Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Occasions for Making Sense of Sport: Celebrating Morgan’s View.Graham McFee - 2018 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 12 (4):435-452.
    In endorsing a conventionalism about the rules of sport, Morgan fails (according to his critics) to ground the normativity of such rules, especially once the historical specificity of their invention and implementation is granted. But how can normativity be grounded in the contingencies of the sporting practices of particular times and places? In particular, do Morgan’s concerns with dependence on ‘conventions’ flow only from the choice of options apparently on offer: roughly the choice between a realism (to reflect ‘facts of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Audiences Appreciating Dances.Graham McFee - 2019 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 44 (1):92-116.
    Midwest Studies In Philosophy, Volume 44, Issue 1, Page 92-116, December 2019.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Not-So-Beautiful Game.Graham McFee - 2015 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 9 (2):166-181.
    Although football is often referred to as ‘the beautiful game’, to take that idea very seriously — by aestheticizing the target of spectating — is to misunderstand a purposive sport such as football. Yet such a view seems required by Stephen Mumford’s endorsement of the purist spectator, in contrast to the partisan, as attending to ‘… only aesthetic aspects of sport’. But, first, not all non-purposive appreciation is thereby aesthetic appreciation, as Mumford assumes. And, second, while a technical understanding of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Scylla and Charybdis: the purist’s dilemma.Leon Culbertson - 2016 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 10 (2):175-196.
    This paper explores the view that, on Mumford’s account of the purist, to the degree that the purist adopts an aesthetic perspective, he or she doesn’t watch the sport in question, and to the degree that he or she does watch the sport, there is a loss of aesthetic appreciation. The idea that spectators oscillate between partisanship and purism means that the purist is unable to avoid either the Scylla of not actually watching the sport, or the Charybdis of loss (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Perception, Aspects and Explanation: Some Remarks on Moderate Partisanship.Leon Culbertson - 2015 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 9 (2):182-204.
    Modifying a contrast introduced by Dixon, Stephen Mumford distinguishes between ‘partisan’ and ‘purist’ ways of watching sport. Recognising that the extreme partisan and extreme purist positions do not explain the nature of sports spectatorship, Mumford follows Dixon in adopting the idea of moderate partisanship. He outlines three theories of spectatorship designed to address the issue of the relationship between the partisan and the purist ways of viewing sport. The true perception theory regards the moderate fan as able to see the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Meaning and Use: Drama and the Aesthetic.Leon Culbertson - 2020 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 15 (3):349-370.
    This paper considers David Best’s claim that descriptions of events in sport as being ‘dramatic’ or ‘tragic’ employ those terms in a figurative sense, along with Stephen Mumford’s rejection of that...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logic, Rules and Intention: The Principal Aim Argument.Leon Culbertson - 2017 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 11 (4):440-452.
    Stephen Mumford develops his view of sport spectatorship partly through a rejection of an argument he attributes to Best, which distinguishes between two categories of sports, the ‘purposive’ and the ‘aesthetic’, on the basis of the claim that they have different principal aims. This paper considers the principal aim argument and one feature of Mumford’s rejection of that argument, namely, Best’s observation that the distinctions to which he draws attention are based on logical differences. The paper argues that Mumford misconstrues (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Criteria, Defeasibility and Rules: Intention and the Principal Aim Argument.Leon Culbertson - 2018 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 12 (2):149-161.
    This paper builds on a previous discussion of Stephen Mumford’s rejection of what he takes to be David Best’s argument for a distinction between purposive and aesthetic sports. That discussion concluded that Mumford’s argument misses its target, but closed by introducing a possible alternative argument, not made by Mumford, that might be thought to have the potential to secure Mumford’s conclusion. This paper considers that alternative argument, namely, the thought that the ascription of psychological predicates conceived of in terms of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Of Values and Commercialisation: An Exploration of Esports’ Place within the Olympic Movement.Cem Abanazir - 2021 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 16 (4):397-412.
    Esports’ rise in popularity has led the Olympic Movement (OM) to consider esports as a possible addition to the Olympic programme. A positive stance on the part of the OM towards certain aspects of esports has become apparent in recent years. However, the OM has expressly stated that while it is values-based, the esports industry is commercially driven. This article aims to take a tenable step towards the conceptualisation of the relationship between esports and ‘values’. Moreover, it weighs esports’ potential (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation