Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. John Stuart Mill's Famous Distinction Between Production and Distribution.Vardaman R. Smith - 1985 - Economics and Philosophy 1 (2):267-284.
    In the final sentence of the "Preliminary Remarks" to the Principles of Political Economy, John Stuart Mill declaresThe laws of Production and Distribution, and some of the practical consequences deducible from them, are the subject of the following treatise. It is almost two hundred pages before Mill asserts thatThe laws and conditions of the Production of wealth partake of the character of physical truths. There is nothing optional or arbitrary in them. … It is not so with the Distribution of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What an economist can teach Nancy Cartwright.Esther-Mirjam Sent - 1996 - Social Epistemology 10 (2):171 – 192.
  • John Stuart Mill and Concepts of Nature.Margaret Schabas - 1995 - Dialogue 34 (3):447-.
    Why did Mill draw such a firm line between nature and society, and what did he mean by the claim that only permanent or necessary truths could be gleaned in nature? Why are the laws of production able to transcend the social realm and thereby attain a higher epistemological standing? Was Mill the first to make this distinction, or does it conform with a long tradition within the history of economic thought?
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An anomaly for Laudan's pragmatic model.Margaret Schabas - 1987 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 18 (1):43-52.
  • The Modal View and Defending Microeconomics.Steven Rappaport - 1986 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 (1):289-297.
    What Daniel Hausman has called “the simple criticism of economic theory”1 is succinctly conveyed by the following passage: “We know full well not only that commodities are not infinitely divisible (which is only intended as a simplification), but businessmen do not always attempt to maximize profits and that the preferences of consumers are not always transitive. ‘Businessmen maximize profits’ and ‘a consumer’s preferences are transitive’ are fundamental economic ‘laws’. How can economists rationally accept a theory which is so full of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • John Stuart Mills liberaler Marktsozialismus: bisheriges Scheitern und bleibende Relevanz.Christian Neuhäuser - 2018 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 66 (3):295-320.
    John Stuart Mill had strong sympathies with a liberal form of market socialism based on worker-owned and worker-managed firms. He thought that only very few government interventions were needed to trigger a peaceful and spontaneous transition to such an economic system. This article recapitulates his thesis and argument by focusing on his major workPrinciples of Political Economy, which is rather neglected by philosophers, especially in the German-speaking world. I will argue that Mill was too optimistic in his hope for a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Universals and the methodenstreit: a re-examination of Carl Menger's conception of economics as an exact science.Uskali Mäki - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 28 (3):475-495.
    In the latter half of the 19th century, economic thought in the Germanspeaking world was dominated, both intellectually and academically, by the so-called historical school, from Wilhelm Roscher to Gustav Schmoller and others. In 1871, the Austrian Carl Menger published his Grun&tze der Volkswirtschaftslehre (Menger, 1976 (1871)), customarily referred to as one of the three simultaneous discoveries of marginalist economics-the other two marginalist ‘revolutionaries’ being Jevons in England and Walras in France. Twelve years later, in 1883, Menger published a major (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On the scope and limits of generalizations in the social sciences.Daniel Little - 1993 - Synthese 97 (2):183 - 207.
    This article disputes the common view that social science explanations depend on discovery of lawlike generalizations from which descriptions of social outcomes can be derived. It distinguishes between governing and phenomenal regularities, and argues that social regularities are phenomenal rather than governing. In place of nomological deductive arguments, the article maintains that social explanations depend on the discovery of causal mechanisms underlying various social processes. The metaphysical correlate of this argument is that there are no social kinds: types of social (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Economic Modelling as Robustness Analysis.Jaakko Kuorikoski, Aki Lehtinen & Caterina Marchionni - 2010 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61 (3):541-567.
    We claim that the process of theoretical model refinement in economics is best characterised as robustness analysis: the systematic examination of the robustness of modelling results with respect to particular modelling assumptions. We argue that this practise has epistemic value by extending William Wimsatt's account of robustness analysis as triangulation via independent means of determination. For economists robustness analysis is a crucial methodological strategy because their models are often based on idealisations and abstractions, and it is usually difficult to tell (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Mill's unrevised philosophy of economics: A comment on Hausman.Neil de Marchi - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (1):89-100.
    Hausman has argued that Mill in the Logic demands verification of qualified, inexact statements if they are to be considered lawlike. This puts Mill in line with a reasonable interpretation of what modern microeconomists are about, but requires the additional hypothesis that Mill abandoned his earlier stress on modal truth in his 1836 essay on the method of economics. The paper maintains that neither textual nor contextual evidence supports this hypothesis. Moreover, it is superfluous if one attends carefully to how (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Deductive Method.Daniel M. Hausman - 1990 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1):372-388.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Plausibility in Economics.Bart Nooteboom - 1986 - Economics and Philosophy 2 (2):197.
    According to the instrumentalism of Friedman and Machlup it is irrelevant whether the explanatory principles or “assumptions” of a theory satisfy any criterion of “plausibility,” “realism,” “credibility,” or “soundness.” In this view the main or only criterion for selecting theories is whether a theory yields empirically testable implications that turn out to be consistent with observations. All we should require or expect from a theory is that it is a useful instrument for the purpose of prediction. Considerations of the “efficiency” (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Causalité, explication scientifique et théorie économique.Thomas Ferretti - 2011 - Ithaque 8:17-40.
    Le modèle déductivo-nomologique domine depuis longtemps la réflexion philosophique concernant l’explication en science économique. Or, pour plusieurs, comme James Woodward et Tony Lawson, ce modèle ne considère pas suffisamment la causalité dans l’explication. L’objectif de cet article est double : 1- renforcer la critique que Tony Lawson adresse à l’économie contemporaine et 2- évaluer la théorie alternative qu’il propose, le « réalisme critique », qui tente de réintroduire la causalité dans l’explication en science économique. Nous conclurons que les considérations causales (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Od Misese k Schutzovi. Otázka apriorismu v ekonomii.Petr Špecián - 2012 - Politická Ekonomie 60 (3):395--410.
    The study analyzes Mises‘s approach to the question of apriorism in a broader methodological context. It shows that it is not inevitable to advocate the aprioristic character of economics (resp. science of human action), as Mises does, to maintain the subjectivist-individualist methodology and the effort to adequately grasp the general laws of human action from its perspective. The present redefinition of apriorism is developed on the basis of thoughts of Barry Smith and Alfred Schutz. It suggests abandoning the apodictic character (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation