Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The maladies of enlightenment science.Tim Wyatt - 2017 - Ethics in Science and Environmental Politics 17 (1):51-62.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Interaction-Dominant Causation in Mind and Brain, and Its Implication for Questions of Generalization and Replication.Sebastian Wallot & Damian G. Kelty-Stephen - 2018 - Minds and Machines 28 (2):353-374.
    The dominant assumption about the causal architecture of the mind is, that it is composed of a stable set of components that contribute independently to relevant observables that are employed to measure cognitive activity. This view has been called component-dominant dynamics. An alternative has been proposed, according to which the different components are not independent, but fundamentally interdependent, and are not stable basic properties of the mind, but rather an emergent feature of the mind given a particular task context. This (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Review of Kyle Stanford’s Exceeding our Grasp: Science, History and the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives. [REVIEW]Ioannis Votsis - 2007 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 21 (1):103 – 106.
    In recent years, two challenges stand out against scientific realism: the argument from the underdetermination of theories by evidence (UTE) and the pessimistic induction argument (PI). In his book, Kyle Stanford accepts the gravity of these challenges, but argues that the most serious and powerful challenge to scientific realism has been neglected. The problem of unconceived alternatives (PUA), as he calls it, is introduced in chapter one and refined in chapter two. In short, PUA holds that throughout history scientists have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Culture, Mass Communication and Social Agency.Andrew Tudor - 1995 - Theory, Culture and Society 12 (1):81-107.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The diversity of modes of discourse and the development of sociological knowledge.Nico Stehr & Anthony Simmons - 1979 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 10 (1):141-161.
    This paper presents an analysis of the structure of contemporary sociological knowledge in terms of a theory of scientific discourse. The concept of 'discourse' is introduced as a theoretical refinement of the concept of 'paradigm' and is applied to the classes of knowledge claims of the natural and social sciences. It is concluded that general modes of scientific discourse are definable in terms of their vertical differentiation from everyday discourse, while particular modes of sociological discourse are additionally definable in terms (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A case for the 'middle ground': exploring the tensions of postmodern thought in nursing.Kelli I. Stajduhar, Lynda Balneaves & Sally E. Thorne - 2001 - Nursing Philosophy 2 (1):72-82.
    Diverse beliefs about the nature and essence of scientific truth are pervasive in the nursing literature. Most recently, rejection of a more traditional and objective truth has resulted in a shift toward an emphasis on the acceptance of multiple and subjective truths. Some nursing scholars have discarded the idea that objective truth exists at all, but instead have argued that subjective truth is the only knowable truth and therefore the one that ought to govern nursing's disciplinary inquiry. Yet, there has (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Review of Maurice A. Finocchiaro: Defending Copernicus and Galileo: Critical Reasoning in the Two Affairs. [REVIEW]Peter Slezak - 2011 - Science & Education 20 (1):71-81.
    In reviewing Finocchiaro's book, I argue that Galileo deserved to be found guilty for the charges against him. A measure of Finocchiaro's scrupulously fair-minded presentation of the issues surrounding the Galileo Affair is the fact that a contrary case against his own exculpatory evaluation may be inferred from his meticulous scholarship. Specifically, to acknowledge that the standards of evaluation and judgment have changed since 1633 is not in any way to diminish Galileo's greatness but, on the contrary, to recognize his (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Book Review: Conquest of Abundance: A Tale of Abstraction Versus the Richness of Being. [REVIEW]Struan Jacobs - 2006 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 36 (3):386-389.
  • The wizardry of OZ (why the machine is really a ghost).Rick Rusovick - 1996 - World Futures 47 (2):215-237.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Rationalisation of Death: The Medico-Legal System and the Elimination of Human Agency.Lindsay Prior - 1984 - Theory, Culture and Society 2 (2):55-70.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Telling the tree: narrative representation and the study of evolutionary history.Robert J. O'Hara - 1992 - Biology and Philosophy 7 (2): 135–160.
    Accounts of the evolutionary past have as much in common with works of narrative history as they do with works of science. Awareness of the narrative character of evolutionary writing leads to the discovery of a host of fascinating and hitherto unrecognized problems in the representation of evolutionary history, problems associated with the writing of narrative. These problems include selective attention, narrative perspective, foregrounding and backgrounding, differential resolution, and the establishment of a canon of important events. The narrative aspects of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • An Exposition of Process Theory and Critique of Mohr’s (1982) Conceptualization Thereof.Fred Niederman & Salvatore T. March - 2018 - Philosophy of Management 17 (3):321-331.
    Championed by Whitehead (1979), a process metaphysics has been forwarded as one way of conceptualizing the fundamental nature of our existence. On an applied level, we might use the notion of process within the framework of scientific method to advance our knowledge of how we might take steps to create particular outcomes or states that we desire within organizations. We discuss both forward and backward looking approaches to developing process theory. Ultimately, though, in this paper, we present discussion of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Popper, Kuhn, Lakatos, and Aim-Oriented Empiricism.Nicholas Maxwell - 2005 - Philosophia 32 (1-4):181-239.
    In this paper I argue that aim-oriented empiricism (AOE), a conception of natural science that I have defended at some length elsewhere[1], is a kind of synthesis of the views of Popper, Kuhn and Lakatos, but is also an improvement over the views of all three. Whereas Popper's falsificationism protects metaphysical assumptions implicitly made by science from criticism, AOE exposes all such assumptions to sustained criticism, and furthermore focuses criticism on those assumptions most likely to need revision if science is (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Postscript on Modernism and Postmodernism, Both.Joseph Margolis - 1989 - Theory, Culture and Society 6 (1):5-30.
  • Epistemology and the sociology of knowledge.Charles Kurzman - 1994 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 24 (3):267-290.
    Epistemology, I will argue, is of crucial importance to the sociology of knowledge— not just by way of definition of the phenomenon under study, but also because approaches to the sociology of knowledge rely on too-often implicit epistemological stances. I will make this argument through a series of categorizations: first, I will classify the field of epistemology into its three main forms; second, I will classify the sociology of knowledge into epistemological categories; third, I will classify the sociology of science (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Social science-based understandings of science: Reflections on Fuller.Arie W. Kruglanski - 1991 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 21 (2):223-231.
  • Learning in the age of digital reason. [REVIEW]Jeremy Knox - 2017 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 51 (1):128-129.
  • The logic of discovery and Darwin's pre-malthusian researches.Scott A. Kleiner - 1988 - Biology and Philosophy 3 (3):293-315.
    Traditional logical empiricist and more recent historicist positions on the logic of discovery are briefly reviewed and both are found wanting. None have examined the historical detail now available from recent research on Darwin, from which there is evidence for gradual transition in descriptive and explanatory concepts. This episode also shows that revolutionary research can be directed by borrowed metascientific objectives and heuristics from other disciplines. Darwin's own revolutionary research took place within an ontological context borrowed from non evolutionary predecessors (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Serendipity and vision: Two methods for discovery comments on Nickles.Scott A. Kleiner - 1999 - Biology and Philosophy 14 (1):55-63.
    Thomas Nickles challenges my thesis that innovative discoveries can be based on deliberately chosen problems and research strategies. He suggests that all significant innovation can be seen as such only in retrospect and that its generation must be serendipitous. Here I argue in response that significant innovations can and do often arise from self conscious critical appraisal of orthodox practice combined with regulated though speculative abductive argumentation to alternative explanatory schemata. Orthodox practice is not based upon monolithic systems of belief (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evolution or Progress? A (Critical) Defence of Habermas's Theory of Social Development.Graeme Kirkpatrick - 2002 - Thesis Eleven 72 (1):91-112.
    Habermas's theory of social evolution has been subjected to critique by environmentally motivated sociologists. They argue that his decision to recast social theory in terms of an extended, if selective analogy with biology leads him into a set of practical positions that are irreconcilable with Green politics and inconsistent with the goals of traditional critical theory. This article argues that these criticisms are based on an inaccurate assessment of the role of evolutionary concepts in Habermas's thought. By drawing out the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Why did Feyerabend Defend Astrology? Integrity, Virtue, and the Authority of Science.Ian James Kidd - 2016 - Social Epistemology 30 (4):464-482.
    This paper explores the relationship between epistemic integrity, virtue, and authority by offering a virtue epistemological reading of the defences of non-scientific beliefs, practices, and traditions in the writings of Paul Feyerabend. I argue that there was a robust epistemic rationale for those defences and that it can inform contemporary reflection on the epistemic authority of the sciences. Two common explanations of the purpose of those defences are rejected as lacking textual support. A third “pluralist” reading is judged more persuasive, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A Role for Experiment in Using the Law of Inertia to Explain the Nature of Science: A Comment on Lopes Celho.Calvin Kalman - 2009 - Science & Education 18 (1):25-31.
  • Physical Laws, Physical Entities and Ontology.E. Kaeser - 1977 - Dialectica 31 (3‐4):273-299.
    We investigate the way physical laws objectively refer to the entities they are about. Laws of mathematical physics do not refer directly to the “real world” but to an ideal specific domain of objects, which we term “scope”. In order to find out which real objects physical laws deal with, reference to the scope is not sufficient. We need in addition the search for domains to which laws apply — i. e. “empirical domains”— in order to establish their reference to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The status of the anomaly in the feminist God-talk of Rosemary Ruether.George Alfred James - 1990 - Zygon 25 (2):167-185.
    Scripture, the creeds, and tradition have provided the raw material that theology has attempted to refine. The contribution of much recent theology comes from new insight into these materials by women, blacks, and the Third World, often as examined by analytic tools derived from post‐Christian ideologies. The theology of Rosemary Ruether stands out because of her choice of sources, among which she includes documents excoriated as heretical by what she calls the patriarchal orthodoxy of the early Christian church. Because of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Retrieving the university.Vesa Huotari - 1998 - Social Epistemology 12 (1):59 – 65.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evaluating Complementary and Alternative Medicine: The Limits of Science and of Scientists.David J. Hufford - 2003 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 31 (2):198-212.
    My presentation was set as a counterpoint to the presentation by Lawrence Schneiderman, M.D., “Alternative Medicine or Alternatives to Medicine.”’ In this talk, Dr. Schneiderman vigorously critiqued CAM on the basis of evidence-based science as opposed to what he called “the collective romantic fantasy” of CAM. will challenge this science-versus-CAM view on the basis of several limits to science. My thesis here is: (1) the basic methods of science are as appropriate to the study of CAM as they are to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Unreality Business - How Economics (and Management) Became Anti-philosophical.Matthias P. Hühn - 2015 - Philosophy of Management 14 (1):47-66.
    This paper argues that economics, over the past 200 years, has become steadily more anti-philosophical and that there are three stages in the development of economic thought. Adam Smith intended economics to be a descriptive social science, rooted in an understanding of the moral and psychological processes of an individual’s decision-making and its connection to society in general. Yet, immediately after Smith’s death, economists made a clean cut and invented a totally new discipline: they switched towards a physicalist understanding of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • A normative theory of humanistic knowledge.Frans Gregersen & Simo Køppe - 1989 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 20 (1):40-53.
    Ausgehend von der Gegenüberstellung der Wissenschaftlichkeit der Naturwissenschaften und der Geisteswissenschaften wird argumentiert, daß Wissenschaftlichkeit nur auf der Basis einer Zusammenstellung wissenschaftstheoretischer, wissenschaftsgeschichtlicher und wissenschaftssoziologischer Kriterien definiert werden kann. Eine solche dreiteilige Definition wird skizziert, und es wird behauptet, daß dies gültig sowohl für die Naturwissenschaften als auch für die Geisteswissenschaften ist. Es folgt daraus, daß es im Prinzip keine Verschiedenheit zwischen der Wissenschaftlichkeit der einen Basiswissenschaft und der anderen gibt. Die Formulierung dreier normativer Kriterien für Wissenschaft als solche schließt (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Scientism, interpretation, and criticism.Philip S. Gorski - 1990 - Zygon 25 (3):279-307.
    What is the relationship between natural science, social science, and religion? The dominant paradigm in contemporary social science is scientism, the attempt to apply the methods of natural science to the study of society. However, scientism is problematic: it rests on a conception of natural science that cannot be sustained. Natural scientific understanding emerges from an instrumental and objectifying relation to the world; it is oriented toward control and manipulation of the physical world. Social‐scientific understanding, by contrast, must begin with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • European science and scholarship in exile: conformity and disparity: Mitchell Ash and Alfons Söllner, Forced Migration and Scientific Change: Emigre German-Speaking Scientists and Scholars After 1933. Washington, DC: German Historical Institute, 1996.A. C. Garrett - 1996 - History of the Human Sciences 9 (4):139-149.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Case of the Female Orgasm. [REVIEW]Lisa Gannett - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (4):619-638.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Autonomy, Reciprocity and Science in the Thought of Pierre Bourdieu.Bridget Fowler - 2006 - Theory, Culture and Society 23 (6):99-117.
    This article addresses the increasingly widespread view that Bourdieu's sociological analysis is flawed by excessive determinism and thus is anti-rationalist in its socio-political implications. Against this contention, it argues that works such as Distinction should be viewed as critiques of an absolutist universalism rather than of universalism as such. Moreover, Bourdieu's logic of practice, it is claimed, caters not only for a degree of autonomy at the level of the individual, but also identifies two key intellectual fields as pivotal cultural (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Galilean Approach to the Galileo Affair, 1609–2009.Maurice A. Finocchiaro - 2011 - Science & Education 20 (1):51-66.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teaching Chemistry for All Its Worth: The Interaction Between Facts, Ideas, and Language in Lavoisier’s and Priestley’s Chemistry Practice: The Case of the Study of the Composition of Air.Kevin de Berg - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (10):2045-2068.
  • Science education as an exercise in foreign affairs.William W. Cobern - 1995 - Science & Education 4 (3):287-302.
  • Complexity and post-modernism: understanding complex systems.P. Cilliers & David Spurrett - 1999 - South African Journal of Philosophy 18 (2):258-274.
    This is a review article of Paul Cillier's 1999 book _Complexity and Postmodernism_. The review article is generally encouraging and constructive, although isolates a number of areas in need of clarification or development in Cillier's work. The volume of the _South African Journal of Philosophy_ in which the review article appeared also printed a response by Cilliers.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Rethinking ‘style’ for historians and philosophers of science: converging lessons from sexuality, translation, and East Asian studies.Howard H. Chiang - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 40 (2):109-118.
    Historians and philosophers of science have furnished a wide array of theoretical-historiographical terms to emphasize the discontinuities among different systems of knowledge. Some of the most famous include Thomas Kuhn’s “paradigm”, Michel Foucault’s “episteme”, and the notion of “styles of reasoning” more recently developed by Ian Hacking and Arnold Davidson. This paper takes up this theoretical-historiographical thread by assessing the values and limitations of the notion of “style” for the historical and philosophical study of science. Specifically, reflecting on various methodological (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What is postnormal when there is no normal? a postdichotomous view of the histories of the past, present, and future.George Cairns - 2017 - World Futures 73 (6):1-15.
    In this paper, I discuss the concept of ‘postnormal times’ and argue that the term postnormal is misrepresentative where applied to describe a state beyond so-called ‘normal’ times. Such normality is characterized by, i) progress towards social, economic and political equilibrium, and ii) future betterment for all. I posit that these conditions represent, at best, misplaced optimism and, at worst, a deliberate veil of untruths. I also argue that the foundation of thinking on normalcy, based on the classical free market (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thinking with, against, and beyond the Pratyabhijñā philosophy—and back again.Sari L. Berger, J. M. Fritzman & Brandon J. Vance - 2018 - Asian Philosophy 28 (1):1-19.
    We argue that the pratyabhijñā system of Kaśmir Śaivism holds an inconsistent position. On the one hand, the Pratyabhijñā regards Śiva as an impersonal mechanism and the universe, including persons, as not having agency; call this the Impersonal Component. On the other hand, it considers Śiva himself as a person, and individual persons as having agency sufficient to respond to Śiva; call this the Personal Component. We maintain that the Personal Component should be affirmed and the Impersonal Component rejected. The (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Dada between Nietzsche's Birth of Tragedy and Bourdieu's Distinction: Existenz and Conflict in Cultural Analysis.T. J. Berard - 1999 - Theory, Culture and Society 16 (1):141-165.
    Dada continues to attract a small following among scholars, but has perhaps not yet been recognized as providing invaluable insight into the underlying functions and potentials of culture generally. This article explores the nature and theoretical import of Dada, and two radically different visions of culture as they might try to accommodate and explain Dada. Models of culture taken from Bourdieu and Nietzsche are brought to bear, first on Dada, and then on each other, with the aim of developing a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Idea of Academic Administration.Ronald Barnett - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 27 (2):179-192.
    Academic administration is not to be construed simply as a technical practice, the development of efficient management systems, nor as reactive, as response to the collective views of the academic community, nor in terms of academic leadership, the establishment and implementation of institutional aims. A full account of academic administration will provide a sense of the integral relationship between the academic administrator and the academic community. For that, a prior notion of the academic community is required. Such a notion, giving (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Unfortunate Domination of Social Theories by `Social Theory'.Paul Acourt - 1987 - Theory, Culture and Society 4 (4):659-689.
  • Karl Popper, Science and Enlightenment.Nicholas Maxwell - 2017 - London: UCL Press.
    Karl Popper is famous for having proposed that science advances by a process of conjecture and refutation. He is also famous for defending the open society against what he saw as its arch enemies – Plato and Marx. Popper’s contributions to thought are of profound importance, but they are not the last word on the subject. They need to be improved. My concern in this book is to spell out what is of greatest importance in Popper’s work, what its failings (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reason Dethroned; Knowledge Regained.James Arthur Moore - 1991 - Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh
    Hume held that we have no rational justification for our inductive beliefs. A more radical view is that we have no rational justification for any of our beliefs. This dissertation has two goals pertaining to this more radical view. // The first goal is to find a basis for constructive epistemology that is consistent with this view. This goal is first sought by considering externalist theories of knowledge since these do not require rational justification for knowledge. Externalist theories are defended (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark