Switch to: References

Citations of:

(1994)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Ksenologia i ksenotopografia Bernharda Waldenfelsa wobec podstawowych założeń światotwórczych literatury fantastycznej (Orson Scott Card, Neil Gaiman, George R. R. Martin).Krzysztof M. Maj - 2014 - Hybris, Revista de Filosofí­A (27):072-095.
    XENOLOGY AND XENOTOPOGRAPHY OF BERNHARD WALDENFELS The paper strives to adapt Bernhard Waldenfels’ xenology and so called ‘xenotopography’ for the philosophico-literary studies in fantastic world-building with a special concern of the ‘portal-quest’ model of fantasy and SF. Following Waldenfel’s remarks on the nature of post- Husserlian diastasis of our world [Heimwelt] and otherworld [Fremdwelt] and acknowledging the consequences of allocating one’s attitude towards the otherness in the symbolical borderland [‘sphere of intermonde’] in between, it is examined whether such a model (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction. The School: Its Genesis, Development and Significance.U. Wybraniec-Skardowska - 2018 - In Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska & Ángel Garrido (eds.), The Lvov-Warsaw School. Past and Present. Cham, Switzerland: Springer- Birkhauser,. pp. 3-14.
    The Introduction outlines, in a concise way, the history of the Lvov-Warsaw School – a most unique Polish school of worldwide renown, which pioneered trends combining philosophy, logic, mathematics and language. The author accepts that the beginnings of the School fall on the year 1895, when its founder Kazimierz Twardowski, a disciple of Franz Brentano, came to Lvov on his mission to organize a scientific circle. Soon, among the characteristic features of the School was its serious approach towards philosophical studies (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Етика и истина у доба кризе.Nenad Cekić (ed.) - 2021 - Belgrade: University of Belgrade - Faculty of Philosophy.
  • Dysjunktywizm i natura percepcyjnej relacji.Paweł Zięba - 2016 - Analiza I Egzystencja 35:87-111.
    This paper surveys selected (though arguably representative) versions of metaphysical and epistemological disjunctivism. Although they share a common logical structure, it is hard to find a further common denominator among them. Two main conclusions are: (1) a specific standpoint on the nature of perceptual relation is not such a common denominator, which means that it is very unlikely that all of these views could be refuted with a single objection; (2) contrary to what its name suggests, disjunctivism can be correctly (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Something, nothing and Leibniz’s question. negation in logic and metaphysics.Jan Woleński - 2018 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 54 (1):175-190.
    This paper discusses the concept of nothing (nothingness) from the point of logic and ontology (metaphysics). It is argued that the category of nothing as a denial of being is subjected to various interpretations. In particular, this thesis concerns the concept of negation as used in metaphysics. Since the Leibniz question ‘Why is there something rather than nothing?’ and the principle of sufficient reason is frequently connected with the status of nothing, their analysis is important for the problem in question. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle and Tarski.Jan Woleński - 2017 - Peitho 8 (1):261-270.
    Alfred Tarski frequently declared that his semantic definition of truth was inspired by Aristotle’s views. The present paper discusses this issue in the context of Marian Wesoły’s criticism of the thesis that there is an affinity between Tarski’s views and those of Aristotle. The article concludes with an inquiry into whether Aristotle’s definition of truthfulness can be identified with the correspondence theory of truth.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An abstract approach to bivalence.Jan Woleński - 2014 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 23 (1):3-14.
    This paper outlines an approach to the principle of bivalence based on very general, but still elementary, semantic considerations. The principle of bivalence states that “every sentence is either true or false”. Clearly, some logics are bivalent while others are not. A more general formulation of uses the concept of designated and non-designated logical values and is captured by “every sentence is either designated or non-designated”. Yet this formulation seems trivial, because the concept of non-designated value is negative. In order (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The logical challenge of negative theology.Piotr Urbańczyk - 2018 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 54 (1):149-174.
    In this paper I present four interpretations of so-called negative theology and provide a number of attempts to model this theory within a formal system. Unfortunately, all of them fail in some manner. Most of them are simply inconsistent, some contradict the usual religious praxis and discourse, and some do not correspond to the key theses of negative theology. I believe that this paper shows how challenging this theory is from a logical perspective.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Logical and Metaphysical Assumptions of Bernard Bolzano’s Theodicy.Dariusz Łukasiewicz - 2007 - Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 12 (1):33-56.
    Bolzano's theodicy is a very good example of Platonism in the philosophy of religion. Above all, Bolzano believes that there obtains an ideal realm of truths in themselves and mathematical objects, which are independent of God. Therefore, we are allowed to conclude that God is only a contractor; true, more powerful than Plato's demiurge because He created substances and sustains them in existence, but God must follow a project which is independent of Him. Since the world is determined, by the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Analogy and diagonal argument.Zbigniew Tworak - 2006 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 15 (1):39-66.
    In this paper, I try to accomplish two goals. The first is to provide a general characterization of a method of proofs called — in mathematics — the diagonal argument. The second is to establish that analogical thinking plays an important role also in mathematical creativity. Namely, mathematical research make use of analogies regarding general strategies of proof. Some of mathematicians, for example George Polya, argued that deductions is impotent without analogy. What I want to show is that there exists (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A estrutura do noema e a dupla concepção do objeto intencional em Husserl.Carlos Cortes Tourinho - 2013 - Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 58 (3):482-498.
    O presente artigo aborda a especificidade do vivido intencional e a sua relação com as sensações não intencionais. Em seguida, examina a relação entre a noese e o noema, além de analisar a estrutura completa do noema. Mostra que o objeto intencional oscila entre o caráter imanente do noema e o que transcende o próprio noema. Ele traz como conclusão, então, que a análise da estrutura completa do noema evidencia uma dupla concepção do objeto intencional na subjetividade transcendental.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Grounding Reichenbach’s Pragmatic Vindication of Induction.Michael J. Shaffer - 2017 - Polish Journal of Philosophy 11 (1):43-55.
    This paper has three interdependent aims. The first is to make Reichenbach’s views on induction and probabilities clearer, especially as they pertain to his pragmatic justification of induction. The second aim is to show how his view of pragmatic justification arises out of his commitment to extensional empiricism and moots the possibility of a non-pragmatic justification of induction. Finally, and most importantly, a formal decision-theoretic account of Reichenbach’s pragmatic justification is offered in terms both of the minimax principle and the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A lattice for the language of Aristotle's syllogistic and a lattice for the language of Vasiľév's syllogistic.Andrew Schumann - 2006 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 15 (1):17-37.
    In this paper an algebraic system of the new type is proposed (namely, a vectorial lattice). This algebraic system is a lattice for the language of Aristotle’s syllogistic and as well as a lattice for the language of Vasiľév’s syllogistic. A lattice for the language of Aristotle’s syllogistic is called a vectorial lattice on cap-semilattice and a lattice for the language of Vasiľév’s syllogistic is called a vectorial lattice on closure cap-semilattice. These constructions are introduced for the first time.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the Polish Roots of the Analytic Philosophy of Religion.Roger Pouivet - 2011 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 3 (1):1 - 20.
    Philosophers of religion of the Cracow Circle (1934-1944) are the principal precursors of what is now called the analytic philosophy of religion. The widespread claim that the analytic philosophy of religion was from the beginning an Anglo-American affair is an ill-informed one. It is demonstrable that the enterprise, although not the label "analytic philosophy of religion," appeared in Poland in the 1930’s. Józef Bochenski’s postwar work is a development of the Cracow Circle’s prewar work in the analytic philosophy of religion, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Paraconsistent logics, conventionalism and ontology.Anna Pietryga - 1999 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 7:119.
    Paraconsistent logics may be viewed as one of the last elementsin a series of rapid developments in science in the 19th and early 20th c.,triggered by the appearance of non-Euclidean geometries. The philosophyof conventionalism, which gave a metatheoretical framework to the basicchanges involved, may also help in evaluating the truth import of logic and in determining its relation to ontology.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Truth vs. provability – philosophical and historical remarks.Roman Murawski - 2002 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 10:93.
  • Would Leibniz have shared von Neumann's logical physicalism?Witold Marciszewski - 1995 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 3:115-128.
    This paper represents such an amateur approach; hence any comments backed up by professional erudition will be highly appreciated. Let me start from an attempt to sketch a relationship between professionals’ and amateurs’ contributions. The latter may be compared with the letters to the Editor of a journal, written by perceptive readers, while professionals contribute to the very content of the journal in question. Owing to such letters, the Editor and his professional staff can become more aware of the responses (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Ajdukiewicz's and Quine's Views on Ontology.Artur Kosecki - 2019 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 33 (2):49-66.
    The aim of the paper is to analyze the views of Willard van Orman Quine and compare them with the views of Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz, an eminent philosopher from the Lvov-Warsaw School. I will argue that Ajdukiewicz's approach to ontology is deationary and, in that respect, similar to Quine's. In my analysis of these two ontological stances, I would like to refer to Price's deationist interpretation of Quine's views in order to highlight the similarity between Ajdukiewicz's views and Quine's stance on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz’s Views on Ontology.Artur Kosecki - 2020 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 34 (3):99-116.
    This article will address the views of Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz - the leading representative of the Lvov-Warsaw School. I will present arguments proving that the Polish philosopher could have anticipated contemporary metaontological discussions. -/- In the first part, I will provide a profile of Ajdukiewicz as a representative of the Lvov-Warsaw School. I will outline the assumptions of his metaepistemological projects: radical conventionalism and semantic epistemology. In the second part, I will argue that the former project resulted in views on existence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logical Culture as a Common Ground for the Lvov-Warsaw School and the Informal Logic Initiative.Ralph H. Johnson & Marcin Koszowy - 2018 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 55 (1):187-229.
    In this paper, we will explore two initiatives that focus on the importance of employing logical theories in educating people how to think and reason properly, one in Poland: The Lvov-Warsaw School; the other in North America: The Informal Logic Initiative. These two movements differ in the logical means and skills that they focus on. However, we believe that they share a common purpose: to educate students in logic and reasoning (logical education conceived as a process) so that they may (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The interactive nature of computing: Refuting the strong church–turing thesis. [REVIEW]Dina Goldin & Peter Wegner - 2008 - Minds and Machines 18 (1):17-38.
    The classical view of computing positions computation as a closed-box transformation of inputs (rational numbers or finite strings) to outputs. According to the interactive view of computing, computation is an ongoing interactive process rather than a function-based transformation of an input to an output. Specifically, communication with the outside world happens during the computation, not before or after it. This approach radically changes our understanding of what is computation and how it is modeled. The acceptance of interaction as a new (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • ‘‘Quine’s Evolution from ‘Carnap’s Disciple’ to the Author of “Two Dogmas.Greg Frost-Arnold - 2011 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 1 (2):291-316.
    Recent scholarship indicates that Quine’s “Truth by Convention” does not present the radical critiques of analytic truth found fifteen years later in “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.” This prompts a historical question: what caused Quine’s radicalization? I argue that two crucial components of Quine’s development can be traced to the academic year 1940–1941, when he, Russell, Carnap, Tarski, Hempel, and Goodman were all at Harvard together. First, during those meetings, Quine recognizes that Carnap has abandoned the extensional, syntactic approach to philosophical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Formy agnostycyzmu XVII i XVIII wieku — od Pascala do Kanta.Zbigniew Drozdowicz - 2018 - Rocznik Filozoficzny Ignatianum 23 (2):132-150.
    W rozważaniach tych podejmuję próby pokazania, że w myśli filozoficznej XVII i XVIII stulecia pojawiły się zarówno takie formy agnostycyzmu, które określały swoją ideową tożsamość poprzez odwoływanie się do wiary religijnej, jak i takie, które określały ją poprzez opozycję do niej. Spotykały się one i niejednokrotnie spotykają do dzisiaj z surową oceną zarówno ze strony niektórych Kościołów, jak i zdeklarowanych ateistów. Warto się nieco uważniej przyjrzeć argumentacji zwolenników tych form agnostycyzmu. Być może pozwoli to uniknąć przynajmniej niektórych nieporozumień związanych z (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How Many Concepts of Intentionality?Andrzej Dąbrowski - 2015 - Studia Humana 4 (3):3-13.
    The current discussion of the intentionality nature has become more sophisticated and complex. In this paper I will delineate a number of approaches to intentionality in contemporary philosophy: 1 mentalistic; 2 semantic / linguistic; 3 pragmatic; 4 somatic; 5 and naturalistic. Although philosophers identify and analyse many concepts of intentionality, from the author point of view, there is only one intentionality: mentalistic intentionality. Furthermore, there are the pre-intentionality in the physical world and the meta-intentionality in the world of culture.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Philosophical-Logical Views of Ludwik Borkowski.Bożena Czernecka-Rej - 2018 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 66 (2):149-171.
    Ludwik Borkowski’s vast knowledge of philosophy allowed him to put his logical studies in a philosophical context. As a logician, he continued the tradition of the Lvov-Warsaw school. He dealt with the basic issues of the widely understood logic as well as with those having strong philosophical implications (e.g. non-classical logics, the theory of truth, natural deduction, the theory of consequence). He also worked on the theory of definition and the intuitive interpretation of logical results. For Borkowski, logic was an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • SAD computers and two versions of the Church–Turing thesis.Tim Button - 2009 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (4):765-792.
    Recent work on hypercomputation has raised new objections against the Church–Turing Thesis. In this paper, I focus on the challenge posed by a particular kind of hypercomputer, namely, SAD computers. I first consider deterministic and probabilistic barriers to the physical possibility of SAD computation. These suggest several ways to defend a Physical version of the Church–Turing Thesis. I then argue against Hogarth's analogy between non-Turing computability and non-Euclidean geometry, showing that it is a non-sequitur. I conclude that the Effective version (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Routledge Handbook of Franz Brentano and the Brentano School.Uriah Kriegel (ed.) - 2017 - London and New York: Routledge.
    Both through his own work and that of his students, Franz Clemens Brentano had an often underappreciated influence on the course of 20 th - and 21 st -century philosophy. _The Routledge Handbook of Franz Brentano and the Brentano School_ offers full coverage of Brentano’s philosophy and his influence. It contains 38 brand-new essays from an international team of experts that offer a comprehensive view of Brentano’s central research areas—philosophy of mind, metaphysics, and value theory—as well as of the principal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • O etyce niezależnej Tadeusza Kotarbińskiego.Przemysław Spryszak - 2016 - Argument: Biannual Philosophical Journal 6 (2):429-454.
    In this paper I briefly discuss principles of “independent ethics” formulated and popularized by the Polish philosopher Tadeusz Kotarbiński. I focus on the notion of “conscience” which seems to play a fundamental role in this moral theory.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Jan WOLEŃSKI, Wierzę w to, co potrafię zrozumieć. [REVIEW]Rec Joanna Pierzga - 2014 - Argument: Biannual Philosophical Journal 4 (2):459-464.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The man who defined truth and the lvov crisis.Miroslava Trajkovski - 2021 - In Nenad Cekić (ed.), Етика и истина у доба кризе. Belgrade: University of Belgrade - Faculty of Philosophy. pp. 97-110.
    In the period after the First World War when the various national-ideological “truths” that led to it were not well resolved which resulted in the Second World War, one of the greatest world crises occurs. In those turbulent times, one philosopher renounces his national identity (changes his religion and name), wanting not to save himself from an evil world that is emerging but to join the creation of a completely new world – the world of modern logic. This man is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Confrontation of Reism with Type- theoretical Approach and Everyday Experience.Witold Marciszewski - 2012 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 27 (40).
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tadeusz Czeżowski’s method of analytical description – historical and systematic study.Maciej Zinkiewicz - 2016 - Philosophical Problems in Science 61:53-103.
    The paper depicts the evolution of the conception of the method of analytical description of Czeżowski, one of the most important figures of the Lvov-Warsaw School of Philosophy. It portrays Czeżowski as an author, whose voice on relation between theory and experience, as well as language and empirical reality, can be still considered important and significant. Generally speaking, Czeżowski distinguishes between two kinds of methods: the inductive ones and the no inductive, i.e. the method of analytic description. The results of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Descartes' "Radical" Rationalism? On the History of the Theory of Science.Stanisław Rev Janeczek - 2010 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 20 (33).
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ani racjonalizacja światopoglądu, ani rezygnacja z mądrości. Czy metafilozofia Kazimierza Twardowskiego może być wyznacznikiem rzetelnie uprawianej filozofii klasycznej? / / Can Kazimierz Twardowski's metaphilosophy be the determinant of reliable practiced classical philosophy? 2018.Marek Pepliński - 2018 - Filo-Sofija 18 (40/1):41-78.
    The article aims to determine whether it is possible to build the reliably practiced classical philosophy, understood as a metaphysical research, directed towards the nature of objective reality. The purpose of this kind of philosophizing is knowledge and truth. Moreover, the practice of such philosophizing and its results should meet some of the characteristics of science. The paper establishes a set of conditions that have been imposed on the science of metaphysics by Kazimierz Twardowski. Among the conditions of such philosophizing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adam Olech, Semantyczna teoria poznania. [REVIEW]Grzegorz Trela - 2017 - Argument: Biannual Philosophical Journal 7 (2):393-399.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Chaos a nieobliczalność.Andrzej Wilk - 2014 - Filozofia i Nauka 2:323-338.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wiedza niepojęciowa a Kazimierza Twardowskiego postulat jasności stylu filozoficznego.Ignacy Szczeniowski - 2014 - Filozofia i Nauka 2:199-218.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Correspondentia: A Neologism by Aquinas Attains its Zenith in Swedenborg.James F. Lawrence - 2017 - Correspondences: Journal for the Study of Esotericism 5:41-63.
    This article performs a word history on correspondentia, a neo-Latin construction by Thomas Aquinas in Scholastic thought attempting to interpret Aristotle on the perception of truth, and then tracks succeeding circles of the neologism’s utility. The new term “correspondentia” performs a crucial role in shaping correspondence theory in early modern hermetic thought and again in modern neo-Cartesian thought. A thread of shared discourse demonstrates an ­interconnected journey for the neologism from Aquinas through these contiguous ­conversations all the way to Swedenborg’s (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • O naturze filozoficznego zabobonu – według Innocentego Józefa M. Bocheńskiego.Jan F. Jacko - 2013 - Filo-Sofija 13 (21):135-150.
    This text analyzes the concept of philosophical superstition according to Joseph Maria Bocheński. It specifies sufficient conditions for beliefs and statements to be a philosophical superstition. Philosophical superstitions consist in specific contradictions in beliefs or statements: (a) Superstitions assume or contain contradictory beliefs or statements or/and (b) they are inconsistent with direct experiences or (c) beliefs of their followers, or/and (d) without sufficient reasons superstitions contradict what has already been sufficiently justified or/and (e) they contradict semantic rules of reference of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ukraińcy w Szkole Lwowsko-Warszawskiej.Stepan Ivanyk - 2012 - Diametros 32:232-235.
    Tematyka niniejszego referatu wpisuje się w badania nad jedną z najważniejszych formacji filozoficznych w XX wieku – Szkołą Lwowsko-Warszawską. W pracy dokonano analizy fenomenu Szkoły Twardowskiego z perspektywy dotychczas przez badaczy tego zagadnienia nie branej pod uwagę – a mianowicie uwzględniającej wielokulturowy charakter Lwowa, jako kolebki Szkoły. Uzasadnienie głównej hipotezy komunikatu, polegającej na stwierdzeniu przynależności szeregu czołowych przedstawicieli ukraińskiej myśli filozoficznej w przedwojennej Galicji do tradycji tzw. filozoficznej Szkoły Lwowskiej, wypełnia istotną lukę w badaniach nad Szkołą Lwowsko-Warszawską i rozszerza perspektywę (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • "Ważność" a naturalizm. Antypsychologizm Wilhelma Windelbanda.Tomasz Kubalica - 2007 - Idea Studia nad strukturą i rozwojem pojęć filozoficznych 19.
  • Logika, wszechmoc, Bóg.Ryszard Kleszcz - 2012 - Filo-Sofija 12 (19).
    Traditional theism (in Christianity, Judaism and Islam) understands God as possessing certain attributes including omnipotence. God is omnipotent in the sense that God possesses unlimited (maximal) power. For some classical philosophers and theologians (PetrusDamiani, René Descartes) God’s omnipotence requires his being able to do absolutely anything, including the logically impossible. But in Thomas Aquinas’ opinion, to do what is logically impossible is not an act of power but is self-contradictory action. For Aquinas, a logically impossible action is not an action. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Louis Joly as a Platonist Painter?Roger Pouivet - 2006 - In Johan van Benthem, Gerhard Heinzman, M. Rebushi & H. Visser (eds.), The Age of Alternative Logics. Springer. pp. 337--341.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Koncepcja pomiaru według Kazimierza Ajdukiewicza.O. F. M. Olejnik - 1993 - Zagadnienia Filozoficzne W Nauce 15.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark