Switch to: References

Citations of:

Reference and generality

Ithaca, N.Y.,: Cornell University Press. Edited by Michael C. Rea (1962)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Data on language input: Incomprehensible omission indeed!Catherine E. Snow & Michael Tomasello - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):357-358.
  • Parts and Moments. Studies in Logic and Formal Ontology.Barry Smith (ed.) - 1982 - Philosophia Verlag.
    A collection of material on Husserl's Logical Investigations, and specifically on Husserl's formal theory of parts, wholes and dependence and its influence in ontology, logic and psychology. Includes translations of classic works by Adolf Reinach and Eugenie Ginsberg, as well as original contributions by Wolfgang Künne, Kevin Mulligan, Gilbert Null, Barry Smith, Peter M. Simons, Roger A. Simons and Dallas Willard. Documents work on Husserl's ontology arising out of early meetings of the Seminar for Austro-German Philosophy.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • Material Constitution is Ad Hoc.Jeroen Smid - 2017 - Erkenntnis 82 (2):305-325.
    The idea that two objects can coincide—by sharing all their proper parts, or matter—yet be non-identical, results in the “Problem of Coincident Objects”: in what relation do objects stand if they are not identical but share all their proper parts? One solution is to introduce material constitution. In this paper, I argue that this is ad hoc since, first, this solution cannot be generalized to solve similar problems, and, second, there are pseudo cases of coincidence that should not trigger the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Logic and grammar.Hartley Slater - 2007 - Ratio 20 (2):206–218.
    I have written a number of articles recently that have a rather remarkable character. They all point out trivial grammatical facts that, at great cost, have not been respected in twentieth century Logic. A major continuous strand in my previous work, with this same character, I will first summarise, to locate the kind of fact that is involved. But then I shall present an overview of the more recent, and more varied points I have made, which demonstrate the far larger (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Completing Russell’s Logic.Hartley Slater - 2007 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 27 (1).
    The epsilon calculus improves upon the predicate calculus by systematically providing complete individual terms. Recent research has shown that epsilon terms are therefore the “logically proper names” Russell was not able to formalize, but their use improves upon Russell’s theory of descriptions not just in that way. This paper details relevant formal aspects of the epsilon calculus before tracing its extensive application not just to the theory of descriptions, but also to more general problems with anaphoric reference. It ends by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pointers.Peter Simons - 2017 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 94 (3):381-390.
    _ Source: _Volume 94, Issue 3, pp 381 - 390 Reference can fail in a way that intentionality cannot. Though the stream of phenomenal experience typically does not fail to target objects outside, it may do. How does the mind go about targeting objects beyond itself? The speculative conjecture of this paper is that it does so by a type of process which can be called _pointing_, and that the acts or act-aspects of pointing can be called _pointers_. The notion (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Parthood.Theodore Sider - 2007 - Philosophical Review 116 (1):51-91.
    There will be a few themes. One to get us going: expansion versus contraction. About an object, o, and the region, R, of space(time) in which o is exactly located,1 we may ask: i) must there exist expansions of o: objects in filled superregions2 of R? ii) must there exist contractions of o: objects in filled subregions of..
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   220 citations  
  • The logic and mathematics of occasion sentences.Pieter A. M. Seuren, Venanizo Capretta & Herman Geuvers - 2001 - Linguistics and Philosophy 24 (5):531-595.
    The prime purpose of this paper is, first, to restore to discourse-bound occasion sentences their rightful central place in semantics and secondly, taking these as the basic propositional elements in the logical analysis of language, to contribute to the development of an adequate logic of occasion sentences and a mathematical foundation for such a logic, thus preparing the ground for more adequate semantic, logical and mathematical foundations of the study of natural language. Some of the insights elaborated in this paper (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language acquisition: Dubious assumptions and a specious explanatory principle.I. M. Schlesinger - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):355-356.
  • Donkey anaphora: the view from sign language (ASL and LSF).Philippe Schlenker - 2011 - Linguistics and Philosophy 34 (4):341-395.
    There are two main approaches to the problem of donkey anaphora (e.g. If John owns a donkey , he beats it ). Proponents of dynamic approaches take the pronoun to be a logical variable, but they revise the semantics of quantifiers so as to allow them to bind variables that are not within their syntactic scope. Older dynamic approaches took this measure to apply solely to existential quantifiers; recent dynamic approaches have extended it to all quantifiers. By contrast, proponents of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Against the Russellian open future.Anders J. Schoubye & Brian Rabern - 2017 - Mind 126 (504): 1217–1237.
    Todd (2016) proposes an analysis of future-directed sentences, in particular sentences of the form 'will(φ)', that is based on the classic Russellian analysis of definite descriptions. Todd's analysis is supposed to vindicate the claim that the future is metaphysically open while retaining a simple Ockhamist semantics of future contingents and the principles of classical logic, i.e. bivalence and the law of excluded middle. Consequently, an open futurist can straightforwardly retain classical logic without appeal to supervaluations, determinacy operators, or any further (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Vague Objects and the Problem of the Many.Thomas Sattig - 2013 - Metaphysica 14 (2):211-223.
    The problem of the many poses the task of explaining mereological indeterminacy of ordinary objects in a way that sustains our familiar practice of counting these objects. The aim of this essay is to develop a solution to the problem of the many that is based on an account of mereological indeterminacy as having its source in how ordinary objects are, independently of how we represent them. At the center of the account stands a quasi-hylomorphic ontology of ordinary objects as (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Seeing the language: a diagrammatic approach to natural discourse.Aránzazu San Ginés - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):411-439.
    The key idea behind the diagrammatic approach presented in the paper is that the sophisticated mechanisms of human visual construction also play an important role in natural languages. We propose a diagrammatic representation of English, giving examples, translation rules, and semantics. Special attention will be paid to anaphoric phenomena, in particular, the possibility of a uniform treatment of anaphoric pronouns.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reflections on Reflexivity.Nathan Salmon - 1992 - Linguistics and Philosophy 15 (1):53 - 63.
  • Intentional identity interpreted: A case study of the relations among quantifiers, pronouns, and propositional attitudes. [REVIEW]Esa Saarinen - 1978 - Linguistics and Philosophy 2 (2):151 - 223.
  • Modal subordination and pronominal anaphora in discourse.Craige Roberts - 1989 - Linguistics and Philosophy 12 (6):683 - 721.
  • On working both sides of the street.R. L. Purtill - 1977 - Metaphilosophy 8 (2‐3):108-115.
  • On the format for parameters.Luigi Rizzi - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):355-356.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On interpreting pronouns.Barry Richards - 1984 - Linguistics and Philosophy 7 (3):287 - 324.
  • Mereological Nihilism and Puzzles about Material Objects.Bradley Rettler - 2018 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99 (4):842-868.
    Mereological nihilism is the view that no objects have proper parts. Despite how counter‐intuitive it is, it is taken quite seriously, largely because it solves a number of puzzles in the metaphysics of material objects – or so its proponents claim. In this article, I show that for every puzzle that mereological nihilism solves, there is a similar puzzle that (a) it doesn’t solve, and (b) every other solution to the original puzzle does solve. Since the solutions to the new (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Methodological reflections on current linguistic theory.W. V. Quine - 1970 - Synthese 21 (3-4):386-398.
  • The argument from convention revisited.Francesco Pupa - 2018 - Synthese 195 (5):2175-2204.
    The argument from convention contends that the regular use of definite descriptions as referential devices strongly implies that a referential semantic convention underlies such usage. On the presumption that definite descriptions also participate in a quantificational semantic convention, the argument from convention has served as an argument for the thesis that the English definite article is ambiguous. Here, I revisit this relatively new argument. First, I address two recurring criticisms of the argument from convention: its alleged tendency to overgenerate and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Fregean grammar: A formal outline.Timothy C. Potts - 1978 - Studia Logica 37 (1):7 - 26.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What am I? Virtual machines and the mind/body problem.John L. Pollock - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (2):237–309.
    When your word processor or email program is running on your computer, this creates a "virtual machine” that manipulates windows, files, text, etc. What is this virtual machine, and what are the virtual objects it manipulates? Many standard arguments in the philosophy of mind have exact analogues for virtual machines and virtual objects, but we do not want to draw the wild metaphysical conclusions that have sometimes tempted philosophers in the philosophy of mind. A computer file is not made of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Substance: The Constitution of Reality.P. M. S. Hacker - 1979 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1):239-261.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • There is no 'is' of constitution.Bryan Pickel - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 147 (2):193 - 211.
    I defend the view that ordinary objects like statues are identical to the pieces of matter from which they are made. I argue that ordinary speakers assert sentences such as ‘this statue is a molded piece of clay’. This suggests that speakers believe propositions which entail that ordinary objects such as statues are the pieces matter from which they are made, and therefore pluralism contradicts ordinary beliefs. The dominant response to this argument purports to find an ambiguity in the word (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On some proposals for the semantics of mass nouns.Francis Jeffry Pelletier - 1974 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 3 (1/2):87 - 108.
    Simple mass nouns are words like ‘water’, ‘furniture’ and ‘gold’. We can form complex mass noun phrases such as ‘dirty water’, ‘leaded gold’ and ‘green grass’. I do not propose to discuss the problems in giving a characterization of the words that are mass versus those that are not. For the purposes of this paper I shall make the following decrees: (a) nothing that is not a noun or noun phrase can be mass, (b) no abstract noun phrases are considered (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Non-singular reference: Some preliminaries.F. Jeffry Pelletier - 1975 - Philosophia 5 (4):451-465.
    One of the goals of a certain brand of philosopher has been to give an account of language and linguistic phenomena by means of showing how sentences are to be translated into a "logically perspicuous notation" (or an "ideal language"—to use passe terminology). The usual reason given by such philosophers for this activity is that such a notational system will somehow illustrate the "logical form" of these sentences. There are many candidates for this notational system: (almost) ordinary first-order predicate logic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • ([How/why]) does linguistics matter to philosophy?Francis Jeffry Pelletier - 1977 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 15 (3):393-426.
  • Solving the Caesar Problem Without Categorical Sortals.Nikolaj Jang Pedersen - 2009 - Erkenntnis 71 (2):141-155.
    The neo-Fregean account of arithmetical knowledge is centered around the abstraction principle known as Hume’s Principle: for any concepts X and Y , the number of X ’s is the same as the number of Y ’s just in case there is a 1–1 correspondence between X and Y . The Caesar Problem, originally raised by Frege in §56 of Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik , emerges in the context of the neo-Fregean programme, because, though Hume’s Principle provides a criterion of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Supposition as Quantification versus Supposition as Global Quantificational Effect.Terence Parsons - 1997 - Topoi 16 (1):41-63.
    This paper follows up a suggestion by Paul Vincent Spade that there were two Medieval theories of the modes of personal supposition. I suggest that early work by Sherwood and others was a study of quantifiers: their semantics and the effects of context on inferences that can be made from quantified terms. Later, in the hands of Burley and others, it changed into a study of something else, a study of what I call global quantificational effect. For example, although the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Opacity, coreference, and pronouns.Barbara Hall Partee - 1970 - Synthese 21 (3-4):359 - 385.
    The problem discussed here is to find a basis for a uniform treatment of the relation between pronouns and their antecedents, taking into account both linguists' and philosophers' approaches. The two main candidates would appear to be the linguists' notion of coreference and the philosophers' notion of pronouns as variables. The notion of coreference can be extended to many but not all cases where the antecedent is non-referential. The pronouns-as-variables approach appears to come closer to full generality, but there are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Nominal and temporal anaphora.Barbara H. Partee - 1984 - Linguistics and Philosophy 7 (3):243--286.
  • Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact.Barbara H. Partee - 2010 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6 (1).
    Formal semantics is an approach to SEMANTICS1, the study of meaning, with roots in logic, the philosophy of language, and linguistics, and since the 1980’s a core area of linguistic theory. Characteristics of formal semantics to be treated in this article include the following: Formal semanticists treat meaning as mind-independent (though abstract), contrasting with the view of meanings as concepts “in the head” (see I-LANGUAGE AND E-LANGUAGE and MEANING EXTERNALISM AND INTERNALISM); formal semanticists distinguish semantics from knowledge of semantics (Lewis (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact.Barbara H. Partee - 2011 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6:13.
    Formal semantics and pragmatics as they have developed since the late 1960's have been shaped by fruitful interdisciplinary collaboration among linguists, philosophers, and logicians, among others, and in turn have had noticeable effects on developments in syntax, philosophy of language, computational linguistics, and cognitive science.In this paper I describe the environment in which formal semantics was born and took root, highlighting the differences in ways of thinking about natural language semantics in linguistics and in philosophy and logic. With Montague as (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Anaphoric pronouns in very late medieval supposition theory.Terence Parsons - 1994 - Linguistics and Philosophy 17 (5):429 - 445.
    This paper arose from an attempt to determine how the very late medieval1 supposition theorists treated anaphoric pronouns, pronouns whose significance is derivative from their antecedents. Modern researches into pronouns were stimulated in part by the problem of "donkey sentences" discussed by Geach 1962 in a section explaining what is wrong with medieval supposition theory. So there is some interest in seeing exactly what the medieval account comes to, especially if it turns out, as I suspect, to work as well (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Atomic ontology.Andrew Parisi - 2020 - Synthese 197 (1):355-379.
    The aim of this article is to offer a method for determining the ontological commitments of a formalized theory. The second section shows that determining the consequence relation of a language model-theoretically entails that the ontology of a theory is tied very closely to the variables that feature in that theory. The third section develops an alternative way of determining the ontological commitments of a theory given a proof-theoretic account of the consequence relation for the language that theory is in. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La philosophie au xive siècle.Claude Panaccio - 1992 - Dialogue 31 (3):363-.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Preface.Ewan Klein - 1984 - Linguistics and Philosophy 7 (3):209-210.
  • Geach, Aristotle and Predicate Logics.Alex Orenstein - 2015 - Philosophical Investigations 38 (1-2):96-114.
    Geach's account of the Aristotelian logic of categorical sentences supplemented the views shared by Frege, Russell, Quine and others. I argue that this particular predicate logic approach and Geach's points apply to only one variety of natural language categorical sentences. For example, it takes the universal categorical as a universal conditional “If anything is a man, then it is mortal”. A different natural language form can and should be invoked: “Every man is a mortal.” Employing special restricted quantifiers in a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Extended Self.Eric T. Olson - 2011 - Minds and Machines 21 (4):481-495.
    The extended-mind thesis says that mental states can extend beyond one’s skin. Clark and Chalmers infer from this that the subjects of such states also extend beyond their skin: the extended-self thesis. The paper asks what exactly the extended-self thesis says, whether it really does follow from the extended-mind thesis, and what it would mean if it were true. It concludes that the extended-self thesis is unattractive, and does not follow from the extended mind unless thinking beings are literally bundles (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • XI*—A Few More Remarks on Logical Form.Alex Oliver - 1999 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (1):247-272.
    Alex Oliver; XI*—A Few More Remarks on Logical Form, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 99, Issue 1, 1 June 1999, Pages 247–272, https://doi.org/10.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Two perspectives on learnability.William O'Grady - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):354-355.
  • Book Reviews. [REVIEW]Sari Nusseibeh, Gabriel Nuchelmans, Francisco A. Rodriguez-Consuegra, G. Lolli, D. P. Henry, Francis Jeffry Pelletier, George Rousspoulos, J. Woleński, B. Smith & Peter Simons - 1992 - History and Philosophy of Logic 13 (1):115-132.
    Al-Farahr’s commentarv and short treatise on Aristotle’s De interpretatione. Introduction and translation from Arabic by F. Zimmerman. Oxford: Published for the British Academy by Oxford University Press, 1987. clii + 287 pp. of English. £22.50 Johann Andreas Segner, Specimen logicae universaliter demonstrate. Appendices: Two dissertations De syllogismo. Edited by Mirella Capozzi. Bologna: Editrice CLUEB, 1990. clxxii + 281 pp. 85 000 Lire M. Borga, P. Fregugua And D. Palladino, I contribua fondazionali della scuola di Peano. Milano: Franco Angeli, 1985, 257 (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tibbles the cat – reply to Burke.Harold W. Noonan - 1999 - Philosophical Studies 95 (3):215-218.
    In his interesting article, Michael Burke (1996) offers a novel solution to the puzzle of Tibbles, the cat, a solution he says, which is based on Aristotelian essentialism. In what follows I argue that, despite its ingenuity, Burke’s solution can be seen to be too implausible to be accepted once we extend it to a variant of the puzzle Burke himself suggests. The conclusion must be that one of the other solutions to the puzzle must be correct. Or, perhaps, that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Relative Identity.Harold W. Noonan - 2015 - Philosophical Investigations 38 (1-2):52-71.
    Examples suggest that one and the same A may be different Bs, and hence that there is some sort of incompleteness in the unqualified statement that x and y are the same which needs to be eliminated by answering the question “the same what?” One way to make this more precise is by appeal to Geach's idea that identity is relative. In this paper I evaluate Geach's relative identity thesis.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Personal Identity and the Hybrid View: A Middle Way.Harold W. Noonan - 2021 - Metaphysica 22 (2):263-283.
    Two of the main contenders in the debate about personal persistence over time are the neo-Lockean psychological continuity view and animalism as defended by Olson and Snowdon. Both are wrong. The position I shall argue for, which I call, following Olson, the hybrid view, takes psychological continuity as a sufficient but, pace the neo-Lockeans, not necessary condition for personal persistence. It sides with the animalist in allowing that mere biological continuity is also sufficient. So I am, in a sense, a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A conceptualist interpretation of Lesniewski's ontology.Nino B. Cocchiarella - 2001 - History and Philosophy of Logic 22 (1):29-43.
    A first-order formulation of Leśniewski's ontology is formulated and shown to be interpretable within a free first-order logic of identity extended to include nominal quantification over proper and common-name concepts. The latter theory is then shown to be interpretable in monadic second-order predicate logic, which shows that the first-order part of Leśniewski's ontology is decidable.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Ambiguity Thesis Versus Kripke's Defence of Russell.Murali Ramachandran - 1996 - Mind and Language 11 (4):371-387.
    In his influential paper 'Speaker's Reference and Semantic Reference', Kripke defends Russell's theory of descriptions against the charge that the existence of referential and attributive uses of descriptions reflects a semantic ambiguity. He presents a purely defensive argument to show that Russell's theory is not refuted by the referential usage and a number of methodological considerations which apparently tell in favour of Russell's unitary theory over an ambiguity theory. In this paper, I put forward a case for the ambiguity theory (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Transplantation, chemical inheritance, and the identity of organs.Stephen R. Munzer - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (2):555-570.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations