Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Freedom in the Body: The Physical, the Causal, and the Possibility of Choice.Michael L. Spezio - 2004 - Zygon 39 (3):577-590.
    . In Minding God Gregory Peterson takes a careful look at the kind of freedom that human persons have. He concludes that humans are constrained to be free and unpacks this into a version of compatibilism. That is, humans are not metaphysically free under current existence because of the causal determination inherent in their physical nature, but they can take credit for the origination of selfforming decisions because the causes occur inside of us. Peterson does advocate an eschatological hope looking (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Early knowledge of object motion: continuity and inertia.Elizabeth S. Spelke, Gary Katz, Susan E. Purcell, Sheryl M. Ehrlich & Karen Breinlinger - 1994 - Cognition 51 (2):131-176.
  • The somatic mutation theory of cancer: growing problems with the paradigm?Ana M. Soto & Carlos Sonnenschein - 2004 - Bioessays 26 (10):1097-1107.
    The somatic mutation theory has been the prevailing paradigm in cancer research for the last 50 years. Its premises are: (1) cancer is derived from a single somatic cell that has accumulated multiple DNA mutations, (2) the default state of cell proliferation in metazoa is quiescence, and (3) cancer is a disease of cell proliferation caused by mutations in genes that control proliferation and the cell cycle. From this compelling simplicity, an increasingly complicated picture has emerged as more than 100 (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • And yet another epicycle.Carlos Sonnenschein & Ana M. Soto - 2006 - Bioessays 28 (1):100-101.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Stance and strategy: post‐structural perspective and post‐colonial engagement to develop nursing knowledge.Anne M. Sochan - 2011 - Nursing Philosophy 12 (3):177-190.
    How should nursing knowledge advance? This exploration contextualizes its evolution past and present. In addressing how it evolved in the past, a probable historical evolution of its development draws on the perspectives of Frank & Gills's World System Theory, Kuhn's treatise on Scientific Revolutions, and Foucault's notions of Discontinuities in scientific knowledge development. By describing plausible scenarios of how nursing knowledge evolved, I create a case for why nursing knowledge developers should adopt a post‐structural stance in prioritizing their research agenda(s). (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Why and How Do I Write the History of Science?Roger Smith - 2013 - Science in Context 26 (4):611-625.
    I make a large claim for the intellectual and institutional centrality of the history of science as critical reason. The reality on the ground, of course, does not always exhibit this. I trace the vicissitudes of my own way of thought in relation to developments in the field, leading to an interest, first, in relating intellectual history (with its philosophical orientation) to mainstream (evidence based) history, and second, to finding a place for the human sciences in the history of science. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The homunculus at home.J. David Smith - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):697-698.
    In Gray's conjecture, mismatches in the subicular comparator and matches have equal prominence in consciousness. In rival cognitive views novelty and difficulty especially elicit more conscious modes of cognition and higher levels of self-regulation. The mismatch between Gray's conjecture and these views is discussed.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Nature and Sources of Practical Necessity.Ted J. Smith - 1980 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 10 (4):379-396.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is There Progress in Philosophy? The Case for Taking History Seriously.Peter P. Slezak - 2018 - Philosophy 93 (4):529-555.
    In response to widespread doubts among professional philosophers (Russell, Horwich, Dietrich, McGinn, Chalmers), Stoljar argues for a ‘reasonable optimism’ about progress in philosophy. He defends the large and surprising claim that ‘there is progress on all or reasonably many of the big questions.’ However, Stoljar’s caveats and admitted avoidance of historical evidence permits overlooking persistent controversies in philosophy of mind and cognitive science that are essentially unchanged since the 17th Century. Stoljar suggests that his claims are commonplace in philosophy departments (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Reflective Reasoning in Groups.Christina Slade - 1995 - Informal Logic 17 (2).
    The conception of reflective reasoning, like that of higher order thinking, has been informed by a Cartesian view of the self. Reflection is conceived of as a solipsistic process, in which persons consider their own thoughts in isolation. Higher order thinking has equally been represented as a single thinker considering thoughts at a meta-level. This paper proposes a different conception of reflection and higher order thinking, in which reflective dialogue is seen as the fundamental context in which reflection is possible (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Listening to Quackery: Reading John Wesley’s Primitive Physic in an Age of Health Care Reform.Daniel Skinner & Adam Schneider - 2019 - Journal of Medical Humanities 40 (1):69-83.
    This article uses a reading of John Wesley's Primitive Physic, or An Easy and Natural Method of Curing Most Diseases (1747) to resist the common rejection—often as "quackery"—of Wesley's treatments for common maladies. We engage Wesley not because he was right but because his approach offers useful moments of pause in light of contemporary medical epistemology. Wesley's recommendations were primarily oriented towards the categories of personal responsibility and capability, but he also sought to empower individuals—especially the poor—with the knowledge to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A success story or an old wives' tale? On judging experiments in evolutionary computation.Moshe Sipper - 2000 - Complexity 5 (4):31-33.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Individual differences, developmental changes, and social context.Dean Keith Simonton - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):552-553.
  • The end is near!: The phenomenon of the declaration of closure in a discipline.Arthur M. Silverstein - 1999 - History of Science 37 (118):407-425.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Objectivity, rationality, incommensurability, and more. [REVIEW]Harvey Siegel - 1980 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (4):359-375.
  • The Place of Ethics in Business.Jon M. Shepard, Jon Shepard, James C. Wimbush & Carroll U. Stephens - 1995 - Business Ethics Quarterly 5 (3):577-601.
    This article uses concepts from sociology, history, and philosophy to explore the shifting relationship between moral values and business in the Western world. We examine the historical roots and intellectual underpinnings of two major business-society paradigms in ideal-type terms. In pre-industrial Western society, we argue that business activity was linked to society’s values of morality (the moral unity paradigm}-for good or for ill. With the rise of industrialism, we contend that business was freed from moral constraints by the alleged “invisible (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Place of Ethics in Business.Jon M. Shepard, Jon Shepard, James C. Wimbush & Carroll U. Stephens - 1995 - Business Ethics Quarterly 5 (3):577-601.
    This article uses concepts from sociology, history, and philosophy to explore the shifting relationship between moral values and business in the Western world. We examine the historical roots and intellectual underpinnings of two major business-society paradigms in ideal-type terms. In pre-industrial Western society, we argue that business activity was linked to society’s values of morality (the moral unity paradigm}-for good or for ill. With the rise of industrialism, we contend that business was freed from moral constraints by the alleged “invisible (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Truth and Scientific Change.Gila Sher - 2017 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 48 (3):371-394.
    The paper seeks to answer two new questions about truth and scientific change: What lessons does the phenomenon of scientific change teach us about the nature of truth? What light do recent developments in the theory of truth, incorporating these lessons, throw on problems arising from the prevalence of scientific change, specifically, the problem of pessimistic meta-induction?
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Respecting the phenomenology of human creativity.Victor A. Shames & John F. Kihlstrom - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):551-552.
  • Consciousness beyond the comparator.Victor A. Shames & Timothy L. Hubbard - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):697-697.
    Gray's comparator model fails to provide an adequate explanation of consciousness for two reasons. First, it is based on a narrow definition of consciousness that excludes basic phenomenology and active functions of consciousness. Second, match/mismatch decisions can be made without producing an experience of consciousness. The model thus violates the sufficiency criterion.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bacteria are small but not stupid: Cognition, natural genetic engineering and socio-bacteriology.J. A. Shapiro - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 38 (4):807-819.
    Forty years’ experience as a bacterial geneticist has taught me that bacteria possess many cognitive, computational and evolutionary capabilities unimaginable in the first six decades of the twentieth century. Analysis of cellular processes such as metabolism, regulation of protein synthesis, and DNA repair established that bacteria continually monitor their external and internal environments and compute functional outputs based on information provided by their sensory apparatus. Studies of genetic recombination, lysogeny, antibiotic resistance and my own work on transposable elements revealed multiple (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Politics of Theory and the Constitution of Meaning.Peeter Selg - 2013 - Sociological Theory 31 (1):1-23.
    How should sociologists use the word theory? Gabriel Abend’s recent insistence that this question should be tackled politically raises two important issues: Is sociology political? And if so, what normative implications follow for its organization? Drawing on Wittgenstein’s notion of family resemblance and post-Gramscian theories of hegemony, I argue that Abend’s proposal that semantic questions about theory can be addressed separately from ontological, evaluative, and teleological ones is untenable. Disagreements about the latter are constitutive, not merely supplementary to the meaning (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Nasr Hamid Abu Zayd and the foundation of his hermeneutics: A critical review of the attitude that the Quran is the product of culture.Halilović Seid - 2017 - Kom: Časopis Za Religijske Nauke 6 (1):33–53.
    In the cognitive stage of religious traditions, science, in the light of the authority of religious revelation and reason, was dominant in relation to culture, which means that it was possible to determine the true value of different cultures using scientific knowledge. Nowadays, the completely opposite approach is gaining in popularity. Namely, when they discovered the fundamental weaknesses of empiristic definition of science, postmodern philosophers started more vocally saying that culture actually has a crucial influence on the method and internal (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lexicon as module.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):31-32.
  • Filosofia em um novo século.John Searle & Felipe Sousa - 2009 - Filosofia Unisinos 10 (2):203-220.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Referee report on an earlier draft of Peters and Ceci's target article.William A. Scott - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):238-238.
  • The history of semiconductor electronics — A kuhnian story?Joop Schopman - 1981 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (2):297-302.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The future of a discipline: Considering the ontological/methodological future of the anthropology of consciousness, part I.Mark A. Schroll - 2010 - Anthropology of Consciousness 21 (1):1-29.
    Calling for an expanded framework of EuroAmerican science's methodology whose perspective acknowledges both quantitative/etic and qualitative/emic orientations is the broad focus of this article. More specifically this article argues that our understanding of shamanic and/or other related states of consciousness has been greatly enhanced through ethnographic methods, yet in their present form these methods fail to provide the means to fully comprehend these states. They fail, or are limited, because this approach is only a “cognitive interpretation” or “metanarrative” of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Causal Map and Moral Psychology.Timothy Schroeder - 2016 - Philosophical Quarterly 67 (267):347-369.
    Some philosophers hold that the neuroscience of action is, in practice or in principle, incapable of touching debates in action theory and moral psychology. The role of desires in action, the existence of basic actions, and the like are topics that must be sorted out by philosophers alone: at least at present, and perhaps by the very nature of the questions. This paper examines both philosophical and empirical arguments against the relevance of neuroscience to such questions and argues that neither (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Should the psychophysical model be rejected?Bruce Schneider - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):579-580.
  • Sociobiology's bully pulpit: Romancing the gene.Glendon Schubert - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):749-750.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Patterns of abduction.Gerhard Schurz - 2008 - Synthese 164 (2):201-234.
    This article describes abductions as special patterns of inference to the best explanation whose structure determines a particularly promising abductive conjecture and thus serves as an abductive search strategy. A classification of different patterns of abduction is provided which intends to be as complete as possible. An important distinction is that between selective abductions, which choose an optimal candidate from given multitude of possible explanations, and creative abductions, which introduce new theoretical models or concepts. While selective abduction has dominated the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Participant observation and the discovery of meaning.Gary Schwartz & Don Merten - 1971 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 1 (2):279-298.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Organic insight into mental organs.Barry Schwartz - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):30-31.
  • Lyotard, Postmodernism and Science Education: A Rejoinder To Zembylas.Roland M. Schulz - 2007 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 39 (6):633-656.
    Although postmodernist thought has become prominent in some educational circles, its influence on science education has until recently been rather minor. This paper examines the proposal of Michalinos Zembylas, published earlier in this journal, that Lyotardian postmodernism should be applied to science educational reform in order to achieve the much sought after positive transformation. As a preliminary to this examination several critical points are raised about Lyotard's philosophy of education and philosophy of science which serve to challenge and undermine Zembylas’ (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Encapsulation and expectation.Roger Schank & Larry Hunter - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):29-30.
  • Editorial.Robert Schweitzer - 2002 - Indo-Pacific Journal of Phenomenology 2 (1):1-3.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Discussion. What to believe and what to take seriously: A reply to David chart concerning the Riddle of induction.O. Schulte - 2000 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (1):151-153.
    In his commentary on my paper, “Means-Ends Epistemology”, David Chart constructs a Riddle of Induction with the following feature: Means-ends analysis, as I formulated it in the paper, selects “all emeralds are grue” as the optimal conjecture after observing a sample of all green emeralds. Chart’s construction is rigorous and correct. If we disagree, it is in the philosophical morals to be drawn from his example. Such morals are best discussed by elucidating some of the larger epistemological issues involved. “Means-ends (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Defusing eliminative materialism: Reference and revision.Maurice K. D. Schouten & Huib Looren de Jong - 1998 - Philosophical Psychology 11 (4):489-509.
    The doctrine of eliminative materialism holds that belief-desire psychology is massively referentially disconnected. We claim, however, that it is not at all obvious what it means to be referentially (dis)connected. The two major accounts of reference both lead to serious difficulties for eliminativism: it seems that elimination is either impossible or omnipresent. We explore the idea that reference fixation is a much more local, partial, and context-dependent process than was supposed by the classical accounts. This pragmatic view suggests that elimination (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Conceptual Metaphors and Mathematical Practice: On Cognitive Studies of Historical Developments in Mathematics.Dirk Schlimm - 2013 - Topics in Cognitive Science 5 (2):283-298.
    This article looks at recent work in cognitive science on mathematical cognition from the perspective of history and philosophy of mathematical practice. The discussion is focused on the work of Lakoff and Núñez, because this is the first comprehensive account of mathematical cognition that also addresses advanced mathematics and its history. Building on a distinction between mathematics as it is presented in textbooks and as it presents itself to the researcher, it is argued that the focus of cognitive analyses of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Communication and consciousness: A neural network conjecture.N. A. Schmajuk & E. Axelrad - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):695-696.
    The communicative aspects of the contents of consciousness are analyzed in the framework of a neural network model of animal communication. We discuss some issues raised by Gray, such as the control of the contents of consciousness, the adaptive value of consciousness, conscious and unconscious behaviors, and the nature of a model's consciousness.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Phenomenological Study of Dream Interpretation Among the Xhosa-Speaking People in Rural South Africa.Robert Schweitzer - 1996 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 27 (1):72-96.
    Psychologists investigating dreams in non-Western cultures have generally not considered the meanings of dreams within the unique meaning-structure of the person in his or her societal context. The study was concerned with explicating the indigenous system of dream interpretation of the Xhosa-speaking people, as revealed by acknowledged dream experts, and elaborating upon the life-world of the participants. Fifty dreams and their interpretations were collected from participants, who were traditional healers and their clients. A phenomenological methodology was adopted in explicating the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • An anomaly for Laudan's pragmatic model.Margaret Schabas - 1987 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 18 (1):43-52.
  • Anosmic peer review: A rose by another name is evidently not a rose.Sandra Scarr - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):237-238.
  • A rapprochement of biology, psychology, and philosophy.Sandra Scarr - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):29-29.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Importance of Concepts.Sarah Sawyer - 2018 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 118 (2):127-147.
    Words change meaning over time. Some meaning shift is accompanied by a corresponding change in subject matter; some meaning shift is not. In this paper I argue that an account of linguistic meaning can accommodate the first kind of case, but that a theory of concepts is required to accommodate the second. Where there is stability of subject matter through linguistic change, it is concepts that provide the stability. The stability provided by concepts allows for genuine disagreement and ameliorative change (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Foundations of interdisciplinarity: A Lonergan perspective. [REVIEW]Russell J. Sawa - 2004 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 8 (1):53-61.
    The postmodern enterprise, with its foundationlessness, fragmentariness, constructivism, and neopragmatism challenges interdisciplinarity. This paper discusses functional specialization and interdisciplinary method which provides a basis for interdisciplinary collaboration. In functional specialization, successive stages in the process of coming to know are distinguished. These stages correspond to Lonergan’s four levels of consciousness, namely experiencing the data, coming to understanding through addressing questions which arise from the data, and judgment about which hypothesis best fits the data. Authenticity, which involves genuine attentiveness, intelligence, reasonableness, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Structure of Scientific Theories, edited and with a critical introduction by Frederick Suppe.Steven F. Savitt - 1977 - Dialogue 16 (2):328-345.
    This volume is the record of a symposium on the structer of scientific theories held in urbana, Illinois in the spring of 1969. ofSeven main papers, commentaries, discussions, and a postscript form the bulk of the book. The rest is a nearly 240-page monograph-in-the-guise-of-an-introduction by the editor titled “The Search for Philosophic Understanding of Scientific Theories”.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy, theory and science of politics.Giovanni Sartori - 1974 - Political Theory 2 (2):133-162.
  • The Profession and the Killer App, or What Environmental Ethicists Might Learn from Bioethics: A Commentary.Per Sandin - 2015 - Ethics, Policy and Environment 18 (3):275-282.
    In terms of output in the form of published work and attraction of resources, bioethics seems to be a more vibrant field than environmental ethics. In this commentary it is argued that bioethics is, in some respect, less humanistic than environmental ethics and that two factors––bioethics’ strong connection to a profession, and its access to an intellectual ‘killer app’––offer ways in which environmental ethicists might learn from the ‘success story’ of bioethics.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark