Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Synchronization and cognitive carpentry: From systematic structuring to simple reasoning. E. Koerner - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):465-466.
  • Philosophy, Drama and Literature.Rick Benitez - 2011 - In Graham Robert Oppy, Nick Trakakis, Lynda Burns, Steven Gardner & Fiona Leigh (eds.), A companion to philosophy in Australia & New Zealand. Clayton, Victoria, Australia: Monash University Publishing. pp. 371-372.
    Philosophy and Literature is an internationally renowned refereed journal founded by Denis Dutton at the University of Canterbury, Christchurch. It is now published by the Johns Hopkins University Press. Since its inception in 1976, Philosophy and Literature has been concerned with the relation between literary and philosophical studies, publishing articles on the philosophical interpretation of literature as well as the literary treatment of philosophy. Philosophy and Literature has sometimes been regarded as iconoclastic, in the sense that it repudiates academic pretensions, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creativity.Peter Langland-Hassan - 2020 - In Explaining Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 262-296.
    Comparatively easy questions we might ask about creativity are distinguished from the hard question of explaining transformative creativity. Many have focused on the easy questions, offering no reason to think that the imagining relied upon in creative cognition cannot be reduced to more basic folk psychological states. The relevance of associative thought processes to songwriting is then explored as a means for understanding the nature of transformative creativity. Productive artificial neural networks—known as generative antagonistic networks (GANs)—are a recent example of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • There are no i-beliefs or i-desires at work in fiction consumption and this is why.Peter Langland-Hassan - 2020 - In Explaining Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 210-233.
    Currie’s (2010) argument that “i-desires” must be posited to explain our responses to fiction is critically discussed. It is argued that beliefs and desires featuring ‘in the fiction’ operators—and not sui generis imaginings (or "i-beliefs" or "i-desires")—are the crucial states involved in generating fiction-directed affect. A defense of the “Operator Claim” is mounted, according to which ‘in the fiction’ operators would be also be required within fiction-directed sui generis imaginings (or "i-beliefs" and "i-desires"), were there such. Once we appreciate that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Explaining Imagination.Peter Langland-Hassan - 2020 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    ​Imagination will remain a mystery—we will not be able to explain imagination—until we can break it into parts we already understand. Explaining Imagination is a guidebook for doing just that, where the parts are other ordinary mental states like beliefs, desires, judgments, and decisions. In different combinations and contexts, these states constitute cases of imagining. This reductive approach to imagination is at direct odds with the current orthodoxy, according to which imagination is a sui generis mental state or process—one with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Functional distinctions within the medical temporal lobe memory system: What is the evidence?Stuart Zola-Morgan & Pablo Alvarez - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):495-496.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Smell's puzzling discrepancy: Gifted discrimination, yet pitiful identification.Benjamin D. Young - 2019 - Mind and Language 35 (1):90-114.
  • Ethereal oscillations.Malcolm P. Young - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):476-477.
  • Hippocampal neuronal activity in rat and primate: Memory and movement.Frasar A. W. Wilson - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):499-500.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Turing's Analysis of Computation and Theories of Cognitive Architecture.A. J. Wells - 1998 - Cognitive Science 22 (3):269-294.
    Turing's analysis of computation is a fundamental part of the background of cognitive science. In this paper it is argued that a re‐interpretation of Turing's work is required to underpin theorizing about cognitive architecture. It is claimed that the symbol systems view of the mind, which is the conventional way of understanding how Turing's work impacts on cognitive science, is deeply flawed. There is an alternative interpretation that is more faithful to Turing's original insights, avoids the criticisms made of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Directions in Connectionist Research: Tractable Computations Without Syntactically Structured Representations.Jonathan Waskan & William Bechtel - 1997 - Metaphilosophy 28 (1‐2):31-62.
    Figure 1: A pr ototyp ical exa mple of a three-layer feed forward network, used by Plunkett and M archm an (1 991 ) to simulate learning the past-tense of En glish verbs. The inpu t units encode representations of the three phonemes of the present tense of the artificial words used in this simulation. Th e netwo rk is trained to produce a representation of the phonemes employed in the past tense form and the suffix (/d/, /ed/, or /t/) (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A parallel approach to syntax for generation.Nigel Ward - 1992 - Artificial Intelligence 57 (2-3):183-225.
  • The systematicity challenge to anti-representational dynamicism.Víctor M. Verdejo - 2015 - Synthese 192 (3):701-722.
    After more than twenty years of representational debate in the cognitive sciences, anti-representational dynamicism may be seen as offering a rival and radically new kind of explanation of systematicity phenomena. In this paper, I argue that, on the contrary, anti-representational dynamicism must face a version of the old systematicity challenge: either it does not explain systematicity, or else, it is just an implementation of representational theories. To show this, I present a purely behavioral and representation-free account of systematicity. I then (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science.Tim van Gelder - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (5):615-28.
    According to the dominant computational approach in cognitive science, cognitive agents are digital computers; according to the alternative approach, they are dynamical systems. This target article attempts to articulate and support the dynamical hypothesis. The dynamical hypothesis has two major components: the nature hypothesis (cognitive agents are dynamical systems) and the knowledge hypothesis (cognitive agents can be understood dynamically). A wide range of objections to this hypothesis can be rebutted. The conclusion is that cognitive systems may well be dynamical systems, (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   207 citations  
  • What do animal models of memory model?Endel Tulving & Hans J. Markowitsch - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):498-499.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Dynamic-binding theory is not plausible without chaotic oscillation.Ichiro Tsuda - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):475-476.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reconstructing Physical Symbol Systems.David S. Touretzky & Dean A. Pomerleau - 1994 - Cognitive Science 18 (2):345-353.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Should first-order logic be neurally plausible?David S. Touretzky & Scott E. Fahlman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):474-475.
  • Temporal synchrony and the speed of visual processing.Simon J. Thorpe - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):473-474.
  • What can neuroanatomy tell us about the functional components of the hippocampal memory system?Wendy A. Suzuki - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):496-498.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phase logic is biologically relevant logic.Gary W. Strong - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):472-473.
  • What are the best strategies for understanding hippocampal function?Paul R. Solomon & Bo-Yi Yang - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):494-495.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Do simple associations lead to systematic reasoning?Steven Sloman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):471-472.
  • From simple associations to systematic reasoning: A connectionist representation of rules, variables, and dynamic binding using temporal synchrony.Lokendra Shastri & Venkat Ajjanagadde - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):417-51.
    Human agents draw a variety of inferences effortlessly, spontaneously, and with remarkable efficiency – as though these inferences were a reflexive response of their cognitive apparatus. Furthermore, these inferences are drawn with reference to a large body of background knowledge. This remarkable human ability seems paradoxical given the complexity of reasoning reported by researchers in artificial intelligence. It also poses a challenge for cognitive science and computational neuroscience: How can a system of simple and slow neuronlike elements represent a large (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • From Heisenberg's cat to Eichenbaum's rat: Uncertainty in predicting the neural requirements for animal behavior.Matthew L. Shapiro - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):493-494.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A step toward modeling reflexive reasoning.Lokendra Shastri & Venkat Ajjanagadde - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):477-494.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Linguistic Subversion of Mental Representation.Whit Schonbein - 2012 - Minds and Machines 22 (3):235-262.
    Embedded and embodied approaches to cognition urge that (1) complicated internal representations may be avoided by letting features of the environment drive behavior, and (2) environmental structures can play an enabling role in cognition, allowing prior cognitive processes to solve novel tasks. Such approaches are thus in a natural position to oppose the ‘thesis of linguistic structuring’: The claim that the ability to use language results in a wholesale recapitulation of linguistic structure in onboard mental representation. Prominent examples of researchers (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the relationship between naturalistic semantics and individuation criteria for terms in a language of thought.Robert D. Rupert - 1998 - Synthese 117 (1):95-131.
    Naturalistically minded philosophers hope to identify a privileged nonsemantic relation that holds between a mental representation m and that which m represents, a relation whose privileged status underwrites the assignment of reference to m. The naturalist can accomplish this task only if she has in hand a nonsemantic criterion for individuating mental representations: it would be question-begging for the naturalist to characterize m, for the purpose of assigning content, as 'the representation with such and such content'. If we individuate mental (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Arguing about representation.Mark Rowlands - 2017 - Synthese 194 (11):4215-4232.
    The question of whether cognition requires representations has engendered heated discussion during the last two decades. I shall argue that the question is, in all likelihood, a spurious one. There may or may not be a fact of the matter concerning whether a given item qualifies as a representation. However, even if there is, attempts to establish whether cognition requires representation have neither practical nor theoretical utility.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Useful ideas for exploiting time to engineer representations.Richard Rohwer - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):471-471.
  • Does it still make sense to develop a declarative memory theory of hippocampal function?J. N. P. Rawlins, R. M. J. Deacon, B. K. Yee & H. J. Cassaday - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):492-493.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Functional components of the hippocampal memory system: Implications for future learning and memory research in nonhuman primates.Peter R. Rapp - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):491-492.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Computational Origin of Representation.Steven T. Piantadosi - 2020 - Minds and Machines 31 (1):1-58.
    Each of our theories of mental representation provides some insight into how the mind works. However, these insights often seem incompatible, as the debates between symbolic, dynamical, emergentist, sub-symbolic, and grounded approaches to cognition attest. Mental representations—whatever they are—must share many features with each of our theories of representation, and yet there are few hypotheses about how a synthesis could be possible. Here, I develop a theory of the underpinnings of symbolic cognition that shows how sub-symbolic dynamics may give rise (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Darwin's mistake: Explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds.Derek C. Penn, Keith J. Holyoak & Daniel J. Povinelli - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (2):109-130.
    Over the last quarter century, the dominant tendency in comparative cognitive psychology has been to emphasize the similarities between human and nonhuman minds and to downplay the differences as (Darwin 1871). In the present target article, we argue that Darwin was mistaken: the profound biological continuity between human and nonhuman animals masks an equally profound discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. To wit, there is a significant discontinuity in the degree to which human and nonhuman animals are able to approximate (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   227 citations  
  • On the difficulty of really considering a radical novelty.Derek Partridge - 1995 - Minds and Machines 5 (3):391-410.
    The fundamental assumptions in Dijkstra''s influential article on computing science teaching are challenged. Dijkstra''s paper presents the radical novelties of computing, and the consequent problems that we must tackle through a formal, logic-based approach to program derivation. Dijkstra''s main premise is that the algorithmic programming paradigm is the only one, in fact, the only possible one. It is argued that there is at least one other, the network-programming paradigm, which itself is a radical novelty with respect to the implementation of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Making reasoning more reasonable: Event-coherence and assemblies.Günther Palm - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):470-470.
  • A connectionist theory of phenomenal experience.Jonathan Opie & Gerard O'Brien - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (1):127-148.
    When cognitive scientists apply computational theory to the problem of phenomenal consciousness, as many of them have been doing recently, there are two fundamentally distinct approaches available. Either consciousness is to be explained in terms of the nature of the representational vehicles the brain deploys; or it is to be explained in terms of the computational processes defined over these vehicles. We call versions of these two approaches _vehicle_ and _process_ theories of consciousness, respectively. However, while there may be space (...)
    Direct download (16 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • A Defense of Cartesian Materialism.Jonathan Opie - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (4):939-963.
    One of the principal tasks Dennett sets himself in Consciousness Explained is to demolish the Cartesian theater model of phenomenal consciousness, which in its contemporary garb takes the form of Cartesian materialism: the idea that conscious experience is a process of presentation realized in the physical materials of the brain. The now standard response to Dennett is that, in focusing on Cartesian materialism, he attacks an impossibly naive account of consciousness held by no one currently working in cognitive science or (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Psychological implications of the synchronicity hypothesis.Stellan Ohlsson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):469-469.
  • Computational and biological constraints in the psychology of reasoning.Mike Oaksford & Mike Malloch - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):468-469.
  • On being systematically connectionist.Lars F. Niklasson & Tim van Gelder - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (3):288-30.
    In 1988 Fodor and Pylyshyn issued a challenge to the newly-popular connectionism: explain the systematicity of cognition without merely implementing a so-called classical architecture. Since that time quite a number of connectionist models have been put forward, either by their designers or by others, as in some measure demonstrating that the challenge can be met (e.g., Pollack, 1988, 1990; Smolensky, 1990; Chalmers, 1990; Niklasson and Sharkey, 1992; Brousse, 1993). Unfortu- nately, it has generally been unclear whether these models actually do (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • A Puzzle concerning Compositionality in Machines.Ryan M. Nefdt - 2020 - Minds and Machines 30 (1):47-75.
    This paper attempts to describe and address a specific puzzle related to compositionality in artificial networks such as Deep Neural Networks and machine learning in general. The puzzle identified here touches on a larger debate in Artificial Intelligence related to epistemic opacity but specifically focuses on computational applications of human level linguistic abilities or properties and a special difficulty with relation to these. Thus, the resulting issue is both general and unique. A partial solution is suggested.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Hippocampus, space, and relations.Lynn Nadel - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):490-491.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Relational but not spatial memory: The task at hand.Elisabeth A. Murray - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):489-490.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What we know and the LTKB.Stanley Munsat - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):466-467.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neocortical memory traces.Earl K. Miller - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):488-489.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The hippocampus: Relational processor or antiprocessor?Neil McNaughton - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):487-488.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The connectionism/classicism battle to win souls.Brian P. McLaughlin - 1993 - Philosophical Studies 71 (2):163-190.
  • Connectionist modelling of word recognition.Peter McLeod, David C. Plaut & Tim Shallice - 2001 - Synthese 129 (2):173 - 183.
    Connectionist models offer concretemechanisms for cognitive processes. When these modelsmimic the performance of human subjects theycan offer insights into the computationswhich might underlie human cognition. We illustratethis with the performance of a recurrentconnectionist network which produces the meaningof words in response to their spellingpattern. It mimics a paradoxical pattern oferrors produced by people trying to read degradedwords. The reason why the network produces thesurprising error pattern lies in the nature ofthe attractors which it develops as it learns tomap spelling patterns (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionist Modelling of Word Recognition.Peter Mcleod, David Plaut & Tim Shallice - 2001 - Synthese 129 (2):173-183.
    Connectionist models offer concretemechanisms for cognitive processes. When these modelsmimic the performance of human subjects theycan offer insights into the computationswhich might underlie human cognition. We illustratethis with the performance of a recurrentconnectionist network which produces the meaningof words in response to their spellingpattern. It mimics a paradoxical pattern oferrors produced by people trying to read degradedwords. The reason why the network produces thesurprising error pattern lies in the nature ofthe attractors which it develops as it learns tomap spelling patterns (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark