Topoi 31 (1):9-16.
    What is the appropriate notion of truth for sentences whose meanings are understood in epistemic terms such as proof or ground for an assertion? It seems that the truth of such sentences has to be identified with the existence of proofs or grounds, and the main issue is whether this existence is to be understood in a temporal sense as meaning that we have actually found a proof or a ground, or if it could be taken in an abstract, tenseless (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Judgement aggregation in non-classical logics.Daniele Porello - 2017 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 27 (1-2):106-139.
    This work contributes to the theory of judgement aggregation by discussing a number of significant non-classical logics. After adapting the standard framework of judgement aggregation to cope with non-classical logics, we discuss in particular results for the case of Intuitionistic Logic, the Lambek calculus, Linear Logic and Relevant Logics. The motivation for studying judgement aggregation in non-classical logics is that they offer a number of modelling choices to represent agents’ reasoning in aggregation problems. By studying judgement aggregation in logics that (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Giving Up on “the Rest of the Language".Adam C. Podlaskowski - 2015 - Acta Analytica 30 (3):293-304.
    In this essay, the tension that Benacerraf identifies for theories of mathematical truth is used as the vehicle for arguing against a particular desideratum for semantic theories. More specifically, I place in question the desideratum that a semantic theory, provided for some area of discourse, should run in parallel with the semantic theory holding for the rest of the language. The importance of this desideratum is also made clear by means of tracing out the subtle implications of its rejection.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Laplace's demon consults an oracle: The computational complexity of prediction.Itamar Pitowsky - 1996 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 27 (2):161-180.
  • Laplace's demon consults an oracle: The computational complexity of prediction.Itamar Pitowsky - 1996 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 27 (2):161-180.
  • Indices of truth and intensional operators.Philip Percival - 1990 - Theoria 56 (3):148-172.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sentential Connectives and Translation.Sascia Pavan - 2010 - Erkenntnis 73 (2):145 - 163.
    In the first exposition of the doctrine of indeterminacy of translation, Quine asserted that the individuation and translation of truth-functional sentential connectives like 'and', 'or', 'not' are not indeterminate. He changed his mind later on, conjecturing that some sentential connectives might be interpreted in different non-equivalent ways. This issue has not been debated much by Quine, or in the subsequent literature, it is, as it were, an unsolved problem, not well understood. For the sake of the argument, I will adopt (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Constructivity and the referential/attributive distinction.D. E. Over - 1985 - Linguistics and Philosophy 8 (4):415 - 429.
  • Non-monotonicity and Informal Reasoning: Comment on Ferguson (2003).Mike Oaksford & Ulrike Hahn - 2006 - Argumentation 20 (2):245-251.
    In this paper, it is argued that Ferguson’s (2003, Argumentation 17, 335–346) recent proposal to reconcile monotonic logic with defeasibility has three counterintuitive consequences. First, the conclusions that can be derived from his new rule of inference are vacuous, a point that as already made against default logics when there are conflicting defaults. Second, his proposal requires a procedural “hack” to the break the symmetry between the disjuncts of the tautological conclusions to which his proposal leads. Third, Ferguson’s proposal amounts (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Critique of Resnik’s Mathematical Realism.Timothy John Nulty - 2005 - Erkenntnis 62 (3):379 - 393.
    This paper attempts to motivate skepticism about the reality of mathematical objects. The aim of the paper is not to provide a general critique of mathematical realism, but to demonstrate the insufficiency of the arguments advanced by Michael Resnik. I argue that Resnik’s use of the concept of immanent truth is inconsistent with the treatment of mathematical objects as ontologically and epistemically continuous with the objects posited by the natural sciences. In addition, Resnik’s structuralist program, and his denial of relational (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Critique of Resnik’s Mathematical Realism.Timothy John Nulty - 2005 - Erkenntnis 62 (3):379-393.
    This paper attempts to motivate skepticism about the reality of mathematical objects. The aim of the paper is not to provide a general critique of mathematical realism, but to demonstrate the insufficiency of the arguments advanced by Michael Resnik. I argue that Resnik's use of the concept of immanent truth is inconsistent with the treatment of mathematical objects as ontologically and epistemically continuous with the objects posited by the natural sciences. In addition, Resnik's structuralist program, and his denial of relational (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Tableau Method for a Logical System Based on a Finite Poset.Abir Nour - 2002 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 12 (1):43-62.
    In order to modelize the reasoning of intelligent agents represented by a poset T, H. Rasiowa introduced logic systems called “Approximation Logics”. In these systems a set of constants constitutes a fundamental tool. In this paper, we consider logic systems called L'T without this kind of constants but limited to the case where T is a finite poset. We study the tableau method for this system and we prove its completeness for a class of formulas with respect to an algebraic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sémantique algébrique ďun système logique basé sur un ensemble ordonné fini.Abir Nour - 1999 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 45 (4):457-466.
    In order to modelize the reasoning of an intelligent agent represented by a poset T, H. Rasiowa introduced logic systems called “Approximation Logics”. In these systems a set of constants constitutes a fundamental tool. In this papers, we consider logic systems called L′T without this kind of constants but limited to the case where T is a finite poset. We prove a weak deduction theorem. We introduce also an algebraic semantics using Hey ting algebra with operators. To prove the completeness (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Brouwer's Incomplete Objects.Joop Niekus - 2010 - History and Philosophy of Logic 31 (1):31-46.
    Brouwer's papers after 1945 are characterized by a technique known as the method of the creating subject. It has been supposed that the method was radically new in his work, since Brouwer seems to introduce an idealized mathematician into his mathematical practice. A newly opened source, the unpublished text of a lecture of Brouwer from 1934, fully supports the conclusions of our analysis that: - There is no idealized mathematician involved in the method;- The method was not new at all;- (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The experiential foundations of mathematical knowledge.Nicolas D. Goodman - 1981 - History and Philosophy of Logic 2 (1-2):55-65.
    A view of the sources of mathematical knowledge is sketched which emphasizes the close connections between mathematical and empirical knowledge. A platonistic interpretation of mathematical discourse is adopted throughout. Two skeptical views are discussed and rejected. One of these, due to Maturana, is supposed to be based on biological considerations. The other, due to Dummett, is derived from a Wittgensteinian position in the philosophy of language. The paper ends with an elaboration of Gödel's analogy between the mathematician and the physicist.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Are Uniqueness and Deducibility of Identicals the Same?Alberto Naibo & Mattia Petrolo - 2014 - Theoria 81 (2):143-181.
    A comparison is given between two conditions used to define logical constants: Belnap's uniqueness and Hacking's deducibility of identicals. It is shown that, in spite of some surface similarities, there is a deep difference between them. On the one hand, deducibility of identicals turns out to be a weaker and less demanding condition than uniqueness. On the other hand, deducibility of identicals is shown to be more faithful to the inferentialist perspective, permitting definition of genuinely proof-theoretical concepts. This kind of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Manifestability and Epistemic Truth.Julien Murzi - 2012 - Topoi 31 (1):17-26.
    I argue that the standard anti-realist argument from manifestability to intuitionistic logic is either unsound or invalid. Strong interpretations of the manifestability of understanding are falsified by the existence of blindspots for knowledge. Weaker interpretations are either too weak, or gerrymandered and ad hoc. Either way, they present no threat to classical logic.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Dummett's intuitionism is not strict finitism.Samuel William Mitchell - 1992 - Synthese 90 (3):437 - 458.
    Michael Dummett's anti-realism is founded on the semantics of natural language which, he argues, can only be satisfactorily given in mathematics by intuitionism. It has been objected that an analog of Dummett's argument will collapse intuitionism into strict finitism. My purpose in this paper is to refute this objection, which I argue Dummett does not successfully do. I link the coherence of strict finitism to a view of confirmation — that our actual practical abilities cannot confirm we know what would (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Classical harmony: Rules of inference and the meaning of the logical constants.Peter Milne - 1994 - Synthese 100 (1):49 - 94.
    The thesis that, in a system of natural deduction, the meaning of a logical constant is given by some or all of its introduction and elimination rules has been developed recently in the work of Dummett, Prawitz, Tennant, and others, by the addition of harmony constraints. Introduction and elimination rules for a logical constant must be in harmony. By deploying harmony constraints, these authors have arrived at logics no stronger than intuitionist propositional logic. Classical logic, they maintain, cannot be justified (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Multisets and relevant implication I.Robert K. Meyer & Michael A. McRobbie - 1982 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (2):107 – 139.
  • Essay Review.M. Detlefsen - 1988 - History and Philosophy of Logic 9 (1):93-105.
    S. SHAPIRO (ed.), Intensional Mathematics (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 11 3). Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1985. v + 230 pp. $38.50/100Df.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark