Switch to: References

Citations of:

Constructive probability

Synthese 48 (1):1-60 (1981)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Expressivism, Normative Uncertainty, and Arguments for Probabilism.Julia Staffel - 2019 - Oxford Studies in Epistemology 6.
    I argue that in order to account for normative uncertainty, an expressivist theory of normative language and thought must accomplish two things: Firstly, it needs to find room in its framework for a gradable conative attitude, degrees of which can be interpreted as representing normative uncertainty. Secondly, it needs to defend appropriate rationality constraints pertaining to those graded attitudes. The first task – finding an appropriate graded attitude that can represent uncertainty – is not particularly problematic. I tackle the second (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On Uncertainty.Brian Weatherson - 1998 - Dissertation, Monash University
    This dissertation looks at a set of interconnected questions concerning the foundations of probability, and gives a series of interconnected answers. At its core is a piece of old-fashioned philosophical analysis, working out what probability is. Or equivalently, investigating the semantic question of what is the meaning of ‘probability’? Like Keynes and Carnap, I say that probability is degree of reasonable belief. This immediately raises an epistemological question, which degrees count as reasonable? To solve that in its full generality would (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Measures of uncertainty in expert systems.Peter Walley - 1996 - Artificial Intelligence 83 (1):1-58.
  • On the justification of Dempster's rule of combination.Frans Voorbraak - 1991 - Artificial Intelligence 48 (2):171-197.
  • Theory of the Apparatus and Theory of the Phenomena: The Case of Low Dose Electron Microscopy.Zeno G. Swijtink - 1990 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (1):573-584.
    Electron microscopy, and in particular low dose electron microscopy, offers interesting cases of experimental techniques where the theory of the phenomena studied and the theory of the apparatus used, are intertwined. A single primary exposure usually does not give an interpretable image, and computerized image enhancement techniques are used to create from multiple exposures a single, visually meaningful image. Some of the enhancement programs start from informed guesses at the structure of the specimen and use the primary exposures in a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Acting on belief functions.Nicholas J. J. Smith - 2023 - Theory and Decision 95 (4):575-621.
    The degrees of belief of rational agents should be guided by the evidence available to them. This paper takes as a starting point the view—argued elsewhere—that the formal model best able to capture this idea is one that represents degrees of belief using Dempster–Shafer belief functions. However degrees of belief should not only respect evidence: they also guide decision and action. Whatever formal model of degrees of belief we adopt, we need a decision theory that works with it: that takes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Languages and Designs for Probability Judgment.Glenn Shafer & Amos Tversky - 1985 - Cognitive Science 9 (3):309-339.
    Theories of subjective probability are viewed as formal languages for analyzing evidence and expressing degrees of belief. This article focuses on two probability langauges, the Bayesian language and the language of belief functions (Shafer, 1976). We describe and compare the semantics (i.e., the meaning of the scale) and the syntax (i.e., the formal calculus) of these languages. We also investigate some of the designs for probability judgment afforded by the two languages.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Jeffrey's rule of conditioning.Glenn Shafer - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (3):337-362.
    Richard Jeffrey's generalization of Bayes' rule of conditioning follows, within the theory of belief functions, from Dempster's rule of combination and the rule of minimal extension. Both Jeffrey's rule and the theory of belief functions can and should be construed constructively, rather than normatively or descriptively. The theory of belief functions gives a more thorough analysis of how beliefs might be constructed than Jeffrey's rule does. The inadequacy of Bayesian conditioning is much more general than Jeffrey's examples of uncertain perception (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • A theory of probability should tutor our intuitions.Glenn Shafer - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):508.
  • Human inference: The notion of reasonable rationality.Russell Revlin - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):507.
  • Foundations of the theory of evidence: Resolving conflict among schemata.Bonnie K. Ray & David H. Krantz - 1996 - Theory and Decision 40 (3):215-234.
  • On typicality and vagueness.Daniel Osherson & Edward E. Smith - 1997 - Cognition 64 (2):189-206.
  • Extracting the coherent core of human probability judgement: a research program for cognitive psychology.Daniel Osherson, Eldar Shafir & Edward E. Smith - 1994 - Cognition 50 (1-3):299-313.
  • Can philosophy resolve empirical issues?Clifford R. Mynatt, Ryan D. Tweney & Michael E. Doherty - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):506.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The infinite epistemic regress problem has no unique solution.Ronald Meester & Timber Kerkvliet - 2019 - Synthese 198 (6):4973-4983.
    In this article we analyze the claim that a probabilistic interpretation of the infinite epistemic regress problem leads to a unique solution, the so called “completion” of the regress. This claim is implicitly based on the assumption that the standard Kolmogorov axioms of probability theory are suitable for describing epistemic probability. This assumption, however, has been challenged in the literature, by various authors. One of the alternatives that have been suggested to replace the Kolmogorov axioms in case of an epistemic (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Who commits the base rate fallacy?Isaac Levi - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):502.
  • Quantum physical symbol systems.Kathryn Blackmond Laskey - 2006 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 15 (1-2):109-154.
    Because intelligent agents employ physically embodied cognitive systems to reason about the world, their cognitive abilities are constrained by the laws of physics. Scientists have used digital computers to develop and validate theories of physically embodied cognition. Computational theories of intelligence have advanced our understanding of the nature of intelligence and have yielded practically useful systems exhibiting some degree of intelligence. However, the view of cognition as algorithms running on digital computers rests on implicit assumptions about the physical world that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Towards a Rough Mereology-Based Logic for Approximate Solution Synthesis. Part 1.Jan Komorowski, Lech Polkowski & Andrzej Skowron - 1997 - Studia Logica 58 (1):143-184.
    We are concerned with formal models of reasoning under uncertainty. Many approaches to this problem are known in the literature e.g. Dempster-Shafer theory [29], [42], bayesian-based reasoning [21], [29], belief networks [29], many-valued logics and fuzzy logics [6], non-monotonic logics [29], neural network logics [14]. We propose rough mereology developed by the last two authors [22-25] as a foundation for approximate reasoning about complex objects. Our notion of a complex object includes, among others, proofs understood as schemes constructed in order (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a rough mereology-based logic for approximate solution synthesis. Part.Jan Komorowski, Lech T. Polkowski & Andrzej Skowron - 1997 - Studia Logica 58 (1):143-184.
    We are concerned with formal models of reasoning under uncertainty. Many approaches to this problem are known in the literature e.g. Dempster-Shafer theory [29], [42], bayesian-based reasoning [21], [29], belief networks [29], many-valued logics and fuzzy logics [6], non-monotonic logics [29], neural network logics [14]. We propose rough mereology developed by the last two authors [22-25] as a foundation for approximate reasoning about complex objects. Our notion of a complex object includes, among others, proofs understood as schemes constructed in order (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Norms, competence, and the explanation of reasoning.Gary S. Kahn & Lance J. Rips - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):501.
  • Can irrationality be intelligently discussed?Daniel Kahneman & Amos Tversky - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):509.
  • Inductive reasoning: Competence or skill?Christopher Jepson, David H. Krantz & Richard E. Nisbett - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):494.
  • Probability, logic, and probability logic.Alan Hójek - 2001 - In Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 362--384.
    ‘Probability logic’ might seem like an oxymoron. Logic traditionally concerns matters immutable, necessary and certain, while probability concerns the uncertain, the random, the capricious. Yet our subject has a distinguished pedigree. Ramsey begins his classic “Truth and Probability” with the words: “In this essay the Theory of Probability is taken as a branch of logic. … “speaks of “the logic of the probable.” And more recently, regards probabilities as estimates of truth values, and thus probability theory as a natural outgrowth (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Epistemic Risk in Representation.Stephanie Harvard & Eric Winsberg - 2022 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 32 (1):1-31.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Two views of belief: belief as generalized probability and belief as evidence.Joseph Y. Halpern & Ronald Fagin - 1992 - Artificial Intelligence 54 (3):275-317.
  • A mathematical theory of evidence for G.L.S. Shackle.Guido Fioretti - 2001 - Mind and Society 2 (1):77-98.
    Evidence Theory is a branch of mathematics that concerns combination of empirical evidence in an individual’s mind in order to construct a coherent picture of reality. Designed to deal with unexpected empirical evidence suggesting new possibilities, evidence theory is compatible with Shackle’s idea of decision-making as a creative act. This essay investigates this connection in detail, pointing to the usefulness of evidence theory to formalise and extend Shackle’s decision theory. In order to ease a proper framing of the issues involved, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The punctuated equilibrium of scientific change: a Bayesian network model.Patrick Grim, Frank Seidl, Calum McNamara, Isabell N. Astor & Caroline Diaso - 2022 - Synthese 200 (4):1-25.
    Our scientific theories, like our cognitive structures in general, consist of propositions linked by evidential, explanatory, probabilistic, and logical connections. Those theoretical webs ‘impinge on the world at their edges,’ subject to a continuing barrage of incoming evidence. Our credences in the various elements of those structures change in response to that continuing barrage of evidence, as do the perceived connections between them. Here we model scientific theories as Bayesian nets, with credences at nodes and conditional links between them modelled (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intuition and inconsistency.Richard E. Grandy - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):494.
  • Expert intuitions and the interpretation of social psychological experiments.André Gallois & Michael Siegal - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):492.
  • Violations of probability theory: What do they mean?Deborah E. Frisch - 1988 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 18 (2):137–148.
  • A philosophical basis for decision aiding.Anthony N. S. Freeling - 1984 - Theory and Decision 16 (2):179-206.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is irrationality systematic?Robyn M. Dawes - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):491.
  • The plasticity of human rationality.Norman Daniels & George E. Smith - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):490.
  • A logico-geometric comparison of coherence for non-additive uncertainty measures.Esther Anna Corsi, Tommaso Flaminio & Hykel Hosni - forthcoming - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The controversy about irrationality.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):510.
  • The epistemological status of lay intuition.Christopher Cherniak - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):489.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From Classical to Intuitionistic Probability.Brian Weatherson - 2003 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 44 (2):111-123.
    We generalize the Kolmogorov axioms for probability calculus to obtain conditions defining, for any given logic, a class of probability functions relative to that logic, coinciding with the standard probability functions in the special case of classical logic but allowing consideration of other classes of "essentially Kolmogorovian" probability functions relative to other logics. We take a broad view of the Bayesian approach as dictating inter alia that from the perspective of a given logic, rational degrees of belief are those representable (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Discrepancies between human behavior and formal theories of rationality: The incompleteness of Bayesian probability logic.Lea Brilmayer - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):488.
  • Probability functions, belief functions and infinite regresses.David Atkinson & Jeanne Peijnenburg - 2020 - Synthese 199 (1-2):3045-3059.
    In a recent paper Ronald Meester and Timber Kerkvliet argue by example that infinite epistemic regresses have different solutions depending on whether they are analyzed with probability functions or with belief functions. Meester and Kerkvliet give two examples, each of which aims to show that an analysis based on belief functions yields a different numerical outcome for the agent’s degree of rational belief than one based on probability functions. In the present paper we however show that the outcomes are the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The rationality of the scientist: Toward reconciliation.Jonathan E. Adler - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):487.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark