Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique

Berkeley: University of California Press (1984)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology.Herman Cappelen, Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.) - 2016 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    This is the most comprehensive book ever published on philosophical methodology. A team of thirty-eight of the world's leading philosophers present original essays on various aspects of how philosophy should be and is done. The first part is devoted to broad traditions and approaches to philosophical methodology. The entries in the second part address topics in philosophical methodology, such as intuitions, conceptual analysis, and transcendental arguments. The third part of the book is devoted to essays about the interconnections between philosophy (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Computers Are Syntax All the Way Down: Reply to Bozşahin.William J. Rapaport - 2019 - Minds and Machines 29 (2):227-237.
    A response to a recent critique by Cem Bozşahin of the theory of syntactic semantics as it applies to Helen Keller, and some applications of the theory to the philosophy of computer science.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Psychoanalytic Facts as Unintended Institutional Facts.Filip Buekens & Maarten Boudry - 2012 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 42 (2):239-269.
    We present an inference to the best explanation of the immense cultural success of Freudian psychoanalysis as a hermeneutic method. We argue that an account of psychoanalytic facts as products of unintended declarative speech acts explains this phenomenon. Our argument connects diverse, seemingly independent characteristics of psychoanalysis that have been independently confirmed, and applies key features of John Searle’s and Eerik Lagerspetz’s theory of institutional facts to the psychoanalytic edifice. We conclude with a brief defence of the institutional approach against (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Future of the Past: From the History of Historiography to Historiology.Alexandre Grandazzi - 1990 - Diogenes 38 (151):51-74.
    The history of historiography, in other words the history of history, is in vogue. In the realm of Classical Antiquity (whence speaks the author of this essay), but elsewhere as well, increasing numbers of pioneers set out each day to explore this new path of history.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward the Development of a Superordinate Epistemology for Clinical Psychology: A Critique and a Proposal.Elyse Morgan - 1989 - Dissertation, University of Colorado at Boulder
    This dissertation addresses the problem of how to evaluate and compare the theories that inform diverse approaches to psychotherapy. It is argued that the field needs a superordinate epistemology to provide legitimacy for its theories and for the clinical work that these theories guide. Such a superordinate epistemology would occupy a higher level of analysis than the theories it is used to evaluate. ;Using a constructivist framework, it is argued that much of the epistemological confusion currently characterizing clinical psychology can (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Escape, Fromm, Freedom: The Refutability of Historical Interpretations in the Popperian Perspective.Slava Sadovnikov - 2004 - Dialogue 43 (2):239-280.
    RésuméJe me penche sur un aspect de la philosophie sociale de Popper, à savoir les principes d'évaluation des interprétations historiques. Ma thèse globale est que suivant la perspective poppèrienne, notre choix parmi des interprétations historiques doit user d'au moins deux des critères qu'applique Popper au choix parmi diverses théories scientifiques : une interprétation devrait logiquement se prêter à une réfutation et elle devrait être consistante. Afin de montrer la pertinence et la fécondité de cette approche, je me concentre sur l'interprétation (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Agency and Mistakes.Santiago Amaya - 2022 - In Luca Ferrero (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Agency. New York, NY: Routledge. pp. 149-150.
    This is a draft of my chapter on Agency and Mistakes for the Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Agency. In it, I focus on performance mistakes and distinguish them from other "derivative" mistakes that we make as agents. I argue that a proper understanding of these mistakes recommends a generalized fallibilism about human agency.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychopathy: Morally Incapacitated Persons.Heidi Maibom - 2017 - In Thomas Schramme & Steven Edwards (eds.), Handbook of the Philosophy of Medicine. Springer. pp. 1109-1129.
    After describing the disorder of psychopathy, I examine the theories and the evidence concerning the psychopaths’ deficient moral capacities. I first examine whether or not psychopaths can pass tests of moral knowledge. Most of the evidence suggests that they can. If there is a lack of moral understanding, then it has to be due to an incapacity that affects not their declarative knowledge of moral norms, but their deeper understanding of them. I then examine two suggestions: it is their deficient (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Hermeneutics and psychoanalysis.Robert L. Woolfolk - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):265-266.
  • The epistemological roots of ecclesiastical claims to knowledge.Gereon Wolters - 2009 - Axiomathes 19 (4):481-508.
    In theoretical matters, ecclesiastical claims to knowledge have lead to various conflicts with science. Claims in orientational matters, sometimes connected to attempts to establish them as a rule for legislation, have often been in conflict with the justified claims of non-believers. In addition they violate the Principle of Autonomy of the individual, which is at the very heart of European identity so decisively shaped by the Enlightenment. The Principle of Autonomy implies that state legislation should not interfere in the life (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Psychoanalysis: Conventional wisdom, self knowledge, or inexact science.Murray L. Wax - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):264-265.
  • Early Freud, late Freud, conflict and intentionality.Paul L. Wachtel - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):263-264.
  • Two kinds of autism: a comparison of distinct understandings of psychiatric disease.Berend Verhoeff - 2016 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 19 (1):111-123.
    In this article, I argue that the history and philosophy of autism need to account for two kinds of autism. Contemporary autism research and practice is structured, directed and connected by an ‘ontological understanding of disease’. This implies that autism is understood as a disease like any other medical disease, existing independently of its particular manifestations in individual patients. In contrast, autism in the 1950s and 1960s was structured by a psychoanalytical framework and an ‘individual understanding of disease’. This implied (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ethogenic theory and psychoanalysis: The unconscious as a social construction and a failed explanatory concept.Charles R. Varela - 1995 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 25 (4):363–385.
  • Biological structure and embodied human agency: The problem of instinctivism.Charles R. Varela - 2003 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 33 (1):95–122.
    Hebb's conception of instinctive behavior permits the conclusion that it is just not human nature to be instinctive: while the ant brain is built for instinctive behavior, the human brain is built for intelligent behavior. Since drives cannot be instincts, even when a human driver becomes driven, human motives are not instincts either. This understanding allows us to dismiss the determinism of the old instinctivism found in Freud's bio-psychological unconscious, and of the new instinctivism, exemplified by Wilson's sociobiology. The latter (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Debate between Grunbaum and Ricoeur: The Hermeneutic Conception of Psychoanalysis and the Drive for Scientific Legitimacy.Gregory A. Trotter - 2016 - Études Ricoeuriennes / Ricoeur Studies 7 (1):103-119.
    Paul Ricœur’s hermeneutic approach to psychoanalysis stresses the interpretation of meanings revealed via the narratives woven through the discursive exchanges between analyst and analysand. Despite the tremendous influence Ricœur’s interpretation enjoyed both in philosophy and in psychoanalysis, his approach has been subject to severe criticism by Adolf Grünbaum who argues that Freud modeled psychoanalysis on the natural sciences, and therefore it should be judged according to natural scientific standards. I argue that Grünbaum incorrectly downplays the importance of speech and language (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Interdisciplinary methodology: The case of Kitcher's Freud.M. Tjiattas - 2001 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 32 (3):535-555.
    The guiding idea of Patricia Kitcher's Freud's Dream is that the use of interdisciplinary methodology accounts at the same time for the most central features of Freud's theory of the mind and for its most serious shortcomings. Kitcher proposes to provide an account of Freud's theory that illuminates its interdisciplinary underpinnings. While she indisputably succeeds in providing a subtle and rich reconstruction of Freud's work, her attempt to show up the limitations of interdisciplinary studies does not work. The value of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Interdisciplinary Methodology: The Case of Kitcher's Freud.Mary Tjiattas - 2001 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 32 (3):535-555.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The truthfulness of psychoanalysis.Fredrik Svenaeus - 2000 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 21 (4):355-360.
    This paper is a review article of Elyn R. Saks's book "Interpreting Interpretation: The Limits of Hermeneutic Psychoanalysis" published in 1999. In the article Saks's approach is criticized for lacking a proper background understanding of hermeneutics and its place in psychoanalysis. Psychoanalysis, whether we name it hermeneutic or not, will always deal with both meanings and causes. The role of hermeneutics in psychoanalysis can, thus, not be to get rid of the metapsychology of the unconscious altogether, but rather to stress (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Grünbaum, homosexuality, and contemporary psychoanalysis.Frederick Suppe - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):261-262.
  • Transference: One of Freud's basic discoveries.Hans H. Strupp - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):260-261.
  • Human understanding and scientific validation.Anthony Storr - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):259-260.
  • The Social Psychology of “Pseudoscience”: A Brief History.Arthur Still & Windy Dryden - 2004 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 34 (3):265-290.
    The word ‘pseudoscience’ is a marker of changing worries about science and being a scientist. It played an important role in the philosophical debate on demarcating science from other activities, and was used in popular writings to distance science from cranky theories with scientific pretensions. These uses consolidated a comforting unity in science, a communal space from which pseudoscience is excluded, and the user's right to belong is asserted. The urgency of this process dwindled when attempts to find a formal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Processing of a Subliminal Rebus during Sleep: Idiosyncratic Primary versus Secondary Process Associations upon Awakening from REM- versus Non-REM-Sleep.Jana Steinig, Ariane Bazan, Svenja Happe, Sarah Antonetti & Howard Shevrin - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Primary and secondary processes are the foundational axes of the Freudian mental apparatus: one horizontally as a tendency to associate, the primary process, and one vertically as the ability for perspective taking, the secondary process. Primary process mentation is not only supposed to be dominant in the unconscious but also, for example, in dreams. The present study tests the hypothesis that the mental activity during REM-sleep has more characteristics of the primary process, while during non-REM-sleep more secondary process operations take (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are free associations necessarily contaminated?Donald P. Spence - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):259-259.
  • Subliminal unconscious conflict alpha power inhibits supraliminal conscious symptom experience.Howard Shevrin, Michael Snodgrass, Linda A. W. Brakel, Ramesh Kushwaha, Natalia L. Kalaida & Ariane Bazan - 2013 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7.
    Our approach is based on a tri-partite method of integrating psychodynamic hypotheses, cognitive subliminal processes, and psychophysiological alpha power measures. We present ten social phobic subjects with three individually selected groups of words representing unconscious conflict, conscious symptom experience, and Osgood Semantic negative valence words used as a control word group. The unconscious conflict and conscious symptom words, presented subliminally and supraliminally, act as primes preceding the conscious symptom and control words presented as supraliminal targets. With alpha power as a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • An argument for the evidential standing of psychoanalytic data.Howard Shevrin - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):257-259.
  • Some epistemological concerns about dissociative identity disorder and diagnostic practices in psychology.Michael J. Shaffer & Jeffery S. Oakley - 2005 - Philosophical Psychology 18 (1):1-29.
    In this paper we argue that dissociative identity disorder (DID) is best interpreted as a causal model of a (possible) post-traumatic psychological process, as a mechanical model of an abnormal psychological condition. From this perspective we examine and criticize the evidential status of DID, and we demonstrate that there is really no good reason to believe that anyone has ever suffered from DID so understood. This is so because the proponents of DID violate basic methodological principles of good causal modeling. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Misconceptions of the social sciences.Robert A. Segal - 1990 - Zygon 25 (3):263-278.
    Scholars in religious studies, or “religionists,” often mischaracterize the social‐scientific study of religion. They assume that a social‐scientific analysis of the origin, function, meaning, or truth of religion either opposes or disregards the believer's analysis, which religionists profess to present and defend. I do not argue that the social sciences analyze religion from the believer's point of view. I argue instead that a social scientific analysis is more akin and germane to the believer's point of view than religionists assume. I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Can we define mental disorder by using the criterion of mental dysfunction?Thomas Schramme - 2010 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 31 (1):35-47.
    The concept of mental disorder is often defined by reference to the notion of mental dysfunction, which is in line with how the concept of disease in somatic medicine is often defined. However, the notions of mental function and dysfunction seem to suffer from some problems that do not affect models of physiological function. Functions in general have a teleological structure; they are effects of traits that are supposed to have a particular purpose, such that, for example, the heart serves (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Classical realism, Freud and human nature in international relations.Robert Schuett - 2010 - History of the Human Sciences 23 (2):21-46.
    Classical realism is enjoying a renaissance in the study of international relations. It is well known that the analytical and normative international-political thought of early 20th-century classical realists is based on assumptions about human nature. Yet current knowledge of these assumptions remains limited. This article therefore revisits and examines the nature and intellectual roots of the human nature assumptions of three truly consequential classical realists. The analysis shows — similar to the causa Hans J. Morgenthau — that the human nature (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Some gaps in Grünbaum's critique of psychoanalysis.Irwin Savodnik - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):257-257.
  • Beyond medical ethics: New directions for philosophy and medicine.Raphael Sassower & Michael A. Grodin - 1988 - Journal of Medical Humanities and Bioethics 9 (2):121-134.
    A unique relationship exists between physicians and philosophers — one that expands on the constructive potential of the liaison between physicians and, for example, theologians, on the one hand, or, social workers on the other. This liaison should focus in the scientific aspects of medicine, not just the ethical aspects. Philosophers can provide physicians with a perspective on both the philosophy and the history of medicine through the ages — a sense of how medicine has adapted to the social cultural (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Grünbaum on psychoanalysis: Where do we go from here?Michael Ruse - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):256-257.
  • Testability and candor.Sherrilyn Roush - 2005 - Synthese 145 (2):233 - 275.
    On analogy with testimony, I define a notion of a scientific theory’s lacking or having candor, in a testing situation, according to whether the theory under test is probabilistically relevant to the processes in the test procedures, and thereby to the reliability of test outcomes. I argue that this property identifies what is distinctive about those theories that Karl Popper denounced as exhibiting “reinforced dogmatism” through their self-protective behavior (e.g., psychoanalysis, Hegelianism, Marxism). I explore whether lack of candor interferes with (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Financial interests and research bias.David B. Resnik - 2000 - Perspectives on Science 8 (3):255-285.
    : In the last two decades, scientists, government officials, and science policy experts have expressed concerns about the increasing role of financial interests in research. Many believe that these interests are undermining research by causing bias and error, suppression of results, and even outright fraud. This paper seeks to shed some light on this view by (1) explicating the concept research bias, (2) describing some ways that financial interests can cause research biases, and (3) discussing some strategies for mitigating or (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Legalism, Countertransference, and Clinical Moral Perception.Christy A. Rentmeester & Constance George - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (10):20-28.
    This target article focuses on dynamics that arise in three typical ethically complex cases in which psychiatric consultations are requested by physicians: a dying patient refuses life-prolonging treatment, an uncooperative patient demands to be allowed to go outside and smoke, and an angry patient demands to be admitted to the hospital. The discussion canvasses what is at stake morally and clinically in each of these cases and explores clinician–patient interactions, dynamics in relationships between consulting physicians and consultant psychiatrists, patient transference, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Grünbaum's critique of clinical psychoanalytic evidence: A sheep in wolf's clothing?Morton F. Reiser - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):255-256.
  • The commodification of knowledge about knowledge: Knowledge management and the reification of epistemology.Tomas Hellström & Sujatha Raman - 2001 - Social Epistemology 15 (3):139-154.
  • Tallying the “tally argument”: What next?Sam S. Rakover - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):727-729.
  • Outflanking the mind-body problem: Scientific progress in the history of psychology.Sam S. Rakover - 1992 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 22 (2):145–173.
  • Predicting overt behavior versus predicting hidden states.Karl Popper - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):254-255.
  • Is there a “two-cultures” model for psychoanalysis?George H. Pollock - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):253-254.
  • Freud's phylogenetic fantasy: An essay review. [REVIEW]Thomas Parisi - 1989 - Biology and Philosophy 4 (4):483-494.
  • The persistence of the “exegetical myth”.Alessandro Pagnini - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):252-252.
  • Must a hermeneutical psychoanalysis exclude science?Paul O'Grady, Paul Rigby & John Van Den Hengel - 1995 - Man and World 28 (2):115-128.
  • Is Freudian psychoanalytic theory really falsifiable?Mark A. Notturno & Paul R. McHugh - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):250-252.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The status of Popper's theory of scientific method.Robert Nola - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (4):441-480.
  • That obscure object of psychoanalysis.Dany Nobus - 2013 - Continental Philosophy Review 46 (2):163-187.
    This essay examines how psychoanalytic conceptions of the subject and the object in the works of Freud and Lacan may contribute to a re-examination of the vexed issue of the subject–object relationship in science, philosophy and epistemology. For Freud, the ego is the essential subject, yet he regarded it as an always already objectified subject, which is objectively thinkable yet never subjectively knowable qua subject. Lacan conceptualised this Freudian principle of subjectivity with his notion of the divided (barred) subject, which (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book Reviews : Adolf Grunbaum, Validation in the Clinical Theory of Psychoanalysis: A Study in the Philosophy of Psychoanalysis. International University Press, Madison, WI, Comm., 1993. Pp. xxii, 414. $50.00. [REVIEW]Nathaniel Laor - 1996 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 26 (3):432-435.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark