Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Logic, Mathematics, Philosophy, Vintage Enthusiasms: Essays in Honour of John L. Bell.David DeVidi, Michael Hallett & Peter Clark (eds.) - 2011 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    The volume includes twenty-five research papers presented as gifts to John L. Bell to celebrate his 60th birthday by colleagues, former students, friends and admirers. Like Bell’s own work, the contributions cross boundaries into several inter-related fields. The contributions are new work by highly respected figures, several of whom are among the key figures in their fields. Some examples: in foundations of maths and logic ; analytical philosophy, philosophy of science, philosophy of mathematics and decision theory and foundations of economics. (...)
    No categories
  • Simples and gunk.Kris McDaniel - unknown
    An object is a simple if and only if it has no proper parts. An object is gunk if and only if every proper part of that object itself has a proper part. In my dissertation, I address the following questions. The concepts of simples and gunk presuppose the concept of parthood. What is the status of this concept? his question itself divides into the following: does the concept of parthood have universal applicability, so that, just as every object is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Indivisible Parts and Extended Objects.Dean W. Zimmerman - 1996 - The Monist 79 (1):148-180.
    Physical boundaries and the earliest topologists. Topology has a relatively short history; but its 19th century roots are embedded in philosophical problems about the nature of extended substances and their boundaries which go back to Zeno and Aristotle. Although it seems that there have always been philosophers interested in these matters, questions about the boundaries of three-dimensional objects were closest to center stage during the later medieval and modern periods. Are the boundaries of an object actually existing, less-than-three-dimensional parts of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • The order structure of continua.Athanassios Tzouvaras - 1997 - Synthese 113 (3):381-421.
    A continuum is here a primitive notion intended to correspond precisely to a path-connected subset of the usual euclidean space. In contrast, however, to the traditional treatment, we treat here continua not as pointsets, but as irreducible entities equipped only with a partial ordering ≤ interpreted as parthood. Our aim is to examine what basic topological and geometric properties of continua can be expressed in the language of ≤, and what principles we need in order to prove elementary facts about (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Space, points and mereology. On foundations of point-free Euclidean geometry.Rafał Gruszczyński & Andrzej Pietruszczak - 2009 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 18 (2):145-188.
    This article is devoted to the problem of ontological foundations of three-dimensional Euclidean geometry. Starting from Bertrand Russell’s intuitions concerning the sensual world we try to show that it is possible to build a foundation for pure geometry by means of the so called regions of space. It is not our intention to present mathematically developed theory, but rather demonstrate basic assumptions, tools and techniques that are used in construction of systems of point-free geometry and topology by means of mereology (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Approximate Similarities and Poincaré Paradox.Giangiacomo Gerla - 2008 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 49 (2):203-226.
    De Cock and Kerre, in considering Poincaré paradox, observed that the intuitive notion of "approximate similarity" cannot be adequately represented by the fuzzy equivalence relations. In this note we argue that the deduction apparatus of fuzzy logic gives adequate tools with which to face the question. Indeed, a first-order theory is proposed whose fuzzy models are plausible candidates for the notion of approximate similarity. A connection between these structures and the point-free metric spaces is also established.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Whitehead's pointfree geometry and diametric posets.Giangiacomo Gerla & Bonaventura Paolillo - 2010 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 19 (4):289-308.
    This note is motivated by Whitehead’s researches in inclusion-based point-free geometry as exposed in An Inquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge and in The concept of Nature. More precisely, we observe that Whitehead’s definition of point, based on the notions of abstractive class and covering, is not adequate. Indeed, if we admit such a definition it is also questionable that a point exists. On the contrary our approach, in which the diameter is a further primitive, enables us to avoid (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Point-free geometry, ovals, and half-planes.Giangiacomo Gerla & Rafał Gruszczyński - 2017 - Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (2):237-258.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Point-Free Geometry and Verisimilitude of Theories.Giangiacomo Gerla - 2007 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 36 (6):707-733.
    A metric approach to Popper's verisimilitude question is proposed which is related to point-free geometry. Indeed, we define the theory of approximate metric spaces whose primitive notions are regions, inclusion relation, minimum distance, and maximum distance between regions. Then, we show that the class of possible scientific theories has the structure of an approximate metric space. So, we can define the verisimilitude of a theory as a function of its (approximate) distance from the truth. This avoids some of the difficulties (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Multivalued Logic to Transform Potential into Actual Objects.Giangiacomo Gerla - 2007 - Studia Logica 86 (1):69-87.
    We define the notion of “potential existence” by starting from the fact that in multi-valued logic the existential quantifier is interpreted by the least upper bound operator. Besides, we try to define in a general way how to pass from potential into actual existence.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Distances, diameters and verisimilitude of theories.Giangiacomo Gerla - 1992 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 31 (6):407-414.
  • Point-free Foundation of Geometry and Multivalued Logic.Cristina Coppola, Giangiacomo Gerla & Annamaria Miranda - 2010 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 51 (3):383-405.
    Whitehead, in two basic books, considers two different approaches to point-free geometry: the inclusion-based approach , whose primitive notions are regions and inclusion relation between regions, and the connection-based approach , where the connection relation is considered instead of the inclusion. We show that the latter cannot be reduced to the first one, although this can be done in the framework of multivalued logics.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Boundary.Achille C. Varzi - 2013 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    We think of a boundary whenever we think of an entity demarcated from its surroundings. There is a boundary (a line) separating Maryland and Pennsylvania. There is a boundary (a circle) isolating the interior of a disc from its exterior. There is a boundary (a surface) enclosing the bulk of this apple. Sometimes the exact location of a boundary is unclear or otherwise controversial (as when you try to trace out the margins of Mount Everest, or even the boundary of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Gunk, Topology and Measure.Frank Arntzenius - 2004 - In Dean Zimmerman (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics: Volume 4. Oxford University Press.
    I argue that it may well be the case that space and time do not consist of points, indeed that they have no smallest parts. I examine two different approaches to such pointless spaces : a topological approach and a measure theoretic approach. I argue in favor of the measure theoretic approach.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Can continuous motion be an illusion?Shan Gao - unknown
    It is widely accepted that continuity is the most essential characteristic of motion; the motion of macroscopic objects is apparently continuous, and classical mechanics, which describes such motion, is also based on the assumption of continuous motion. But is motion really continuous in reality? In this paper, I will try to answer this question through a new analysis of the cause of motion. It has been argued that the standard velocity in classical mechanics cannot fulfill the causal role required for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark