Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. No State A Priori Known to Be Factive is Mental.Elia Zardini - 2016 - Philosophical Issues 26 (1):462-492.
  • Dynamics of Epistemic Modality.Malte Willer - 2013 - Philosophical Review 122 (1):45-92.
    A dynamic semantics for epistemically modalized sentences is an attractive alternative to the orthodox view that our best theory of meaning ascribes to such sentences truth-conditions relative to what is known. This essay demonstrates that a dynamic theory about might and must offers elegant explanations of a range of puzzling observations about epistemic modals. The first part of the story offers a unifying treatment of disputes about epistemic modality and disputes about matters of fact while at the same time avoiding (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Du Châtelet’s Libertarianism.Aaron Wells - 2022 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 38 (3):219-241.
    There is a growing consensus that Emilie Du Châtelet’s challenging essay “On Freedom” defends compatibilism. I offer an alternative, libertarian reading of the essay. I lay out the prima facie textual evidence for such a reading. I also explain how apparently compatibilist remarks in “On Freedom” can be read as aspects of a sophisticated type of libertarianism that rejects blind or arbitrary choice. To this end, I consider the historical context of Du Châtelet’s essay, and especially the dialectic between various (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Must . . . stay . . . strong!Kai von Fintel & Anthony S. Gillies - 2010 - Natural Language Semantics 18 (4):351-383.
    It is a recurring mantra that epistemic must creates a statement that is weaker than the corresponding flat-footed assertion: It must be raining vs. It’s raining. Contrary to classic discussions of the phenomenon such as by Karttunen, Kratzer, and Veltman, we argue that instead of having a weak semantics, must presupposes the presence of an indirect inference or deduction rather than of a direct observation. This is independent of the strength of the claim being made. Epistemic must is therefore quite (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Dynamics of reason and the Kantian project.Maarten Van Dyck - 2009 - Philosophy of Science 76 (5):689-700.
    I show why Michael Friedman’s idea that we should view new constitutive frameworks introduced in paradigm change as members of a convergent series introduces an uncomfortable tension in his views. It cannot be justified on realist grounds, as this would compromise his Kantian perspective, but his own appeal to a Kantian regulative ideal of reason cannot do the job either. I then explain a way to make better sense of the rationality of paradigm change on what I take to be (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Truth, Judgment and Speculative Logic.Ioannis D. Trisokkas - 2008 - Hegel Bulletin 29 (1-2):154-172.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lotze on Comparison and the Unity of Consciousness.Mark Textor - 2022 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 52 (5):556-572.
    Hermann Lotze argued that the fact that consciousness simultaneously “holds objects together as well as apart” such that they can be compared implies (a) that there is a simple thinker and (b) that consciousness is an ‘indivisible unity.’ I offer a reconstruction and evaluation of Lotze’s Argument from Comparison. I contend that it does not deliver (a) but makes a good case for (b). I will relate Lotze’s argument to the contemporary debate between “top-down” and “bottom-up” views of the unity (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Preliminary to Concept of the Ontology in Kant’s Critical Philosophy.Vitali Terletsky - 2013 - Sententiae 28 (1):30-41.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Novum in veteri. J. Hintikka about Euclidean Origins of Kant’s Mathematical Method.Vitali Terletsky - 2015 - Sententiae 33 (2):75-92.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Boundaries and Possibilities of the Constellation Research Method.Vitali Terletsky - 2016 - Sententiae 34 (1):169-178.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unconditionality of the «I».Jürgen Stolzenberg - 2014 - Sententiae 31 (2):6-8.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nietzsche and Schiller on Aesthetic Semblance.Timothy Stoll - 2019 - The Monist 102 (3):331-348.
    Nietzsche consistently valorizes artistic falsehoods. On standard interpretations, this is because art provides deceptive yet salutary fictions that help us affirm life. This reading conflicts, however, with Nietzsche’s insistence that life-affirmation requires untrammeled honesty. I present an alternative interpretation which navigates the interpretive impasse. With special attention to the influence of Friedrich Schiller, the paper argues for three claims: (1) Nietzsche does not hold that art is false because it “beautifies,” but because it produces mere semblances of, its objects; (2) (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Fichte’s Proposition «I am».Jürgen Stolzenberg - 2014 - Sententiae 31 (2):52-74.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The True Self. Critique, Nature, and Method.Terje Sparby, Friedrich Edelhäuser & Ulrich W. Weger - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Innate a nd Learned: Carey, Mad Dog Nativism, and the Poverty of Stimuli and Analogies.Georges Rey - 2014 - Mind and Language 29 (2):109-132.
    In her recent (2009) book, The Origins of Concepts, Susan Carey argues that what she calls ‘Quinean Bootstrapping’ and processes of analogy in children show that the expressive power of a mind can be increased in ways that refute Jerry Fodor's (1975, 2008) ‘Mad Dog’ view that all concepts are innate. I argue that it is doubtful any evidence about the manifestation of concepts in children will bear upon the logico-semantic issues of expressive power. Analogy and bootstrapping may be ways (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Education and Autonomy.Sebastian Rödl - 2016 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 50 (1):84-97.
    In his book The Formation of Reason (2011), David Bakhurst asserts that the end of education is autonomy, which he explains is the power to determine what to do.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Kant's two priorities of practical reason.Frederick Rauscher - 1998 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 6 (3):397 – 419.
    I find in Kant two distinct conceptions of the priority of practical over theoretical reason, focused on belief and on action. The former actually involves a higher priority of theoretical reason. The latter, in contrast, gives genuine priority to practical reason by noting that theoretical considerations are irrelevant in moral decision-making. I argue that the former conception requires one to abandon genuine priority of the practical, while the latter conception requires one to abandon the necessary unity of reason. I also (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Patterns, Patterns, Patterns: Art and Meaning at the Crossroads between Two Opposing Forces.Olga Ramirez Calle - 2020 - Theoria (2):220-244.
    This article aims to defend the need to recognize the independent role of those cognitive abilities on whose behalf linguistic meaning is introduced from the proper institution of language. I call this capacity “private pattern recognition” (PPR) and argue that it plays an essential part not just in the instauration of linguistic meaning but also in other relevant cognitive phenomena such as artistic creation and understanding. Moreover, it is precisely the failure to separate both aspects that gives rise to important (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophie pour le monde et sagesse hors du monde : les limites de la revendication éclectique chez Christian Thomasius.Arnaud Pelletier - 2018 - Dialogue 57 (4):695-717.
    Christian Thomasius claims for himself the label of ‘eclectic philosopher.’ This claim first regards the emancipation of reason from any other authority, which not only allows him to claim new juridical rights but also to determine philosophy as awisdom-for-the-world. This claim is, however, narrowed by both the limits of scholastic knowledge and the undue generalizations Thomasius finds in it. The claim is intended to make room for belief, and for a faith purified of all philosophical-theological confusion, i.e., for awisdom-outside-the-world.Despite being (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reconsidering the ignorabimus: du Bois-Reymond and the hard problem of consciousness.Paolo Pecere - 2020 - Science in Context 33 (1):1-18.
    ArgumentIn this paper I present an interpretation of du Bois-Reymond’s thesis on the impossibility of a scientific explanation of consciousness and of its present importance. I reconsider du Bois-Reymond’s speech “On the limits of natural science” in the context of nineteenth-century German philosophy and neurophysiology, pointing out connections and analogies with contemporary arguments on the “hard problem of consciousness.” Du Bois-Reymond’s position turns out to be grounded on an epistemological argument and characterized by a metaphysical skepticism, motivated by the unfruitful (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant: on the Way to Understanding the Spiritual Nature of Man.A. O. Osypov - 2023 - Anthropological Measurements of Philosophical Research 24:118-134.
    _Purpose._ The main purpose of the study is to examine Kant’s first experience in creating a methodology for determining the holistic, spiritual nature of man, firstly, in terms of identifying the range of phenomena that should be included in the analysis of the spiritual essence of man, and secondly, this experience may be indicative for identifying dead ends in the research of spirituality of modern philosophers. _Theoretical__ basis._ The study is based on the methodology of philosophical anthropology formulated by M. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Event of Primary Experience and Philosophy. Metatheory of Experience in Kant and Quine’s Epistemologies.Mykhailo Minakov - 2015 - Sententiae 33 (2):64-74.
    The author argues that Quine’s criticism of Kantian analytical/synthetic distinction, as well as transcendentalist reductionism, is not entirely adequate. Furthermore, the author states that Kant’s and Quine’s theories of experience and cognition (transcendentalist and holistic) are based on a common dogma, the one of consistency. Taking into account their uncritical ac-ceptance of experience as a system that is able to adjust new and old elements to each other, both philosophers have much more in common than Quine and his followers might (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From Tubal Cain to Faraday: William Whewell as a philosopher of technology.Joost Mertens - 2000 - History of Science 38 (3):321-342.
  • Representing and Embodying a Peripheral City’s Place in the World.Tea Lobo - 2022 - Journal of Aesthetics and Phenomenology 8 (1):55-69.
    In an increasingly globalizing world, the aesthetics of Dubai have become potentially available even for impoverished, peripheral cities such as Belgrade. With the explicit rhetoric of finally achi...
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • De la indeterminación y el discurso. Interpretación de la teoría aristotélica de la ousía como ontología apotropaica.Jaime Llorente - 2011 - Endoxa 28:47.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant on conic sections.Alison Laywine - 2014 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44 (5-6):719-758.
    This paper tries to make sense of Kant's scattered remarks about conic sections to see what light they shed on his philosophy of mathematics. It proceeds by confronting his remarks with the source that seems to have informed his thinking about conic sections: the Conica of Apollonius. The paper raises questions about Kant's attitude towards mathematics and the way he understood the cognitive resources available to us to do mathematics.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Significance of Philosophical Anthropology in Determining the Methodology of Modern Scientific Research.O. N. Kubalskyi - 2023 - Anthropological Measurements of Philosophical Research 24:37-45.
    _Purpose._ This research involves revealing the methodological significance of the anthropological understanding of values for conducting modern scientific research. _Theoretical basis._ Philosophical anthropology acts as an epistemological basis for answers to ontological questions that are part of the structure of such problems in modern science as the construction of a scientific picture of the world, the ordering of data of natural attitude, and anthropocosmism. The ontological basis for the formation of the anthropological theory of values is the teaching of Wilhelm (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dangerous epistemology.Pablos Kubes - 2022 - E-Logos 29 (1):19-31.
    Epistemologie a kognitivní věda se zabývají studiem procesů poznání. Z výsledků takového bádání vyplývají určité diagnostické a preskriptivní závěry s cílem pozitivně regulovat způsob myšlení. Předložená práce má za cíl ukázat, že epistemické a kognitivní studie nejsou doposud dostatečně vyvinuté, aby mohly kategoricky doporučit správný a universální způsob myšlení. Pokrok ve vědě je výsledek kolektivního úsilí nejen současnosti, ale i minulých objevů a omylů. Na historickém případě chybné teorie flogistonu se tato práce bude snažit doložit, že se na objevení pravdy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Concept of the “I” in Fichte’s Explanation of Substantiality.Christian Klotz - 2014 - Sententiae 31 (2):75-86.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dedekind's Logicism†.Ansten Mørch Klev - 2015 - Philosophia Mathematica 25 (3):341-368.
    A detailed argument is provided for the thesis that Dedekind was a logicist about arithmetic. The rules of inference employed in Dedekind's construction of arithmetic are, by his lights, all purely logical in character, and the definitions are all explicit; even the definition of the natural numbers as the abstract type of simply infinite systems can be seen to be explicit. The primitive concepts of the construction are logical in their being intrinsically tied to the functioning of the understanding.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The broken mirror. J. G. Fichte’s “The science of knowledge of 1804 2 ” as an attempt of non-reflexive theory of self-consciousness and its influence on Heidelberg School. [REVIEW]Ivan Ivashchenko - 2012 - Sententiae 26 (1):28-68.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • New Science of the Civil World. An Analytical-Historical Commentary on Giovanni Battista Vico’s "Idea of the Work". Part One.Ivan Ivashchenko - 2017 - Sententiae 36 (1):152-165.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Giovanni Gentile’s Actualism.Ivan Ivashchenko - 2014 - Sententiae 30 (1):80-93.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Helmholtz's naturalized conception of geometry and his spatial theory of signs.David Jalal Hyder - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (3):286.
    I analyze the two main theses of Helmholtz's "The Applicability of the Axioms to the Physical World," in which he argued that the axioms of Euclidean geometry are not, as his neo-Kantian opponents had argued, binding on any experience of the external world. This required two argumentative steps: 1) a new account of the structure of our representations which was consistent both with the experience of our (for him) Euclidean world and with experience of a non-Euclidean one, and 2) a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Building A General Theory of Meta‐Argumentation.Hasmik Hovhannisyan & Robert Djidjian - 2017 - Metaphilosophy 48 (3):345-354.
    This article presents a critical analysis of the main modern approaches to the problem of meta-argumentation and suggests a method for developing a general conception of meta-argumentation. A set of theoretical-methodological difficulties along this path is revealed. Overcoming these aporias would constitute the main steps toward developing the body of a theory of meta-argumentation.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Moral Argument for the Existence of God and Immortality.Roe Fremstedal - 2013 - Journal of Religious Ethics 41 (1):50-78.
    This essay tries to show that there exist several passages where Kierkegaard (and his pseudonyms) sketches an argument for the existence of God and immortality that is remarkably similar to Kant's so-called moral argument for the existence of God and immortality. In particular, Kierkegaard appears to follow Kant's moral argument both when it comes to the form and content of the argument as well as some of its terminology. The essay concludes that several passages in Kierkegaard overlap significantly with Kant's (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kant's Table of Judgments and the Doctrine of the Judgment in the German Logic of XVIIIth Century.Yurij Fedorchenko - 2015 - Sententiae 32 (1):47-59.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paradox or contradiction? [REVIEW]John J. Drummond - 2002 - Human Studies 25 (1):89-102.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reconsidering Kant, Friedman, logical positivism, and the exact sciences.Robert DiSalle - 2002 - Philosophy of Science 69 (2):191-211.
    This essay considers the nature of conceptual frameworks in science, and suggests a reconsideration of the role played by philosophy in radical conceptual change. On Kuhn's view of conceptual conflict, the scientist's appeal to philosophical principles is an obvious symptom of incommensurability; philosophical preferences are merely “subjective factors” that play a part in the “necessarily circular” arguments that scientists offer for their own conceptual commitments. Recent work by Friedman has persuasively challenged this view, revealing the roles that philosophical concerns have (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Peut-on fonder l’arithmetique sur la logique pure? La controverse entre Natorp et Rickert.Arnaud Dewalque - 2007 - Dialogue 46 (1):43-68.
    RÉSUMÉ: Dans cet article, j’entreprends de clarifier le projet (frégéen) d’une logique de l’arithmétique -- tel qu’il a été discuté par Natorp et Rickert -- en distinguant trois questions directrices. Le nombre est-il un objet logique? L’arithmétique est-elle réductible à la logique? Est-il possible de déduire les opérations arithmétiques de lois purement logiques? Ma thèse est que la distinction rigoureuse de ces trois questions permet de lever une grande partie des obscurités qui affectent en généralle programme d’une logique de l’arithmétique. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant's Theory of Musical Sound: An Early Exercise in Cognitive Science.Robert E. Butts - 1993 - Dialogue 32 (1):3-.
    Kant is well known as the philosopher who spent his life hunting for a prioris, philosophically identifiable characteristics of the make-up of human beings. These characteristics are species-universal, and are necessary presuppositions of the possibility of the success of various kinds of cognitive and cultural strategies. Kant bagged some big game. Space, time and the categories are a priori conditions of the possibility of human cognition. God, freedom and immortality are a priori conditions of the possibility of morality. The sensus (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Alternative Modes Of Thought.Peter Burke - 2022 - Common Knowledge 28 (1):41-60.
    This essay—a contribution to the Common Knowledge symposium on contextualism—is concerned with the gradual rise of awareness of the existence of modes of thought or systems of belief that are different from those that are dominant in one's own culture. The awareness can be found in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries but was developed further in the early to mid-twentieth century. Its main consequence has been to encourage individuals to distance themselves from their own system—to criticize and change it.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Philosophic sur ordinateur ou intelligence artificielle.Gilbert Boss & Maryvonne Longeart - 1993 - Dialogue 32 (2):271-.
    L'informatique se définissant comme le traitement rationnel de l'information par machine automatique et l'intelligence se caractérisant par une même capacité de traitement rationnel, il était inévitable que l'on songe à associer l'intelligence au traitement automatique de l'information. C'est ce qu'a fait John McCarthy en forgeant le terme d'intelligence artificielle. Par «intelligence artificielle» on peut vouloir exprimer l'ambition de1. Recréer, transformer ou développer l'intelligence artificiellement2. Simuler l'intelligence en la reconstituant dans des modéles imitant certains aspects de notre intelligence dite naturelle.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The transzendenz of mathematical 'experience'.William Boos - 1998 - Synthese 114 (1):49-98.
  • Analytic/synthetic: Sharpening a philosophical tool.Johan van Benthem - 1984 - Theoria 50 (2-3):106-137.
  • Analyticity and Syntheticity in Type Theory Revisited.Bruno Bentzen - forthcoming - Review of Symbolic Logic:1-27.
    I discuss problems with Martin-Löf's distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments in constructive type theory and propose a revision of his views. I maintain that a judgment is analytic when its correctness follows exclusively from the evaluation of the expressions occurring in it. I argue that Martin-Löf's claim that all judgments of the forms a : A and a = b : A are analytic is unfounded. As I shall show, when A evaluates to a dependent function type (x : (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant, Neo‐Kantians, and Transcendental Subjectivity.Charlotte Baumann - 2017 - European Journal of Philosophy 25 (3):595-616.
    This article discusses an interpretation of Kant's conception of transcendental subjectivity, which manages to avoid many of the concerns that have been raised by analytic interpreters over this doctrine. It is an interpretation put forward by selected C19 and early C20 neo-Kantian writers. The article starts out by offering a neo-Kantian interpretation of the object as something that is constituted by the categories and that serves as a standard of truth within a theory of judgment. The second part explicates transcendental (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations