Switch to: References

Citations of:

The syntax of event structure

In Beth Levin & Steven Pinker (eds.), Lexical & Conceptual Semantics. Blackwell. pp. 47-81 (1992)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Perceiving, remembering, and communicating structure in events.Jeffrey M. Zacks, Barbara Tversky & Gowri Iyer - 2001 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 130 (1):29.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Direct causation in the linguistic coding and individuation of causal events.Phillip Wolff - 2003 - Cognition 88 (1):1-48.
  • Roles and their three facets: A foundational perspective.Fumiaki Toyoshima - 2021 - Applied ontology 16 (2):161-192.
    Roles remain nebulous entities, notwithstanding their extensive interdisciplinary research. This paper argues through a meta-ontological conceptual tool of grounding that there are three key facets of roles: a role position, a role specification, and a role potential. A foundational perspective on roles can be specified by “role choices” as to which facet of roles is primary. Role choices are illustrated with theories of roles that are built in compliance with four well-known upper ontologies: GFO, DOLCE, BFO, and UFO. The relationship (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Disagreements about Taste vs. Disagreements about Moral Issues.Isidora Stojanovic - 2019 - American Philosophical Quarterly 56 (1):29-42.
    The aim of this paper is to argue against a growing tendency to assimilate moral disagreements to disagreements about matters of personal taste. The argumentative strategy adopted in the paper appeals to a battery of linguistic criteria that reveal interesting and important differences between predicates of personal taste and moral predicates. The paper further argues that these semantically tractable differences have an impact on the nature of the corresponding disagreements.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Parts and boundaries.Jackendoff Ray - 1991 - Cognition 41 (1-3):9-45.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Lexical knowledge representation and natural language processing.James Pustejovsky & Branimir Boguraev - 1993 - Artificial Intelligence 63 (1-2):193-223.
  • Automatic generation of textual summaries from neonatal intensive care data.François Portet, Ehud Reiter, Albert Gatt, Jim Hunter, Somayajulu Sripada, Yvonne Freer & Cindy Sykes - 2009 - Artificial Intelligence 173 (7-8):789-816.
  • From Event Representation to Linguistic Meaning.Ercenur Ünal, Yue Ji & Anna Papafragou - 2021 - Topics in Cognitive Science 13 (1):224-242.
    A fundamental aspect of human cognition is the ability to parse our constantly unfolding experience into meaningful representations of dynamic events and to communicate about these events with others. How do we communicate about events we have experienced? Influential theories of language production assume that the formulation and articulation of a linguistic message is preceded by preverbal apprehension that captures core aspects of the event. Yet the nature of these preverbal event representations and the way they are mapped onto language (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Meaning through syntax: Language comprehension and the reduced relative clause construction.Gail McKoon & Roger Ratcliff - 2003 - Psychological Review 110 (3):490-525.
  • Reading time evidence for enriched composition.Brian McElree, Matthew J. Traxler, Martin J. Pickering, Rachel E. Seely & Ray Jackendoff - 2001 - Cognition 78 (1):B17-B25.
  • Not Half True.Poppy Mankowitz - 2023 - Mind 132 (525):84-112.
    The word ‘true’ shows some evidence of gradability. For instance, there are cases where truth-bearers are described as ‘slightly true’, ‘completely true’ or ‘very true’. Expressions that accept these types of modifiers are analysed in terms of properties that can be possessed to a greater or lesser degree. If ‘true’ is genuinely gradable, then it would follow that there are degrees of truth. It might also follow that ‘true’ is context-sensitive, like other gradable expressions. Such conclusions are difficult to reconcile (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The relationship between verb meaning and argument realization: What we learn from the processing of agent-implying intransitive verbs in Japanese.Zoe Pei-sui Luk - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13:928649.
    This study investigated whether some Japanese intransitive verbs, called agent-implying intransitive verbs, are processed differently from other ordinary intransitive verbs. These verbs are special in that they denote agentive events, but they are intransitive verbs, which only allow the patient/theme to be the only nominatively marked argument. The priming experiment was designed based on the situation model theory, assuming that verbs with an agentive semantic structure (e.g., ordinary transitive verbs) has a shorter causal inferential distance than those with a non-agentive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The lexical semantics of derived statives.Andrew Koontz-Garboden - 2010 - Linguistics and Philosophy 33 (4):285-324.
    This paper investigates the semantics of derived statives, deverbal adjectives that fail to entail there to have been a preceding (temporal) event of the kind named by the verb they are derived from, e.g. darkened in a darkened portion of skin. Building on Gawron’s (The lexical semantics of extent verbs, San Diego State University, ms, 2009) recent observations regarding the semantics of extent uses of change of state verbs (e.g., Kim’s skin darkens between the knee and the calf) and Kennedy (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Exploring the conceptual universe.Charles Kemp - 2012 - Psychological Review 119 (4):685-722.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Tacit and accessible understanding of language.Kent Johnson - 2007 - Synthese 156 (2):253 - 279.
    The empirical nature of our understanding of language is explored. I first show that there are several important and different distinctions between tacit and accessible awareness. I then present empirical evidence concerning our understanding of language. The data suggests that our awareness of sentence-meanings is sometimes merely tacit according to one of these distinctions, but is accessible according to another. I present and defend an interpretation of this mixed view. The present project is shown to impact on several diverse areas, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Is there an end in sight? Viewers' sensitivity to abstract event structure.Yue Ji & Anna Papafragou - 2020 - Cognition 197 (C):104197.
  • Parts and boundaries.Ray Jackendoff - 1992 - In Beth Levin & Steven Pinker (eds.), Lexical & Conceptual Semantics. Blackwell. pp. 9-45.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Affectedness and direct objects : The role of lexical semantics in the acquisition of verb argument structure.Jess Gropen - 1992 - In Beth Levin & Steven Pinker (eds.), Lexical & Conceptual Semantics. Blackwell. pp. 153-195.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Affectedness and direct objects: The role of lexical semantics in the acquisition of verb argument structure.Jess Gropen, Steven Pinker, Michelle Hollander & Richard Goldberg - 1991 - Cognition 41 (1-3):153-195.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Constructional sources of implicit agents in sentence comprehension.Micah B. Goldwater & Arthur B. Markman - 2006 - Cognitive Linguistics 20 (4).
  • Event Structure, Punctuality, and When.Sheila Glasbey - 2004 - Natural Language Semantics 12 (2):191-211.
    In this paper, I discuss observations on when given by Sandström (1993) for constructions of the form ‘When A B’, where A and B both describe events (as opposed to states). Sandströ m proposes that for events described in the simple past, the temporal interpretation of such sequences varies according to whether A describes a culminated process (CP)(accomplishment) or a culmination (CULM)(roughly, an achievement). She offers an account of this behaviour based on the claim that culminations denote changes of state (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Event segmentation: Cross-linguistic differences in verbal and non-verbal tasks.Johannes Gerwien & Christiane von Stutterheim - 2018 - Cognition 180 (C):225-237.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Processing correlates of lexical semantic complexity.Silvia Gennari & David Poeppel - 2003 - Cognition 89 (1):B27-B41.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Interlingual machine translation A parameterized approach.Bonnie J. Dorr - 1993 - Artificial Intelligence 63 (1-2):429-492.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A force-theoretic framework for event structure.Bridget Copley & Heidi Harley - 2015 - Linguistics and Philosophy 38 (2):103-158.
    We propose an account of dynamic predicates which draws on the notion of force, eliminating reference to events in the linguistic semantics. We treat dynamic predicates as predicates of forces, represented as functions from an initial situation to a final situation that occurs ceteris paribus, that is, if nothing external intervenes. The possibility that opposing forces might intervene to prevent the transition to a given final situation leads us to a novel analysis of non-culminating accomplishment predicates in a variety of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Event Semantics: A Husserlian Critique.Andrés Colapinto - 2018 - Husserl Studies 34 (2):123-143.
    Event semantics is concerned with the formal structure of sentences which appear to describe an event of some kind, e.g. ‘Brutus kills Caesar,’ or ‘My tooth fell out.’ Phenomenologists should be interested in work in this field, if they hope to rescue Husserl’s phenomenology of judgment from its narrow focus on copular judgments of the form ‘S is p.’ An adequate phenomenology of judgment must ultimately develop an account of judgments whose intentional correlates seem to be events, rather than states (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Oxford Handbook of Causal Reasoning.Michael Waldmann (ed.) - 2017 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    Causal reasoning is one of our most central cognitive competencies, enabling us to adapt to our world. Causal knowledge allows us to predict future events, or diagnose the causes of observed facts. We plan actions and solve problems using knowledge about cause-effect relations. Without our ability to discover and empirically test causal theories, we would not have made progress in various empirical sciences. In the past decades, the important role of causal knowledge has been discovered in many areas of cognitive (...)
  • Plurals, all, and the nonuniformity of collective predication.C. Brisson - 2003 - Linguistics and Philosophy 26 (2):129-184.
  • Cognitive, Cultural, and Linguistic Sources of a Handshape Distinction Expressing Agentivity.Diane Brentari, Alessio Di Renzo, Jonathan Keane & Virginia Volterra - 2015 - Topics in Cognitive Science 7 (1):95-123.
    In this paper the cognitive, cultural, and linguistic bases for a pattern of conventionalization of two types of iconic handshapes are described. Work on sign languages has shown that handling handshapes and object handshapes express an agentive/non-agentive semantic distinction in many sign languages. H-HSs are used in agentive event descriptions and O-HSs are used in non-agentive event descriptions. In this work, American Sign Language and Italian Sign Language productions are compared as well as the corresponding groups of gesturers in each (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Foundational ontologies in action.Stefano Borgo, Antony Galton & Oliver Kutz - 2022 - Applied ontology 17 (1):1-16.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • GUM: The generalized upper model.John A. Bateman - 2022 - Applied ontology 17 (1):107-141.
    GUM is a linguistically-motivated ontology originally developed to support natural language processing systems by offering a level of representation intermediate between linguistic forms and domain knowledge. Whereas modeling decisions for individual domains may need to be responsive to domain-specific criteria, a linguistically-motivated ontology offers a characterization that generalizes across domains because its design criteria are derived independently both of domain and of application. With respect to this mediating role, the use of GUM resembles the adoption of upper ontologies as tools (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Yale shooting problem.Tim Fernando - manuscript
    The Yale Shooting Problem introduced by Steve Hanks & Drew McDermott (1987) is a well-known test case of non-monotonic temporal reasoning. There is a sequence of situations. In the initial situation a gun is not loaded and the target is alive. In the next situation the gun is loaded. Eventually, a shot is fired, perhaps with fatal consequences. In this scenario there are two "fluents", alive and loaded, and two actions, load and shoot. Being loaded and being alive are inert (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Events and the semantic content of thematic relations.Barry Schein - 2002 - In Gerhard Preyer Georg Peter (ed.), Logical Form and Language. Oxford University Press. pp. 263--344.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Coercion in on-line semantic processing.Brian McElree, Matthew J. Traxler, Martin J. Pickering, Ray S. Jackendoff & Rachel E. Seely - 2001 - Cognition 78:B17 - B25.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Why giannis can't scrub his plate clean: On the absence of resultative secondary predication in greek.Anastasia Giannakidou - manuscript
    In this paper, we contrast English and Greek resultative secondary predication, showing that Greek lacks the productive syntactic strategy which English employs. We propose that the difference in productivity should be attributed to properties of the morphology in the two languages (namely, to the differing productivity of certain verbal affixes). Finally, we give a compositional semantics for the complex event formation in the morphology/syntax that accounts for the contrasts between resultatives in English and Greek.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark