Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Love Your Patient as Yourself: On Reviving the Broken Heart of American Medical Ethics.Tyler Tate & Joseph Clair - 2023 - Hastings Center Report 53 (2):12-25.
    This article presents a radical claim: American medical ethics is broken, and it needs love to be healed. Due to a unique set of cultural and economic pressures, American medical ethics has adopted a mechanistic mode of ethical reasoning epitomized by the doctrine of principlism. This mode of reasoning divorces clinicians from both their patients and themselves. This results in clinicians who can ace ethics questions on multiple‐choice tests but who fail either to recognize a patient's humanity or to navigate (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A principled and cosmopolitan neuroethics: considerations for international relevance.John R. Shook & James Giordano - 2014 - Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 9:1.
    Neuroethics applies cognitive neuroscience for prescribing alterations to conceptions of self and society, and for prescriptively judging the ethical applications of neurotechnologies. Plentiful normative premises are available to ground such prescriptivity, however prescriptive neuroethics may remain fragmented by social conventions, cultural ideologies, and ethical theories. Herein we offer that an objectively principled neuroethics for international relevance requires a new meta-ethics: understanding how morality works, and how humans manage and improve morality, as objectively based on the brain and social sciences. This (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • James F. Drane: A Liberal Catholic Bioethics. Muenster, DE: Lit Verlag. 2010, 290 Pages.Andrew Papanikitas & Barbara Prainsack - 2011 - Philosophia 39 (4):771-774.
    James F. Drane: A Liberal Catholic Bioethics. Muenster, DE: Lit Verlag. 2010, 290 Pages Content Type Journal Article Category Book Review Pages 771-774 DOI 10.1007/s11406-011-9319-4 Authors Andrew Papanikitas, Department of Education and Professional Studies, King’s College London, Strand Campus, London, WC2R 2LS UK Barbara Prainsack, Kings Institute of Social Science and Public Policy, King’s College London, Strand Campus, London, WC2R 2LS UK Journal Philosophia Online ISSN 1574-9274 Print ISSN 0048-3893 Journal Volume Volume 39 Journal Issue Volume 39, Number 4.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Considering virtue: public health and clinical ethics.Karen M. Meagher - 2011 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17 (5):888-893.
  • Medicine as a Profession: A Hypothetical Imperative in Clinical Ethics.Laurence B. McCullough - 2015 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 40 (1):1-7.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Health-care professionals’ knowledge, attitudes and behaviours relating to patient capacity to consent to treatment.Scott Lamont, Yun-Hee Jeon & Mary Chiarella - 2013 - Nursing Ethics 20 (6):684-707.
    This integrative review aims to provide a synthesis of research findings of health-care professionals’ knowledge, attitudes and behaviours relating to patient capacity to consent to or refuse treatment within the general hospital setting. Search strategies included relevant health databases, hand searching of key journals, ‘snowballing’ and expert recommendations. The review identified various knowledge gaps and attitudinal dispositions of health-care professionals, which influence their behaviours and decision-making in relation to capacity to consent processes. The findings suggest that there is tension between (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Medical Paternalism - Part 1.Daniel Groll - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (3):194-203.
    Medical clinicians – doctors, nurses, nurse practitioners etc. – are charged to act for the good of their patients. But not all ways of acting for a patient's good are on par: some are paternalistic; others are not. What does it mean to act paternalistically, both in general and specifically in a medical context? And when, if ever, is it permissible for a clinician to act paternalistically? -/- This paper deals with the first question, with a special focus on paternalism (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Medical Paternalism – Part 2.Daniel Groll - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (3):194-203.
    Medical clinicians – doctors, nurses, nurse practitioners etc. – are charged to act for the good of their patients. But not all ways of acting for a patient's good are on par: some are paternalistic; others are not. What does it mean to act paternalistically, both in general and specifically in a medical context? And when, if ever, is it permissible for a clinician to act paternalistically? In Medical Paternalism Part 1, I answered the first question. This paper answers the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Power in Practice: Best Interests or Coercive Control?April R. Dworetz & Toby Schonfeld - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (12):62-63.
    The American Journal of Bioethics, Volume 11, Issue 12, Page 62-63, December 2011.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Doctors as appointed fiduciaries: A supplemental model for medical decision-making.Ben Davies & Joshua Parker - 2022 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 31 (1):23-33.
    How should we respond to patients who do not wish to take on the responsibility and burdens of making decisions about their own care? In this paper, we argue that existing models of decision-making in modern healthcare are ill-equipped to cope with such patients and should be supplemented by an “appointed fiduciary” model where decision-making authority is formally transferred to a medical professional. Healthcare decisions are often complex and for patients can come at time of vulnerability. While this does not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Communicating conviction: A pilot study of patient perspectives on guidance during medical decision-making in the United States.Karel-Bart Celie, Allyn Auslander & Stuart Kuschner - forthcoming - Clinical Ethics.
    The COVID-19 pandemic has highlighted the difficult task of balancing access to misinformation with respect for patient decision-making. Due to its innate antagonism, the paradigm of “physician paternalism” versus “patient autonomy” may not adequately capture the clinical relationship. The authors hypothesized that most patients would, in fact, prefer significant physician input as opposed to unopinionated information when making medical decisions. There is a lack of empirical data corroborating this in the United States. To that end, a survey was distributed to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Should physicians tell the truth without taking social complications into account? A striking case.Ercan Avci - 2018 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 21 (1):23-30.
    The principle of respect for autonomy requires informing patients adequately and appropriately about diagnoses, treatments, and prognoses. However, some clinical cases may cause ethical dilemmas regarding telling the truth. Under the existence especially of certain cultural, social, and religious circumstances, disclosing all the relevant information to all pertinent parties might create harmful effects. Even though the virtue of telling the truth is unquestionable, sometimes de facto conditions compel physicians to act paternalistically to protect the patient/patients from imminent dangers. This article, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bioethics Education in Africa: Still Complex Challenges.Cletus T. Andoh - 2013 - Open Journal of Philosophy 3 (4):507.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations