Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. 2000 European Summer Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic. Logic Colloquium 2000.Carol Wood - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (1):82-163.
  • Structural Rules in Natural Deduction with Alternatives.Greg Restall - 2023 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 52 (2):109-143.
    Natural deduction with alternatives extends Gentzen–Prawitz-style natural deduction with a single structural addition: negatively signed assumptions, called alternatives. It is a mildly bilateralist, single-conclusion natural deduction proof system in which the connective rules are unmodi_ed from the usual Prawitz introduction and elimination rules — the extension is purely structural. This framework is general: it can be used for (1) classical logic, (2) relevant logic without distribution, (3) affine logic, and (4) linear logic, keeping the connective rules fixed, and varying purely (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A semantical proof of the strong normalization theorem for full propositional classical natural deduction.Karim Nour & Khelifa Saber - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (3):357-364.
    We give in this paper a short semantical proof of the strong normalization for full propositional classical natural deduction. This proof is an adaptation of reducibility candidates introduced by J.-Y. Girard and simplified to the classical case by M. Parigot.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A completeness result for the simply typed λμ-calculus.Karim Nour & Khelifa Saber - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (1):109-118.
    In this paper, we define a realizability semantics for the simply typed $lambdamu$-calculus. We show that if a term is typable, then it inhabits the interpretation of its type. This result serves to give characterizations of the computational behavior of some closed typed terms. We also prove a completeness result of our realizability semantics using a particular term model.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Strong normalization of classical natural deduction with disjunctions.Koji Nakazawa & Makoto Tatsuta - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 153 (1-3):21-37.
    This paper proves the strong normalization of classical natural deduction with disjunction and permutative conversions, by using CPS-translation and augmentations. Using them, this paper also proves the strong normalization of classical natural deduction with general elimination rules for implication and conjunction, and their permutative conversions. This paper also proves that natural deduction can be embedded into natural deduction with general elimination rules, strictly preserving proof normalization.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Non-strictly positive fixed points for classical natural deduction.Ralph Matthes - 2005 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 133 (1):205-230.
    Termination for classical natural deduction is difficult in the presence of commuting/permutative conversions for disjunction. An approach based on reducibility candidates is presented that uses non-strictly positive inductive definitions.It covers second-order universal quantification and also the extension of the logic with fixed points of non-strictly positive operators, which appears to be a new result.Finally, the relation to Parigot’s strictly positive inductive definition of his set of reducibility candidates and to his notion of generalized reducibility candidates is explained.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Call-by-name reduction and cut-elimination in classical logic.Kentaro Kikuchi - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 153 (1-3):38-65.
    We present a version of Herbelin’s image-calculus in the call-by-name setting to study the precise correspondence between normalization and cut-elimination in classical logic. Our translation of λμ-terms into a set of terms in the calculus does not involve any administrative redexes, in particular η-expansion on μ-abstraction. The isomorphism preserves β,μ-reduction, which is simulated by a local-step cut-elimination procedure in the typed case, where the reduction system strictly follows the “ cut=redex” paradigm. We show that the underlying untyped calculus is confluent (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The λ μ T -calculus.Herman Geuvers, Robbert Krebbers & James McKinna - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (6):676-701.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The λμT-calculus.Herman Geuvers, Robbert Krebbers & James McKinna - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (6):676-701.
    Calculi with control operators have been studied as extensions of simple type theory. Real programming languages contain datatypes, so to really understand control operators, one should also include these in the calculus. As a first step in that direction, we introduce λμTλμT, a combination of Parigotʼs λμ-calculus and Gödelʼs T, to extend a calculus with control operators with a datatype of natural numbers with a primitive recursor.We consider the problem of confluence on raw terms, and that of strong normalization for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Strong normalization results by translation.René David & Karim Nour - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (9):1171-1179.
    We prove the strong normalization of full classical natural deduction by using a translation into the simply typed λμ-calculus. We also extend Mendler’s result on recursive equations to this system.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hypothetical Logic of Proofs.Eduardo Bonelli & Gabriela Steren - 2014 - Logica Universalis 8 (1):103-140.
    The logic of proofs is a refinement of modal logic introduced by Artemov in 1995 in which the modality ◻A is revisited as ⟦t⟧A where t is an expression that bears witness to the validity of A. It enjoys arithmetical soundness and completeness and is capable of reflecting its own proofs . We develop the Hypothetical Logic of Proofs, a reformulation of LP based on judgemental reasoning.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Realizability Interpretation for Classical Arithmetic.Jeremy Avigad - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):439-440.
    Summary. A constructive realizablity interpretation for classical arithmetic is presented, enabling one to extract witnessing terms from proofs of 1 sentences. The interpretation is shown to coincide with modified realizability, under a novel translation of classical logic to intuitionistic logic, followed by the Friedman-Dragalin translation. On the other hand, a natural set of reductions for classical arithmetic is shown to be compatible with the normalization of the realizing term, implying that certain strategies for eliminating cuts and extracting a witness from (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Church–Rosser property of a simple reduction for full first-order classical natural deduction.Y. Andou - 2003 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 119 (1-3):225-237.
    A system of typed terms which corresponds with the classical natural deduction with one conclusion and full logical symbols is defined. Church–Rosser property of the system is proved using an extended method of parallel reduction.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • $lambdamu$-Calculus and Bohm's Theorem.Rene David & Walter Py - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (1):407-413.
    The $\lambda\mu$-calculus is an extension of the $\lambda$-calculus that has been introduced by M Parigot to give an algorithmic content to classical proofs. We show that Bohm's theorem fails in this calculus.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark