Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. John Dewey, Myrtle McGraw and Logic: An unusual collaboration in the 1930s.Thomas C. Dalton & Victor W. Bergenn - 1996 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 27 (1):69-107.
  • Kant’s Crucial Contribution to Euler Diagrams.Jens Lemanski - 2024 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 55 (1):59–78.
    Logic diagrams have been increasingly studied and applied for a few decades, not only in logic, but also in many other fields of science. The history of logic diagrams is an important subject, as many current systems and applications of logic diagrams are based on historical predecessors. While traditional histories of logic diagrams cite pioneers such as Leibniz, Euler, Venn, and Peirce, it is not widely known that Kant and the early Kantians in Germany and England played a crucial role (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Contextualizing Hegel's Phenomenology of the French Revolution and the Terror.Robert Wokler - 1998 - Political Theory 26 (1):33-55.
  • Spirituality in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: An analysis in the wake of Foucault.Ariën Voogt - 2021 - Metaphilosophy 52 (5):616-627.
    Ancient philosophy is often distinguished from modern philosophy regarding its affinity to spirituality. In antiquity, philosophy meant a way of life rather than a body of knowledge. Yet according to Michel Foucault, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit constitutes an important exception to modern philosophy’s break with spirituality, as it integrates structures of spirituality into modern forms and ideals of philosophy. This article builds on Foucault’s analysis by revealing the structures of spirituality that are present within the Phenomenology of Spirit. It argues (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Syllogistic reasoning as a ground for the content of judgment: A line of thought from Kant through Hegel to Peirce.Preston Stovall - 2021 - European Journal of Philosophy 29 (4):864-886.
    European Journal of Philosophy, Volume 29, Issue 4, Page 864-886, December 2021.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hegel and formal idealism.Manish Oza - forthcoming - Hegel Bulletin:1-25.
    I offer a new reconstruction of Hegel’s criticism of Kant’s idealism. Kant held that we impose categorial form on experience, while sensation provides its matter. Hegel argues that the matter we receive cannot guide our imposition of form on it. Contra recent interpretations, Hegel’s argument does not depend on a conceptualist account of perception or a view of the categories as empirically conditioned. His objection is that given Kant’s dualistic metaphysics, the categories cannot have material conditions for correct application. This (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teaching Literature as Aberrant Science.John K. Noyes - 2003 - Diogenes 50 (2):55-64.
    To be a teacher of literature at a university today is to occupy a problematic position in the production and codification of knowledge - a fact that has generated a great deal of critical comment in recent years. But this position in its problematic dimensions is not necessarily new. The teacher of literature has always been a propagator of an aberrant science - yet a science that in its aberrations has more to do with the methodological problems of the natural (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Liberal Naturalism: The Curious Case of Hegel.Paul Giladi - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (2):248-270.
    My aim in this paper is to defend the claim that the absolute idealism of Hegel is a liberal naturalist position against Sebastian Gardner’s claim that it is not genuinely naturalistic, and also to defend the position of ‘liberal naturalism’ from Ram Neta’s charge that there is no logical space for it to occupy. By ‘liberal naturalism’, I mean a doctrine which is a non-reductive form of philosophical naturalism. Like Fred Beiser, I take the thesis of liberal naturalism to find (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Immanence in Schelling and Hegel in the Jena Period.Paolo Diego Bubbio & Daniele Fulvi - 2022 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 60 (3):353-387.
    In this article, we argue that in the Jena period (1801–1803) Schelling and Hegel both rejected the conception of God as coinciding with the moral order, which they attribute to Fichte; such coincidence, in their view, turned God into a transcendent and merely moral Being. In an effort to demonstrate their distance from Fichte's view, we contend, Schelling and Hegel advocated for a metaphysical (rather than merely moral) and immanent (rather than transcendent) understanding of God, conceived in its inextricable relation (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Patriotism as Freedom and the Law: Hegel as Read by Robespierre.Eduardo Baker - 2023 - Philosophia 51 (3):1063-1092.
    Patriotism is not commonly associated with freedom. Even less so when Hegel is evoked. By reading Hegel’s concept of patriotism through the lens of revolutionary France, I present a notion of patriotism that is tied to the realization of freedom. This paper demonstrates what happens when Hegel’s philosophy of law is re-read through the political philosophy of the French Revolution itself. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right and its lectures are marked by tensions. The legacy it leaves traces it leaves behind can (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark