Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Are connectionist models cognitive?Benny Shanon - 1992 - Philosophical Psychology 5 (3):235-255.
    In their critique of connectionist models Fodor and Pylyshyn (1988) dismiss such models as not being cognitive or psychological. Evaluating Fodor and Pylyshyn's critique requires examining what is required in characterizating models as 'cognitive'. The present discussion examines the various senses of this term. It argues the answer to the title question seems to vary with these different senses. Indeed, by one sense of the term, neither representa-tionalism nor connectionism is cognitive. General ramifications of such an appraisal are discussed and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The scope and limits of a mechanistic view of computational explanation.Maria Serban - 2015 - Synthese 192 (10):3371-3396.
    An increasing number of philosophers have promoted the idea that mechanism provides a fruitful framework for thinking about the explanatory contributions of computational approaches in cognitive neuroscience. For instance, Piccinini and Bahar :453–488, 2013) have recently argued that neural computation constitutes a sui generis category of physical computation which can play a genuine explanatory role in the context of investigating neural and cognitive processes. The core of their proposal is to conceive of computational explanations in cognitive neuroscience as a subspecies (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The analytic/holistic dichotomy: An epiphenomenon.Justine Sergent - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):521.
  • Metatheory of animal behavior.Erwin M. Segal - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):386-387.
  • The realistic stance.John R. Searle - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):527.
  • Models and reality.John R. Searle - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):399-399.
  • Redescribing development.Ellin Kofsky Scholnick - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):727-728.
  • Natural kinds.Stephen P. Schwartz - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):301-302.
  • Cognitive science at seven: A wolf at the door for behaviorism?Miriam W. Schustack & Jaime G. Carbonell - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):645.
  • “Behaviorism at fifty” at twenty.Roger Schnaitter - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):644.
  • Al, imagery, and theories.Roger C. Schank - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):566-566.
  • New wine in old glasses?Joseph M. Scandura - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):602-603.
  • Some untoward consequences of Dretske's “causal theory” of information.Kenneth M. Sayre - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):78-79.
  • Intentionality and communication theory.K. M. Sayre - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):155-165.
  • Intentionality and information processing: An alternative model for cognitive science.Kenneth M. Sayre - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):121-38.
    This article responds to two unresolved and crucial problems of cognitive science: (1) What is actually accomplished by functions of the nervous system that we ordinarily describe in the intentional idiom? and (2) What makes the information processing involved in these functions semantic? It is argued that, contrary to the assumptions of many cognitive theorists, the computational approach does not provide coherent answers to these problems, and that a more promising start would be to fall back on mathematical communication theory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Subjective Externalism.Sarah Sawyer - 2018 - Theoria 84 (1):4-22.
    In this article I argue for a novel theory of representational content, which I call ‘subjective externalism’. The view combines an internal, subjective constraint on the attribution of thought content which traditionally underpins internalist theories of thought, and an external, objective constraint on the attribution of thought content which traditionally underpins externalist theories of thought. While internalism and externalism are mutually inconsistent, the constraints to which each theory is committed are not. It is this realization that opens up the conceptual (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Conceptual errors and social externalism.Sarah Sawyer - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (211):265-273.
    Åsa Maria Wikforss has proposed a response to Burge's thought-experiments in favour of social externalism, one which allows the individualist to maintain that narrow content is truth-conditional without being idiosyncratic. The narrow aim of this paper is to show that Wikforss' argument against social externalism fails, and hence that the individualist position she endorses is inadequate. The more general aim is to attain clarity on the social externalist thesis. Social externalism need not rest, as is typically thought, on the possibility (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On demystifying the mental for psychology.Edward Sankowski - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):565-566.
  • Grammars-as-programs versus grammars- as-data.Jerry Samet - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):414-414.
  • The world represented as a hierarchy of nature may not require “species”.Stanley N. Salthe - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):300-301.
  • Situating representational redescriptionin infants' pragmatic knowledge.Julie C. Rutkowska - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):726-727.
  • Species as individuals: Logical, biological, and philosophical problems.Michael Ruse - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):299-300.
  • The sufficiency of information-caused belief for knowledge.Bede Rundle - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):78-78.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A farewell to functionalism.Lynne Rudder Baker - 1985 - Philosophical Studies 48 (July):1-14.
    dilemma, a dilemma concerning the individuation of psychological states that explain behavior. Beliefs are individuated by most functionahsts in terms of that 'that'-clauses; functional states are individuated 'narrowly' (i.e.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The logic of representation.William W. Rozeboom - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):385-386.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can information be de-cognitized?William W. Rozeboom - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):76-77.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Against methodological solipsism: The ecological approach.Mark Rowlands - 1995 - Philosophical Psychology 8 (1):5-24.
    This paper argues that an ecological approach to psychology of the sort advanced by J. J. Gibson provides a coherent and powerful alternative to the computational, information-processing, paradigm. The paper argues for two principles. Firstly, one cannot begin to understand what internal information processing an organism must accomplish until one understands what information is available to the organism in its environment. Secondly, an organism can process information by acting on or manipulating physical structures in its environment. An attempt is made (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Sensorimotor maps in the tectum.A. Roucoux & M. Crommelinck - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):386-387.
  • Worm detector replaced by network model – but still a bit worm-infested.Gerhard Roth & Kiisa Nishikawa - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):385-386.
  • Will the argument for abstracta please stand up?Alexander Rosenberg - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):526.
  • Typologies: Obstacles and opportunities in scientific change.Alexander Rosenberg - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):298-299.
  • The behaviorist concept of mind.David M. Rosenthal - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):643.
  • Group Doxastic Rationality Need Not Supervene on Individual Rationality.Don Ross - 2006 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 44 (S1):106-117.
    There is a strong formal analogy between proposition-wise supervenience of collective doxastic rationality on individual doxasticrationality and supervenience of social choice functions on individual choice functions. In light of this analogy, the basis for List and Pettit’s impossibility theorems can fruitfully be compared with the basis for Arrow’s. This helps to explain why List and Pettit can derive no impossibility theorem for set-wise supervenience. However, there are empirical reasons for doubting that set-wise supervenience of collective doxastic rationality on individual doxastic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • II. Searle on Intentionality∗.Ronald McIntyre - 1984 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 27 (1-4):468-483.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Representations and cognition.H. L. Roitblat - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):394-406.
  • How to build a mind.H. L. Roitblat - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):525.
  • The relevance of the machine metaphor.Thomas Roeper - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):413.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • There is more than one way to access an image.Lynn C. Robertson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):568.
  • Premature closure of controversial issues concerning animal memory representations.William A. Roberts - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):384-385.
  • Brain symbols and computationalist explanation.William S. Robinson - 1995 - Minds and Machines 5 (1):25-44.
    Computationalist theories of mind require brain symbols, that is, neural events that represent kinds or instances of kinds. Standard models of computation require multiple inscriptions of symbols with the same representational content. The satisfaction of two conditions makes it easy to see how this requirement is met in computers, but we have no reason to think that these conditions are satisfied in the brain. Thus, if we wish to give computationalist explanations of human cognition, without committing ourselvesa priori to a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Behaviorism at Seventy.Daniel N. Robinson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):641-643.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Concept Cartesianism, Concept Pragmatism, and Frege Cases.Bradley Rives - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 144 (2):211-238.
    This paper concerns the dialectal role of Frege Cases in the debate between Concept Cartesians and Concept Pragmatists. I take as a starting point Christopher Peacocke’s argument that, unlike Cartesianism, his ‘Fregean’ Pragmatism can account for facts about the rationality and epistemic status of certain judgments. I argue that since this argument presupposes that the rationality of thoughts turn on their content, it is thus question-begging against Cartesians, who claim that issues about rationality turn on the form, not the content, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Paralogical reasoning: Evans, Johnson-Laird, and Byrne on liar and truth-teller puzzles.Lance J. Rips - 1990 - Cognition 36 (3):291-314.
  • B. F. Skinner's operationism.Jon D. Ringen - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):567.
  • The demands of mental travel: demand characteristics of mental imagery experiments.Charles L. Richman, David B. Mitchell & J. Steven Reznick - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):564-565.
  • How not to reduce a functional psychology.Robert C. Richardson - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (1):125-37.
    There is often substantial disparity between philosophical ideals and scientific practice. Philosophical reductionism is motivated by a drive for ontological austerity. The vehicle is conceptual parsimony: the fewer our conceptual primitives, the less are our ontological commitments. A general moral to be drawn from my “Functionalism and Reductionism” is that scientific reduction does not, and should not be expected to, facilitate conceptual economy; yet reduction it still is, and in the classical mold. Those who press for the irreducibility of a (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Conscious and nonconscious imagery.Alan Richardson - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):563-564.
  • Vagueness, Identity, and the Dangers of a General Metaphysics in Archaeology.Artur Ribeiro - 2021 - Open Philosophy 4 (1):20-35.
    Archaeology is currently bound to a series of metaphysical principles, one of which claims that reality is composed of a series of discrete objects. These discrete objects are fundamental metaphysical entities in archaeological science and posthumanist/new Materialist approaches and can be posited, assembled, counted, and consequently included in quantitative models (e.g. Big Data, Bayesian models) or network models (e.g. Actor-Network Theory). The work by Sørensen and Marila shows that archaeological reality is not that discrete, that some objects cannot be easily (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ontology and ideology of behaviorism and mentalism.Georges Rey - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):640.
  • Things mere mortals can do, but philosophers can’t.Stephanie Rennick - 2015 - Analysis 75 (1):22-26.
    David Lewis famously argued that the time traveller ‘can’ murder her grandfather, even though she never will: it is compossible with a particular set of facts including her motive, opportunity and skill . I argue that while ordinary agents ‘can’ under Lewis’s conception, philosophers cannot – the latter will not only fail to fulfill their homicidal intentions but also fail to form them in the first place.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations