Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Relation of sensory scales to physical scales.Richard M. Warren - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):586-587.
  • Keeping the bath water along with the baby: Context effects represent a challenge, not a mortal wound, to the body of psychophysics.Mark Wagner - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):585-586.
  • Reasons for pragmatism: affording epistemic contact in a shared environment.Ludger van Dijk & Erik Myin - 2019 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 18 (5):973-997.
    Theorizing about perception is often motivated by a belief that without a way of ensuring that our perceptual experience correctly reflects the external world we cannot be sure that we perceive the world at all. Historically, coming up with a way of securing such epistemic contact has been a foundational issue in psychology. Recent ecological and enactive approaches challenge the requirement for perception to attain epistemic contact. This article aims to explicate this pragmatic starting point and the new direction of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Ceteris paribus laws.J. van Brakel - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):584-585.
  • Do we scale “objects” or isolated sensory dimensions?Michel Treisman - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):581-584.
  • Art in the realist ontology of J. J. Gibson.David R. Topper - 1983 - Synthese 54 (1):71 - 83.
  • The Proper Object of Vision.Gary Thrane - 1975 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 6 (1):3.
  • Selecting one attribute for judgment is not an act of stupidity.Robert Teghtsoonian - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):580-581.
  • Should the psychophysical model be rejected?Bruce Schneider - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):579-580.
  • Seeing empty space.Louise Richardson - 2009 - European Journal of Philosophy 18 (2):227-243.
    Abstract: In this paper I offer an account of a particular variety of perception of absence, namely, visual perception of empty space. In so doing, I aim to make explicit the role that seeing empty space has, implicitly, in Mike Martin's account of the visual field. I suggest we should make sense of the claim that vision has a field—in Martin's sense—in terms of our being aware of its limitations or boundaries. I argue that the limits of the visual field (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • James Gibson's ecological revolution in psychology.Edward S. Reed & Rebecca K. Jones - 1979 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 9 (2):189-204.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Modernity and the Upgrading of Psychological Reflectivity.Arne Poulsen - 1995 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 26 (2):1-20.
    The societal dynamism of modernity results in the theoretical upgrading and the actual development of personal reflective capacities, for example abstract reasoning, Kantian morality, and the development of the idiocentered perspective. These capacities are created in the disembedding of prereflective capacities, for example context-sensitive intelligence, care-morality, and mundocenteredness. The reflective capacities become the prerequisite of further modernization. The development-potential offered by the demands of modernity is accompanied by a risk of assimilative stress, for example pseudological reasoning, varieties of postmodernism, making (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the looks of things.Søren Overgaard - 2010 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 91 (2):260-284.
    In recent publications, Michael Tye and Alva Noë have claimed that there is a sense in which a tilted plate looks round and another sense in which it looks elliptical. This paper argues that their proposal faces decisive objections. On Tye and Noë's account of ordinary, veridical perception, appearances are in constant conflict. As a characterization of ordinary visual experience, this cannot be correct. I examine various responses to this criticism, and conclude that they all fail. I then argue that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Context effects in the entropic theory of perception.Kenneth H. Norwich - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):578-579.
  • The evident object of inquiry.Keith K. Niall - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):578-578.
  • Reasons for pragmatism: affording epistemic contact in a shared environment.Erik Myin & Ludger Dijk - 2019 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 18 (5):973-997.
    Theorizing about perception is often motivated by a belief that without a way of ensuring that our perceptual experience correctly reflects the external world we cannot be sure that we perceive the world at all. Historically, coming up with a way of securing such epistemic contact has been a foundational issue in psychology. Recent ecological and enactive approaches challenge the requirement for perception to attain epistemic contact. This article aims to explicate this pragmatic starting point and the new direction of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Attributes or objects: A paradigm shift in psychophysics.John S. Monahan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):577-577.
  • How important are dimensions to perception?Robert D. Melara - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):576-577.
  • Psychophysics and quantitative perceptual laws.Sergio C. Masin - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):575-576.
  • The perplexing plurality of psychophysical processes.Lawrence E. Marks - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):574-575.
  • Covert converging operations for multidimensional psychophysics.Neil A. Macmillan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):573-574.
  • Psychophysical scaling: Judgments of attributes or objects?Gregory R. Lockhead - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):543-558.
    Psychophysical scaling models of the form R = f, with R the response and I some intensity of an attribute, all assume that people judge the amounts of an attribute. With simple biases excepted, most also assume that judgments are independent of space, time, and features of the situation other than the one being judged. Many data support these ideas: Magnitude estimations of brightness increase with luminance. Nevertheless, I argue that the general model is wrong. The stabilized retinal image literature (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Constancy in a changing world.Gregory R. Lockhead - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):587-600.
  • Two categories of contextual variable in perception.Donald Laming - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):572-573.
  • Will the real stimulus please step forward?Lester E. Krueger - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):570-572.
  • Context effects: Pervasiveness and analysis.Donald L. King - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):570-570.
  • Psychophysics: Plus ça change ….Peter R. Killeen - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):569-569.
  • Perspective and spatial experience.Alex Kerr - forthcoming - Australasian Journal of Philosophy.
    Distant things look smaller, in a sense. Why? I argue that the reason is not that our experiences have a certain subject matter, or are about certain mind-independent things and features. Instead, distant things look smaller because of our way of perceiving them. I go on to offer a hypothesis about which specific way of perceiving explains why distant things look smaller.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Locke and the Visual Array.Michael Jacovides - 2011 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (1):69-91.
    A.D. Smith opens his excellent paper, “Space and Sight,” by remarking, One of the most notable features of both philosophy and psychology throughout the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries is the almost universal denial that we are immediately aware through sight of objects arrayed in three-dimensional space. This was not merely a denial of Direct Realism, but a denial that truly visual objects are even phenomenally presented in depth (481). Times have changed. As Smith writes, “It is hard to think of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Walking in a psychophysical dustbowl creates a dustcloud.Robert A. M. Gregson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):568-569.
  • Scales falling from the eyes?Richard L. Gregory - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):567-568.
  • The complexity and importance of the psychophysical scaling of sensory attributes.George A. Gescheider - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):567-567.
  • Psychophysical invariance, perceptual invariance and the physicalistic trap.Hannes Eisler - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):566-567.
  • Can brightness be related to luminance by a meaningful function?Ehtibar N. Dzhafarov - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):565-566.
  • The determinants of perceived brightness are complicated, but not hopelessly so.Thomas R. Corwin - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):564-565.
  • Psychophysical scaling: Context and illusion.Stanley Coren - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):563-564.
  • Accounting for an old inconsistency in the psychophysics of Plateau and Delboeuf.Marc Brysbaert - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):562-563.
  • Euclid's optics and its compatibility with linear perspective.C. D. Brownson - 1981 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 24 (3):165-194.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Dynamic size constancy.Leonard Brosgole, Daniel G. McNichol, John Doyle & Ann Neylon - 1976 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 7 (1):12-14.
  • Psychophysical scaling: To describe relations or to uncover a law?Gunnar Borg - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):561-562.
  • Psychophysical scaling within an information processing approach?Claude Bonnet - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):560-561.
  • Lockhead's view of scaling: Something's fishy here.Stanley J. Bolanowski - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):560-560.
  • The relation of apparent shape to apparent slant in the perception of objects.Jacob Beck & James J. Gibson - 1955 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 50 (2):125.
  • Integration psychophysics is not traditional psychophysics.Norman H. Anderson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):559-560.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Perception, apperception and psychophysics.Daniel Algom - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):558-559.
  • Art and Ambiguity: A Gestalt-Shift Approach to Elusive Appearances.John O'Dea - 2018 - In Fabian Dorsch & Fiona Macpherson (eds.), Phenomenal Presence. Oxford University Press.
    I defend a solution to a long-standing problem with perceptual appearances, brought about by the phenomenon of perceptual constancy. The problem is that in conditions which are non-ideal, yet within the range that perceptual constancy works, we see things veridically despite an “appearance” which is traditionally taken to be non-veridical. For example, a tilted coin is often taken to have an “elliptical appearance”, shadowed surfaces a “darker appearance”. These appearances are puzzling for a number of reasons. I defend and elaborate (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consciousness and existence as a process.Riccardo Manzotti - 2006 - Mind and Matter 4 (1):7-43.