Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A function for sensory storage: perception of rapid change.J. T. Lindsay Wilson - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):42-43.
  • Quantal basis of iconic dispersion.Gerald S. Wasserman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):40-42.
  • Can you perceive ensembles without perceiving individuals?: The role of statistical perception in determining whether awareness overflows access.Emily J. Ward, Adam Bear & Brian J. Scholl - 2016 - Cognition 152 (C):78-86.
    Do we see more than we can report? Psychologists and philosophers have been hotly debating this question, in part because both possibilities are supported by suggestive evidence. On one hand, phenomena such as inattentional blindness and change blindness suggest that visual awareness is especially sparse. On the other hand, experiments relating to iconic memory suggest that our in-the-moment awareness of the world is much richer than can be reported. Recent research has attempted to resolve this debate by showing that observers (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The sequential pickup of spatial information needs visual memory.A. Vassilev & A. Penchev - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):40-40.
  • Don't exterminate perceptual fruit flies!William R. Uttal - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):39-40.
  • Why we need iconic memory.George Sperling - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):37-39.
  • Found and missed: Failing to recognize a search target despite moving it.Grayden Jf Solman, J. Allan Cheyne & Daniel Smilek - 2012 - Cognition 123 (1):100-118.
  • Change Detection.Ronald A. Rensink - 2002 - Annual Review of Psychology 53 (1):245-277.
    Five aspects of visual change detection are reviewed. The first concerns the concept of change itself, in particular the ways it differs from the related notions of motion and difference. The second involves the various methodological approaches that have been developed to study change detection; it is shown that under a variety of conditions observers are often unable to see large changes directly in their field of view. Next, it is argued that this “change blindness” indicates that focused attention is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Icons, visual buffers, and eye movements.Keith Rayner - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):36-37.
  • Change perception needs sensory storage.W. A. Phillips - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):35-36.
  • A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness.J. Kevin O’Regan & Alva Noë - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (5):883-917.
    Many current neurophysiological, psychophysical, and psychological approaches to vision rest on the idea that when we see, the brain produces an internal representation of the world. The activation of this internal representation is assumed to give rise to the experience of seeing. The problem with this kind of approach is that it leaves unexplained how the existence of such a detailed internal representation might produce visual consciousness. An alternative proposal is made here. We propose that seeing is a way of (...)
    Direct download (16 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   732 citations  
  • The rise and fall of the sensory register.Ulric Neisser - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):35-35.
  • Visual persistence: Just a flash in the scan?Glenn E. Meyer - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):33-34.
  • On the nature of brief visual storage: There never was an icon.D. J. K. Mewhort & B. E. Butler - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):31-33.
  • Icons and iconoclasts.Dominic W. Massaro - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):31-31.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Encoder: A Connectionist Model of How Learning to Visually Encode Fixated Text Images Improves Reading Fluency.Gale L. Martin - 2004 - Psychological Review 111 (3):617-639.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The implications of occlusion for perceiving persistence.William M. Mace & Michael T. Turvey - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):29-31.
  • The icon as visual phenomenon and theoretical construct.Gerald M. Long - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):28-29.
  • Icons no, iconic memory yes.Vincent Di Lollo - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):19-20.
  • The continuing persistence of the icon.Geoffrey R. Loftus - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):28-28.
  • The icon is dead: Long live the icon.Roberta L. Klatzky - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):27-28.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Textons, rapid focal attention shifts, and iconic memory.Bela Julesz - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):25-27.
  • Reports of the icon's impending demise are premature.John Jonides - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):24-25.
  • Optic flow, icons, and memory.Gunnar Johansson - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):23-24.
  • Intentionalism and change blindness.Greg Janzen - 2008 - Philosophia 36 (3):355-366.
    According to reductive intentionalism, the phenomenal character of a conscious experience is constituted by the experience's intentional (or representational) content. The goal of this article is to show that a phenomenon in visual perception called change blindness poses a problem for this doctrine. It is argued, in particular, that phenomenal character is not sensitive, as it should be if reductive intentionalism is correct, to fine-grained variations in content. The standard anti-intentionalist strategy is to adduce putative cases in which phenomenal character (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Distinguishing supraspan from subspan iconic storage.Dennis H. Holding - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):22-23.
  • The dependence of perception on persisting images and “icons”.G. Hauske, W. Wolf & H. Deubel - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):21-22.
  • Word-Initial Letters Influence Fixation Durations during Fluent Reading.Christopher J. Hand, Patrick J. O’Donnell & Sara C. Sereno - 2012 - Frontiers in Psychology 3.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The icon is finally dead.Ralph Norman Haber - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):43-54.
  • The impending demise of the icon: A critique of the concept of iconic storage in visual information processing.Ralph Norman Haber - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):1-11.
  • Iconoclasm avoided: What the single neuron tells the psychologist about the icon.Michael E. Goldberg - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):20-21.
  • Apparent motion and the icon.Ronald A. Finke - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):20-20.
  • Icons: To see or not to see.Stanley Coren - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):18-19.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ecological necessity of iconic memory.Max Coltheart - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):17-18.
  • Iconic storage and saccadic eye movements.Bruce Bridgeman & Melanie Mayer - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):16-17.
  • Icon as visual persistence: Alive and well.Bruno G. Breitmeyer - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):15-16.
  • On “raw perception” of “the stimulus itself”.Robert M. Boynton - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):15-15.
  • Overflow, access, and attention.Ned Block - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6):530-548.
    In this response to 32 commentators, I start by clarifying the overflow argument. I explain why the distinction between generic and specific phenomenology is important and why we are justified in acknowledging specific phenomenology in the overflow experiments. Other issues discussed are the relations among report, cognitive access, and attention; panpsychic disaster; the mesh between psychology and neuroscience; and whether consciousness exists.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Consciousness, Accessibility, and the Mesh between Psychology and Neuroscience.Ned Block - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5):481--548.
    How can we disentangle the neural basis of phenomenal consciousness from the neural machinery of the cognitive access that underlies reports of phenomenal consciousness? We can see the problem in stark form if we ask how we could tell whether representations inside a Fodorian module are phenomenally conscious. The methodology would seem straightforward: find the neural natural kinds that are the basis of phenomenal consciousness in clear cases when subjects are completely confident and we have no reason to doubt their (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   388 citations  
  • Action blindness in response to gradual changes.Bruno Berberian, Stephanie Chambaron-Ginhac & Axel Cleeremans - 2010 - Consciousness and Cognition 19 (1):152-171.
    The goal of this study is to characterize observers’ abilities to detect gradual changes and to explore putative dissociations between conscious experience of change and behavioral adaptation to a changing stimulus. We developed a new experimental paradigm in which, on each trial, participants were shown a dot pattern on the screen. Next, the pattern disappeared and participants had to reproduce it. In some conditions, the target pattern was incrementally rotated over successive trials and participants were either informed or not of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the decay of the icon.William P. Banks - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):14-14.
  • How bad is the icon?Jüri Allik & Tails Bachmann - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):12-13.
  • What is iconic storage good for?Edward H. Adelson - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):11-12.
  • "Consciousness". Selected Bibliography 1970 - 2004.Thomas Metzinger - unknown
    This is a bibliography of books and articles on consciousness in philosophy, cognitive science, and neuroscience over the last 30 years. There are three main sections, devoted to monographs, edited collections of papers, and articles. The first two of these sections are each divided into three subsections containing books in each of the main areas of research. The third section is divided into 12 subsections, with 10 subject headings for philosophical articles along with two additional subsections for articles in cognitive (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • To have seen or not to have seen: A Look at Rensink, O’Regan, and Clark (1997).Ronald A. Rensink - 2018 - Perspectives on Psychological Science 13 (2):230– 235.
    Rensink, O’Regan, and Clark (1997) drew attention to the phenomenon of change blindness, in which even large changes can be difficult to notice if made during the appearance of motion transients elsewhere in the image. This article provides a sketch of the events that inspired that article as well as its subsequent impact on psychological science and on society at large.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the failure to detect changes in scenes across brief interruptions.Ronald A. Rensink, Kevin J. O'Regan & James J. Clark - 2000 - Visual Cognition 7 (1/2/3):127-145.
    When brief blank fields are placed between alternating displays of an original and a modified scene, a striking failure of perception is induced: the changes become extremely difficult to notice, even when they are large, presented repeatedly, and the observer expects them to occur (Rensink, O'Regan, & Clark, 1997). To determine the mechanisms behind this induced "change blindness", four experiments examine its dependence on initial preview and on the nature of the interruptions used. Results support the proposal that representations at (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Seeing, sensing, and scrutinizing.Ronald A. Rensink - 2000 - Vision Research 40:1469-1487.
    Large changes in a scene often become difficult to notice if made during an eye movement, image flicker, movie cut, or other such disturbance. It is argued here that this _change blindness_ can serve as a useful tool to explore various aspects of vision. This argument centers around the proposal that focused attention is needed for the explicit perception of change. Given this, the study of change perception can provide a useful way to determine the nature of visual attention, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • To see or not to see: The need for attention to perceive changes in scenes.Ronald A. Rensink, J. Kevin O'Regan & James J. Clark - 1997 - Psychological Science 8:368-373.
    When looking at a scene, observers feel that they see its entire structure in great detail and can immediately notice any changes in it. However, when brief blank fields are placed between alternating displays of an original and a modified scene, a striking failure of perception is induced: identification of changes becomes extremely difficult, even when changes are large and made repeatedly. Identification is much faster when a verbal cue is provided, showing that poor visibility is not the cause of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   194 citations  
  • Scene perception: What we can learn from visual integration and change detection.Daniel J. Simons, Steve Mitroff & Steve Franconeri - 2003 - In Michael L. Peterson & G. Rhodes (eds.), Perception of Faces, Objects, and Scenes: Analytic and Holistic Processes (335-355). Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark