Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Preface and Afterword to the Special Section : New Horizon of Meta-theories for Psychology and Human Sciences.Tsuneo Watanabe - 2013 - Journal of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 40 (2):85-86.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Relation of sensory scales to physical scales.Richard M. Warren - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):586-587.
  • Keeping the bath water along with the baby: Context effects represent a challenge, not a mortal wound, to the body of psychophysics.Mark Wagner - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):585-586.
  • Operationalism and realism in psychometrics.Elina Vessonen - 2019 - Philosophy Compass 14 (10):e12624.
    Psychometrics is one of the main approaches to social scientific measurement. It is relied upon in drug testing, economic policymaking, recruitment, and other decision-making contexts. The first aim of this article is to introduce philosophers to key aspects of psychometrics, namely, classical test theory, item response theory, and construct validity. The second aim is to show how a debate on the nature of psychological attributes manifests in psychometrics. In this debate, realists claim that psychometric measures are indicators of independently existing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ceteris paribus laws.J. van Brakel - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):584-585.
  • Do we scale “objects” or isolated sensory dimensions?Michel Treisman - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):581-584.
  • Maps of desire: Edward Tolman's drive theory of wants.Simon Torracinta - 2023 - History of the Human Sciences 36 (1):3-30.
    Wants and desires are central to ordinary experience and to aesthetic, philosophical, and theological thought. Yet despite a burgeoning interest in the history of emotions research, their history as objects of scientific study has received little attention. This historiographical neglect mirrors a real one, with the retreat of introspection in the positivist human sciences of the early 20th century culminating in the relative marginalization of questions of psychic interiority. This article therefore seeks to explain an apparent paradox: the attempt to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Logic of Measurement: A Defense of Foundationalist Empiricism.Mariam Thalos - forthcoming - Episteme:1-26.
    Practitioners of science treat evidence as a separate and objective body of materials that is independent of, and possibly also prior to, all of theorizing. Philosophers of science, by contrast, are increasingly wary of the role of theory in testing and measurement contexts, and hence have problematized the notion of evidence as prior or independent, even in the context of measurement. This paper argues that there is an important sense in which empirical certification of a quantity, via measurement, is indeed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Selecting one attribute for judgment is not an act of stupidity.Robert Teghtsoonian - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):580-581.
  • Should the psychophysical model be rejected?Bruce Schneider - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):579-580.
  • Schools of psychology: A complementary pattern.Saul Rosenzweig - 1937 - Philosophy of Science 4 (1):96-106.
    “If, then, we are really to find out what is true and what is false, we must direct our attention to the role of any particular item in the whole of which it is a part.”—Wertheimer: On Truth.In these days of Gestalttheorie it seems not untimely to inquire whether psychology itself does not stand in need of being recognized as a configuration of complementary parts. The suggestion, it is true, tends at the first to be repudiated by the implacability of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Operating with Names: Operational Definitions in the Analects and Beyond.Dawid Rogacz - 2022 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 21 (1):19-35.
    The philosophy of Confucius has often been accused of lacking classical definitions of its core concepts. However, as I shall argue, Confucius systematically used nonclassical definitions—to be precise, operational ones. The notion of operational definition comes from Percy Bridgman’s The Logic of Modern Physics and means that the definiendum is defined by a set of operations that results in determining the meaning of the term in question. In the case of Confucian argumentation, operational definitions are mostly nominal and, in contrast (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Context effects in the entropic theory of perception.Kenneth H. Norwich - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):578-579.
  • The evident object of inquiry.Keith K. Niall - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):578-578.
  • Anthropomorphism in the Context of Scientific Discovery: Implications for Comparative Cognition.Farshad Nemati - 2023 - Foundations of Science 28 (3):927-945.
    Mentalist view began to lose its standing among psychologists mainly during the first half of the twentieth century. As a result, the enthusiasm to build an objective science began to grow among behaviourists and ethologists. The rise of cognitive sciences around the 1960s, however, revived the debates over the importance of cognitive intervening variables in explaining behaviours that could not be explained by clinging solely to a pure behavioural approach. Nevertheless, even though cognitive functions in nonhuman animals have been identified (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Epistemology According to Rand and Hayek.Robert F. Mulligan - 2023 - Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 23 (1-2):123-153.
    Ayn Rand’s Objectivist epistemology is the foundation of an impressive, comprehensive, and integrated system of political philosophy, psychology, art, and literature. Friedrich Hayek’s operational system of epistemology and his analysis of the psychology of perception (presented primarily in The Sensory Order) is not as clearly integrated with his economics and political philosophy—and many have debated their consistency with one another. This paper engages in a comparative analysis of Rand’s and Hayek’s epistemology.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Attributes or objects: A paradigm shift in psychophysics.John S. Monahan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):577-577.
  • How important are dimensions to perception?Robert D. Melara - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):576-577.
  • Psychophysics and quantitative perceptual laws.Sergio C. Masin - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):575-576.
  • The perplexing plurality of psychophysical processes.Lawrence E. Marks - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):574-575.
  • Some Recent Conceptions of Operationalism and Operationalizing.Paul Marshall - 1979 - Philosophia Reformata 44:46.
  • Covert converging operations for multidimensional psychophysics.Neil A. Macmillan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):573-574.
  • Psychophysical scaling: Judgments of attributes or objects?Gregory R. Lockhead - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):543-558.
    Psychophysical scaling models of the form R = f, with R the response and I some intensity of an attribute, all assume that people judge the amounts of an attribute. With simple biases excepted, most also assume that judgments are independent of space, time, and features of the situation other than the one being judged. Many data support these ideas: Magnitude estimations of brightness increase with luminance. Nevertheless, I argue that the general model is wrong. The stabilized retinal image literature (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Constancy in a changing world.Gregory R. Lockhead - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):587-600.
  • Two categories of contextual variable in perception.Donald Laming - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):572-573.
  • Will the real stimulus please step forward?Lester E. Krueger - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):570-572.
  • Context effects: Pervasiveness and analysis.Donald L. King - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):570-570.
  • Psychophysics: Plus ça change ….Peter R. Killeen - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):569-569.
  • Hubris to humility: Tonal volume and the fundamentality of psychophysical quantities.Alistair M. C. Isaac - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 65:99-111.
    Psychophysics measures the attributes of perceptual experience. The question of whether some of these attributes should be interpreted as more fundamental, or “real,” than others has been answered differently throughout its history. The operationism of Stevens and Boring answers “no,” reacting to the perceived vacuity of earlier debates about fundamentality. The subsequent rise of multidimensional scaling (MDS) implicitly answers “yes” in its insistence that psychophysical data be represented in spaces of low dimensionality. I argue the return of fundamentality follows from (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • S. S. Stevens and the origins of operationism.Gary L. Hardcastle - 1995 - Philosophy of Science 62 (3):404-424.
    Despite influencing the social sciences since the 1930s, S. S. Stevens' "operationist" philosophy of science has yet to be adequately understood. I reconstruct Stevens' operationism from his early work and assess the influence of various views (logical positivism, behaviorism and the "operational viewpoint" of P. W. Bridgman, among others) on Stevens. Stevens' operationism emerges, on my reconstruction, as a naturalistic methodological directive aimed at agreement, founded in turn on the belief that agreement is constitutive of science, the scientific community, and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Operationism analysed operationally.Hornell Hart - 1940 - Philosophy of Science 7 (3):288-313.
    Stevens has presented a “lusty embryonic” Science of Science, as having arisen out of “operationism as a revolution against absolute and undefinable concepts in physics, behaviorism as a revolution against dualistic mentalism in psychology, and Logical Positivism as a revolution against rational metaphysics in philosophy.”.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Walking in a psychophysical dustbowl creates a dustcloud.Robert A. M. Gregson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):568-569.
  • Scales falling from the eyes?Richard L. Gregory - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):567-568.
  • The complexity and importance of the psychophysical scaling of sensory attributes.George A. Gescheider - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):567-567.
  • Gestalt psychology, frontloading phenomenology, and psychophysics.Uljana Feest - 2019 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 9):2153-2173.
    In his 1935 book Principles of Gestalt Psychology, Kurt Koffka stated that empirical research in perceptual psychology should begin with “a phenomenological analysis,” which in turn would put constraints on the “true theory.” In this paper, I take this statement as a point of departure to investigate in what sense Gestalt psychologists practiced a phenomenological analysis and how they saw it related to theory construction. I will contextualize the perceptual research in Gestalt psychology vis-a-vis Husserlian phenomenology on the one hand (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Psychophysical invariance, perceptual invariance and the physicalistic trap.Hannes Eisler - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):566-567.
  • Can brightness be related to luminance by a meaningful function?Ehtibar N. Dzhafarov - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):565-566.
  • The determinants of perceived brightness are complicated, but not hopelessly so.Thomas R. Corwin - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):564-565.
  • Psychophysical scaling: Context and illusion.Stanley Coren - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):563-564.
  • The myth of Hempel and the DSM-III.Rachel Cooper & Roger Blashfield - 2018 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 70:10-19.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Accounting for an old inconsistency in the psychophysics of Plateau and Delboeuf.Marc Brysbaert - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):562-563.
  • Phenomenology, Psychoanalysis, and Behaviorism: [E≡=S]v[E≢S]?Lewis W. Brandt - 1970 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 1 (1):7-18.
  • Psychophysical scaling: To describe relations or to uncover a law?Gunnar Borg - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):561-562.
  • Psychophysical scaling within an information processing approach?Claude Bonnet - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):560-561.
  • Lockhead's view of scaling: Something's fishy here.Stanley J. Bolanowski - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):560-560.
  • Integration psychophysics is not traditional psychophysics.Norman H. Anderson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):559-560.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Perception, apperception and psychophysics.Daniel Algom - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):558-559.
  • Measurement in Science.Eran Tal - 2015 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • What Is Defined in Operational Definitions? The Case of Operant Psychology.Emilio Ribes-Iñesta - 2003 - Behavior and Philosophy 31:111 - 126.
    With S.S. Stevens, operationism became an important influence in psychology. In this paper I discuss the differences between Bridgman's and Stevens' proposals on operationism and the role that operational definitions play in scientific theory. I discuss how Stevens' notions of the basic act of discrimination and of the relation procedure–outcome influenced B.F. Skinner's criteria under which the main conceptual distinctions in operant psychology were formulated. The operational origin of the dichotomies between respondent and operant behavior, contingency-shaped and rulegoverned behavior, private (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark