Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Advances and retreats In laterality research.Eran Zaidel - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):523.
  • Smell's puzzling discrepancy: Gifted discrimination, yet pitiful identification.Benjamin D. Young - 2019 - Mind and Language 35 (1):90-114.
  • Is “Behaviorism at fifty” twenty years older?Everett J. Wyers - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):653.
  • On the operational definition of a toothache.Colin Wright - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):571.
  • Thought and the social community.Andrew Woodfield - 1982 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 25 (December):435-50.
    The anti?Cartesian idea that a person's thoughts are not entirely fixed by what goes on inside that person's head is suggested by Hegel, and echoed in Wittgenstein and Frege. An argument for the view has recently been given by Tyler Burge. This paper claims that Burge's data can be explained better by an individualistic theory. The basic idea is that an individual's thoughts are specified analogically, in ordinary discourse, through the model of a language. Though the modelling?sentences are public, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Operant conditioning and behavioral neuroscience.Michael L. Woodruff - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):652.
  • What Does it Mean to Understand Language?Terry Winograd - 1980 - Cognitive Science 4 (3):209-241.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Articulating Babel: An approach to cultural evolution.William C. Wimsatt - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 44 (4):563-571.
    After an initial discussion of the character of interdisciplinary linkages between complex disciplines, I consider an area with confluences of many diverse disciplines—the study of cultural evolution. This must embrace not only the traditional biological sciences, but also the multiple often warring disciplines of the human sciences. This interdisciplinary articulation is in its early stages compared, e.g., to that of evolutionary biology or evolutionary developmental biology, and I try to lay out major axes along which its articulation should plausibly occur, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The metaphysics of individuality and its consequences for systematic biology.E. O. Wiley - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):302-303.
  • Rules are not processes.Robert Wilensky - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):415.
  • Mind the brain.Martha Wilson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):393-393.
  • Meaning making and the mind of the externalist.Robert A. Wilson - 2010 - In Richard Menary (ed.), The Extended Mind. MIT Press. pp. 167--188.
    This paper attempts to do two things. First, it recounts the problem of intentionality, as it has typically been conceptualized, and argues that it needs to be reconceptualized in light of the radical form of externalism most commonly referred to as the extended mind thesis. Second, it provides an explicit, novel argument for that thesis, what I call the argument from meaning making, and offers some defense of that argument. This second task occupies the core of the paper, and in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Interface Theory vs Gibson: An Ontological Defense of the Ecological Approach.Andrew D. Wilson - 2021 - Philosophical Psychology 34 (7):989-1010.
    Interface theory is the hypothesis that inferential, representational theories of perception entail that fitness, not truth, dictates the evolution of perceptual systems. They show, with simulations, that “veridical” perceptual mappings (ones that preserve at least some of the structure of the world) are routinely out-competed by “non-veridical” interfaces (ones that make no attempt to preserve that structure). They therefore take particular aim at the direct perception, ecological approach to perception and work to show that such a system, even if technically (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How Can Philosophy Be a True Cognitive Science Discipline?William Bechtel - 2010 - Topics in Cognitive Science 2 (3):357-366.
    Although philosophy has been only a minor contributor to cognitive science to date, this paper describes two projects in naturalistic philosophy of mind and one in naturalistic philosophy of science that have been pursued during the past 30 years and that can make theoretical and methodological contributions to cognitive science. First, stances on the mind–body problem (identity theory, functionalism, and heuristic identity theory) are relevant to cognitive science as it negotiates its relation to neuroscience and cognitive neuroscience. Second, analyses of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Self-Knowledge and Knowledge of Content.Åsa Maria Wikforss - 2008 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (3):399-424.
    The question of whether content externalism poses a threat to the traditional view of self-knowledge has been much debated. Compatibilists have tried to diffuse the threat by appealing to the self-verifying character of reflexive judgments about our own thoughts, while incompatibilists have strenuously objected that this does not suffice. In my paper I argue that this debate is fundamentally misconceived since it is based, on both sides, on the problematic notion of ‘knowledge of content’. What this shows, I argue, is (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Semantic Externalism and Psychological Externalism.Åsa Wikforss - 2008 - Philosophy Compass 3 (1):158-181.
    Externalism is widely endorsed within contemporary philosophy of mind and language. Despite this, it is far from clear how the externalist thesis should be construed and, indeed, why we should accept it. In this entry I distinguish and examine three central types of externalism: what I call foundational externalism, externalist semantics, and psychological externalism. I suggest that the most plausible version of externalism is not in fact a very radical thesis and does not have any terribly interesting implications for philosophy (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Social Externalism and Conceptual Errors.Asa Maria Wikforss - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 51 (203):217-231.
    Ever since Putnam and Burge launched their respective attacks on individualist accounts of meaning the individualist has felt squeezed for space.1 Very little maneuvering room, it seems, is left for the philosopher who wants to deny that meaning and mental content depend on the speaker's social environment. One option, popular amongst individualists, is to grant that reference is socially determined but argue that there is nevertheless a notion of meaning or content that can be understood individualistically. That is, the individualist (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Negation in Skinner's system.N. E. Wetherick - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):606-607.
  • The development of concepts of the mental world.Henry M. Wellman - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):651.
  • Interpreting Degree Semantics.Alexis Wellwood - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Contemporary research in compositional, truth-conditional semantics often takes judgments of the relative unacceptability of certain phrasal combinations as evidence for lexical semantics. For example, observing that completely full sounds perfectly natural whereas completely tall does not has been used to motivate a distinction whereby the lexical entry for full but not for tall specifies a scalar endpoint. So far, such inferences seem unobjectionable. In general, however, applying this methodology can lead to dubious conclusions. For example, observing that slightly bent is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The dynamics of perception and action.William H. Warren - 2006 - Psychological Review 113 (2):358-389.
  • On the function of mental imagery.David L. Waltz - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):569-570.
  • On the metaphysics of internalism and externalism.Alberto Voltolini - 2005 - Disputatio 1 (18):1 - 24.
    In this paper, I explore the consequences of the thesis that externalism and internalism are (possibly, but as we will see not necessarily, opposite) metaphysical doctrines on the individuation conditions of a thought. If I am right, this thesis primarily entails that at least some naturalist positions on the ontology of the mind, namely the reductionistic ones, are hardly compatible with both externalism and a version of internalism so conceived, namely relational internalism. Indeed, according to both externalism and relational internalism, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Extended mathematical cognition: external representations with non-derived content.Karina Vold & Dirk Schlimm - 2020 - Synthese 197 (9):3757-3777.
    Vehicle externalism maintains that the vehicles of our mental representations can be located outside of the head, that is, they need not be instantiated by neurons located inside the brain of the cogniser. But some disagree, insisting that ‘non-derived’, or ‘original’, content is the mark of the cognitive and that only biologically instantiated representational vehicles can have non-derived content, while the contents of all extra-neural representational vehicles are derived and thus lie outside the scope of the cognitive. In this paper (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Is there an implicit level of representation?Annie Vinter & Pierre Perruchet - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):730-731.
  • The egg revealed.William S. Verplanck - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):605-606.
  • Smolensky's theory of mind.Paul F. M. J. Verschure - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):407-407.
  • On observing emergent properties and their compositions.Francisco T. Varela & Vicente Sanchez-Leighton - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):401-402.
  • The roles of philosophy in cognitive science.Tim Van Gelder - 1998 - Philosophical Psychology 11 (2):117-36.
    When the various disciplines participating in cognitive science are listed, philosophy almost always gets a guernsey. Yet, a couple of years ago at the conference of the Cognitive Science Society in Boulder (USA), there was no philosophy or philosopher with any prominence on the program. When queried on this point, the organizer (one of the "superstars" of the field) claimed it was partly an accident, but partly also due to an impression among members of the committee that philosophy is basically (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Intentional system theory and experimental psychology.Michael H. Van Kleeck - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):533.
  • Internal representations and indeterminacy: A skeptical view.William R. Uttal - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):392-393.
  • Intentionally: A problem of multiple reference frames, specificational information, and extraordinary boundary conditions on natural law.M. T. Turvey - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):153-155.
  • Ecological laws of perceiving and acting: In reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn.Michael T. Turvey, R. E. Shaw, Edward S. Reed & William M. Mace - 1981 - Cognition 9 (3):237-304.
  • Methodological solipsism and explanation in psychology.Raimo Tuomela - 1989 - Philosophy of Science 56 (March):23-47.
    This paper is a discussion of the tenability of methodological solipsism, which typically relies on the so-called Explanatory Thesis. The main arguments in the paper are directed against the latter thesis, according to which internal (or autonomous or narrow) psychological states as opposed to noninternal ones suffice for explanation in psychology. Especially, feedback-based actions are argued to require indispensable reference to noninternal explanantia, often to explanatory common causes. Thus, to the extent that methodological solipsism is taken to require the truth (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Metaphysics, method, and the mouth: Philosophical lessons of speech perception.J. D. Trout - 2001 - Philosophical Psychology 14 (3):261-291.
    This paper advances a novel argument that speech perception is a complex system best understood nonindividualistically and therefore that individualism fails as a general philosophical program for understanding cognition. The argument proceeds in four steps. First, I describe a "replaceability strategy", commonly deployed by individualists, in which one imagines replacing an object with an appropriate surrogate. This strategy conveys the appearance that relata can be substituted without changing the laws that hold within the domain. Second, I advance a "counterfactual test" (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Models, yes; homunculus, no.Frederick M. Toates - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):650.
  • Computation misrepresented: The procedural/declarative controversy exhumed.Henry Thompson - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):415.
  • Are radical and cognitive behaviorism incompatible?Roger K. Thomas - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):650.
  • “Mental way stations” in contemporary theories of animal learning.William S. Terry - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):649.
  • Animal versus human minds.H. S. Terrace - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):391-392.
  • A behavioral theory of mind?H. S. Terrace - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):569.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What really matters.Charles Taylor - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):532.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wskazywanie w myślach. Myśli zależne od przedmiotu a semantyka złożonych wyrażeń wskazujących.Maciej Tarnowski - 2020 - Filozofia Nauki 28 (1):85-110.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intelligent neurons.G. Székely - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):388-389.
  • Probaility and information.Patrick Suppes - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):81-82.
  • Chomsky, London and Lewis.D. Stoljar - 2015 - Analysis 75 (1):16-22.
    This article suggests that Chomsky’s notorious ‘London’ argument against semantics looks much more plausible that it is usually interpreted as being when seen in the light of something apparently remote from its concerns, viz., David Lewis’s distinction between natural and non-natural properties.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mutualism in the human sciences: Towards the implementation of a theory.Arthur Still & James M. M. Good - 1992 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 22 (2):105–128.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Is behaviorism vacuous?Stephen P. Stich - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):647.
  • Intentionality and naturalism.Stephen P. Stich & Stephen Laurence - 1994 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1):159-82.
    ...the deepest motivation for intentional irrealism derives not from such relatively technical worries about individualism and holism as we.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Connectionism, Realism, and realism.Stephen P. Stich - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):531.