Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Intelligent Eye

Mcgraw-Hill (1970)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Does connectionism suffice?Steven W. Zucker - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):301-302.
  • Vision as Bayesian inference: analysis by synthesis?Alan Yuille & Daniel Kersten - 2006 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10 (7):301-308.
  • Hybrid Truths and Emotion in Film.Robert J. Yanal - 2010 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 34 (1):180-189.
  • To what extent do beliefs affect apparent motion?Richard D. Wright & Michael R. W. Dawson - 1994 - Philosophical Psychology 7 (4):471-491.
    A number of studies in the apparent motion literature were examined using the cognitive penetrability criterion to determine the extent to which beliefs affect the perception of apparent motion. It was found that the interaction between the perceptual processes mediating apparent motion and higher order processes appears to be limited. In addition, perceptual and inferential beliefs appear to have different effects on perceived motion optimality and direction. Our findings suggest that the system underlying apparent motion perception has more than one (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Comparative cognition of spatial representation.Donald M. Wilkie & Robert J. Wilison - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):97-98.
  • Cross-cultural research needs crossfertilisation.Peter Wenderoth - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):97-97.
  • Perceptions in perspective.R. A. Weale - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):96-97.
  • Relation of sensory scales to physical scales.Richard M. Warren - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):586-587.
  • Keeping the bath water along with the baby: Context effects represent a challenge, not a mortal wound, to the body of psychophysics.Mark Wagner - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):585-586.
  • Cross-cultural research in perception: The missing theoretical perspective.Fons J. R. van de Vijver & Ype H. Poortinga - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):95-96.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ceteris paribus laws.J. van Brakel - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):584-585.
  • Do we scale “objects” or isolated sensory dimensions?Michel Treisman - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):581-584.
  • Cultural determination of picture space: The acid test.E. Broydrick Thro - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):94-95.
  • Selecting one attribute for judgment is not an act of stupidity.Robert Teghtsoonian - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):580-581.
  • Folk psychology: Simulation or tacit theory?Stephen Stich & Shaun Nichols - 1992 - Mind and Language 7 (1-2):35-71.
    A central goal of contemporary cognitive science is the explanation of cognitive abilities or capacities. [Cummins 1983] During the last three decades a wide range of cognitive capacities have been subjected to careful empirical scrutiny. The adult's ability to produce and comprehend natural language sentences and the child's capacity to acquire a natural language were among the first to be explored. [Chomsky 1965, Fodor, Bever & Garrett 1974, Pinker 1989] There is also a rich literature on the ability to solve (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • Controlled versus automatic processing.Robert J. Sternberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):32-33.
  • Whither cross-cultural perception?Daniel W. Smothergill - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):93-94.
  • Prolegomena to an understanding of play.John Shotter - 1973 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 3 (1):47–89.
  • Evolutionary theory meets cognitive psychology: A more selective perspective.Lawrence Shapiro & William Epstein - 1998 - Mind and Language 13 (2):171-94.
    Quite unexpectedly, cognitive psychologists find their field intimately connected to a whole new intellectual landscape that had previously seemed remote, unfamiliar, and all but irrelevant. Yet the proliferating connections tying together the cognitive and evolutionary communities promise to transform both fields, with each supplying necessary principles, methods, and a species of rigor that the other lacks. (Cosmides and Tooby, 1994, p. 85).
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Lexicon as module.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):31-32.
  • Top-down influences on ambiguous perception: the role of stable and transient states of the observer.Lisa Scocchia, Matteo Valsecchi & Jochen Triesch - 2014 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
  • Should the psychophysical model be rejected?Bruce Schneider - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):579-580.
  • Organic insight into mental organs.Barry Schwartz - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):30-31.
  • Luminance controls the perceived 3-D structure of dynamic 2-D displays.Barry J. Schwartz & George Sperling - 1983 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 21 (6):456-458.
  • Encapsulation and expectation.Roger Schank & Larry Hunter - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):29-30.
  • A rapprochement of biology, psychology, and philosophy.Sandra Scarr - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):29-29.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation of Posterior Parietal Cortex Modulates Line-Length Estimation but Not Illusory Depth Perception.Adriana Salatino, Gaetana Chillemi, Federica Gontero, Marisa Poncini, Maria Pyasik, Anna Berti & Raffaella Ricci - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perception as hypothesis testing.Timothy A. Salthouse & Warren L. Danziger - 1978 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 11 (3):197-199.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Dimensionality of Visual Space.William H. Rosar - 2016 - Topoi 35 (2):531-570.
    The empirical study of visual space has centered on determining its geometry, whether it is a perspective projection, flat or curved, Euclidean or non-Euclidean, whereas the topology of space consists of those properties that remain invariant under stretching but not tearing. For that reason distance is a property not preserved in topological space whereas the property of spatial order is preserved. Specifically the topological properties of dimensionality, orientability, continuity, and connectivity define “real” space as studied by physics and are the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Many a slip 'twixt external and internal representation.David Rose - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):93-93.
  • Objectification and vision: how images shape our early visual processes.Alice Roberts - 2021 - Synthese 32 (1-2).
    Objectification involves treating someone as a thing. The role of images in perpetuating objectification has been discussed by feminist philosophers. However, the precise effect that images have on an individual's visual system is seldom explored. Kathleen Stock’s work is an exception—she describes certain images of women as causing viewers to develop an objectifying ‘gestalt’ which is then projected onto real-life women. However, she doesn’t specify the level of visual processing at which objectification occurs. In this paper, I propose that images (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Faculties, modules, and computers.Daniel N. Robinson - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):28-29.
  • On computer science, visual science, and the physiological utility of models.Barry J. Richmond & Michael E. Goldberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):300-301.
  • How Philosophy Lost Perceptual Expertise.Joel Richeimer - 2000 - Synthese 124 (3):385-406.
    If we think of perceptual expertise, we might think ofa neurologist interpreting a CAT scan or an astronomerlooking at a star. But perceptual expertise is notlimited to ‘experts’. Perceptual expertise is atthe heart of our everyday competence in the world. Wenavigate around obstacles, we take turns inconversations, we make left-turns in face of on-comingtraffic. Each of us is a perceptual expert (thoughonly in certain domains). If we misunderstandperceptual expertise, we risk misunderstanding ourepistemic relationship to the world. I argue that thestandard (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Quinity, isotropy, and Wagnerian rapture.Georges Rey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):27-28.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A psychological definition of illusion.Robert I. Reynolds - 1988 - Philosophical Psychology 1 (2):217-223.
    The psychological concept of illusion is defined as a process involving an interaction of logical and empirical considerations. Common usage suggests that an illusion is a discrepancy between one's awareness and some stimulus. Following preliminary definitions of classes of stimuli, five definitions of illusion are considered, based upon the possible discrepancies between awareness and a stimulus. It is found that each of these definitions fails to make important distinctions, even to the point of equating all illusory and perceptual phenomena. This (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intentionality of Phenomenology in Brentano.Matjaž Potrč - 2002 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (S1):231-267.
    Phenomenology is intrinsically intentional for Brentano. Qualitative conscious experiences are individuated by their phenomenal space. Examples concerning the phenomenal take account of both experiential and physical spaces. As directedness at an object and reflexive directedness of the act at itself come interwoven, there is the intrinsic phenomenology of intentionality. Both intentionality of phenomenology and phenomenology of intentionality present the wholes with mutually pervading and only logically distinguishable parts. The above theses establish balance between phenomenology and intentionality, a balance disrupted in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Popper's severity of test as an intuitive probabilistic model of hypothesis testing.Fenna H. Poletiek - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (1):99-100.
    Severity of Test (SoT) is an alternative to Popper's logical falsification that solves a number of problems of the logical view. It was presented by Popper himself in 1963. SoT is a less sophisticated probabilistic model of hypothesis testing than Oaksford & Chater's (O&C's) information gain model, but it has a number of striking similarities. Moreover, it captures the intuition of everyday hypothesis testing.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pictures, maybe; illusions, no.Robert H. Pollack - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):92-93.
  • Plea for more exploration of cross-cultural cognitive space.David Piggins - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):91-92.
  • Artworks as dichotomous objects: implications for the scientific study of aesthetic experience.Robert Pepperell - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9.
  • The archaeology of space: Real and representational.Christopher S. Peebles - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):91-91.
  • Computational Neuropsychology and Bayesian Inference.Thomas Parr, Geraint Rees & Karl J. Friston - 2018 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 12.
  • Visual Switching: The Illusion of Instantaneity and Visual Search.Nicoletta Orlandi - 2012 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 3 (4):469-480.
    This paper questions two prima facie plausible claims concerning switching in the presence of ambiguous figures. The first is the claim that reversing is an instantaneous process. The second is the claim that the ability to reverse demonstrates the interpretive, inferential and constructive nature of visual processing. Empirical studies show that optical and cerebral events related to switching protract in time in a way that clashes with its perceived instantaneity. The studies further suggest an alternative theory of reversing: according to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Predictive perceptual systems.Nico Orlandi - 2018 - Synthese 195 (6):2367-2386.
    This article attempts to clarify the commitments of a predictive coding approach to perception. After summarizing predictive coding theory, the article addresses two questions. Is a predictive coding perceptual system also a Bayesian system? Is it a Kantian system? The article shows that the answer to these questions is negative.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Embedded seeing-as: Multi-stable visual perception without interpretation.Nicoletta Orlandi - 2012 - Philosophical Psychology 25 (4):1-19.
    Standard models of visual perception hold that vision is an inferential or interpretative process. Such models are said to be superior to competing, non-inferential views in explanatory power. In particular, they are said to be capable of explaining a number of otherwise mysterious, visual phenomena such as multi-stable perception. Multi-stable perception paradigmatically occurs in the presence of ambiguous figures, single images that can give rise to two or more distinct percepts. Different interpretations are said to produce the different percepts. In (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Embedded Seeing: Vision in the Natural World.Nicoletta Orlandi - 2011 - Noûs 47 (4):727-747.
  • Ambiguous figures and representationalism.Nicoletta Orlandi - 2011 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 10 (3):307-323.
    Ambiguous figures pose a problem for representationalists, particularly for representationalists who believe that the content of perceptual experience is non-conceptual (MacPherson in Nous 40(1):82–117, 2006). This is because, in viewing ambiguous figures, subjects have perceptual experiences that differ in phenomenal properties without differing in non-conceptual content. In this paper, I argue that ambiguous figures pose no problem for non-conceptual representationalists. I argue that aspect shifts do not presuppose or require the possession of sophisticated conceptual resources and that, although viewing ambiguous (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Are sensory properties represented in perceptual experience?Nicoletta Orlandi - 2010 - Philosophical Psychology 23 (6):721-740.
    Philosophers of perception widely agree that sensory properties, like color, are represented in perceptual experience. Arguments are usually needed to establish that something other than sensory properties, for example three-dimensional objects or kind properties, are part of perceptual content. Call the idea that sensory properties are represented in perceptual experience the Sensation View (SV). Given its widespread acceptance, we may expect to find strong reasons for holding SV. In this paper, I argue that we lack such reasons: SV is largely (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reliable computation in parallel networks.Keith Oatley - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):299-299.